Journal of Indian Philosophy

ISSNs: 0022-1791, 1573-0395

28 found

View year:

  1.  3
    Divine Favour and Human Gratitude: A Study of Vedānta Deśikaṉ’s Upakārasaṅgraham.Suganya Anandakichenin - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (5):639-674.
    Among the many works that Vedānta Deśikaṉ—(traditional dates: 1268-1369), a most eminent theologian of all times—composed in his lifetime, his minor works—thirty in number and collectively known as the _Cillaṟai rahasyam_ (‘miscellaneous esoterica’)—stand out like guides meant to help those eager Śrīvaiṣṇavas who lack time to deepen their knowledge of Viśiṣṭādvaita by the study of longer and deeper texts. One such _rahasyam_ is the _Upakārasaṅgraham_, in which Deśikaṉ deals (almost exhaustively) with the theme of God’s countless acts of _upakāra_ (‘aid, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  4
    ‘I Don’t Know’: An Epistemic Analysis of First-Personal Ignorance.Shruti Krishna Bhat - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (5):701-721.
    Ignorance becomes a philosophical issue when it is first-personal, i.e., _x_’s awareness about _x_’s own ignorance. It raises exciting and apparently paradoxical questions about cognition. Keeping first-personal experience of ignorance at the centre, some Indian philosophical schools discuss extensively the nature of ignorance. Vyāsatīrtha from the Dualist school (Dvaita Vedānta), along with the Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika school propound that ignorance belongs to a negative category (_abhāvapadārtha_) or in other words, that it must be understood as an absence of some cognition. The Non-dualist (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  16
    Nyāya-Cārvāka Debate on Inference and the Problem of Induction.Arka Pratim Mukhoty - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (5):675-700.
    Inductive inference faces the problem of induction, while Nyāya inference confronts Cārvāka objections. It has been generally agreed that the problem of induction is essentially similar to the Cārvāka objections against the validity of Nyāya inference. In this article, I will endeavor to refute this claim. The objections Cārvāka raised against inference, I shall argue, do not construe the problem of induction. I will analyze Udayana and Mādhavācārya's works on Cārvāka objections against inference to support my claim. Following Udayanācārya, I (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  1
    The Proof of Bindu as the Source of Determinate Knowledge. Ratnatrayaparīkṣā 45–70ab with a Critical Edition of an Unpublished Anonymous Commentary. [REVIEW]Akane Saito & Francesco Sferra - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (5):579-637.
    The paper covers a topic that sits between theology and philosophy of language and is based on completely unpublished material. The bulk of the paper consists in the critical edition and annotated translation of a section of an unpublished and anonymous commentary on the _Ratnatrayaparīkṣā_ by Śrīkaṇṭha. This section describes the transition of the indeterminate knowledge to the determined one according to the early Śaiva Siddhānta perspective. The introduction contains parts that are more “philological” or “historical” and others that are (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  3
    Correction: From Anekānta-vāda to Sarva-tantra-sva-tantra: Pluralism About Views and Philosophical Systems.Dimitry Shevchenko - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (5):723-724.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  4
    Dialogues About Death in Milindapañha and Carakasaṃhitā.Yukio Yamanaka & Tsutomu Yamashita - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (5):559-578.
    This paper deals with the debates over _kālamṛtyu_ (“timely death” or human death at the end of the life span) and _akālamṛtyu_ (“untimely death” or premature death that occurs when the life span still remains). In cultural areas like ancient India, where the _karman_ doctrine or the law of _karman_ is firmly rooted, such “timely death” and “untimely death” have seemed to be the catalysts for the philosophical and ethical debates. Assuming that a person’s life itself would be affected by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  22
    Relational Realism and Practical Reason in Utpaladeva’s Sambandhasiddhi.Jesse A. Berger - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (4):329-355.
    One debate that occupied Pratyabhijñā philosophers and their Buddhist interlocutors was the question of the reality of _sambandha_, or relation. A central treatise on the topic is Utpaladeva’s (∼10th c.) _Sambandhasiddhi_ [SS] (‘_Proof of Relation_’), a response to Dharmakīrti’s (∼7th c.) _Sambandhaparīkṣā_ [SP] (‘_Analysis of Relation_’). As the contrasting titles suggest, Dharmakīrti held that relations are merely conceptual constructions (_kalpanā_), inferred _post hoc_ from discrete perceptual cognitions (_pratyakṣa_)—and thus ultimately _unreal_. Utpaladeva, on the other hand, attempted to ‘prove’ (_siddhi_) the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  7
    Correction: Relational Realism and Practical Reason in Utpaladeva’s Sambandhasiddhi.Jesse A. Berger - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (4):357-357.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  13
    The Grammatical Philosophy on Vijñāna and Vijñapti in Yogācāra.Yan Cao - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (4):245-262.
    The traditional Buddhist Sanskrit term _vijñāna_ cannot be given the meaning “consciousness” in accordance with the grammatical rules of Pāṇini’s _Aṣṭādhyāyī_. In Vedic texts the traditional Sanskrit terms _citta_ and _manas_ refer to the eternal cognitive entities, which were also popular in some Indian Prakrit languages at the time of Buddha. It seems possible that Buddha himself created the new Prakrit term to denote the impermanent cognitive apparatus, which is produced by object and sensory organ. The sound of the Prakrit (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  5
    On Hearing a Yogi’s Talk: Āgamapramāṇa, Language, and Mind in the Pātañjalayoga.Rocco Cestola - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (4):423-463.
    The current study aims to clarify the meaning, the epistemic construction, and the pragmatics of the term _āgama_ occurring in _Pātañjalayogaśāstra_ I.7 and its commentaries. Since _āgama_ is a linguistic construction, this paper is also a contribution to the inquiry into the philosophy of language of the _Pātañjalayogaśāstra_. The inclusion of linguistic-philosophical arguments corroborates the Pātañjalayoga system of philosophy as a _śāstra_ text and its logical and epistemological paradigm. The structure of the present work is as follows: a first part (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  11
    The (Bitter) Nectar of the Knowledge of Reality: Madhyamakahṛdayakārikā 3.129cd-136 and Tarkajvālā on the Unconditioned Entities (asaṃskṛta).Krishna Del Toso - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (4):279-327.
    This article provides an annotated English translation and edition of the Sanskrit and Tibetan texts of Bhāviveka’s (490/500-570) _Madhyamakahṛdayakārikā_ 3.129cd-136 and of the Tibetan text of the _Tarkajvālā_ thereon, which focus on the discussion of unconditioned entities (_asaṃskṛta_). The study is accompanied by an introduction that outlines the general themes of the third chapter, the specific topics within the examined section and various problematic aspects found in the _Tarkajvālā_ exposition of Buddhist (Vaibhāṣika, Yogācāra) and non-Buddhist (Vaiśeṣika, Jain) doctrines and philosophies. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  5
    The (Bitter) Nectar of the Knowledge of Reality: Madhyamakahṛdayakārikā 3.129cd-136 and Tarkajvālā on the Unconditioned Entities (asaṃskṛta).Krishna Del Toso - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (4):279-327.
    This article provides an annotated English translation and edition of the Sanskrit and Tibetan texts of Bhāviveka’s (490/500-570) _Madhyamakahṛdayakārikā_ 3.129cd-136 and of the Tibetan text of the _Tarkajvālā_ thereon, which focus on the discussion of unconditioned entities (_asaṃskṛta_). The study is accompanied by an introduction that outlines the general themes of the third chapter, the specific topics within the examined section and various problematic aspects found in the _Tarkajvālā_ exposition of Buddhist (Vaibhāṣika, Yogācāra) and non-Buddhist (Vaiśeṣika, Jain) doctrines and philosophies. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  1
    Ethical Causality and Rebirth in the Pātañjalayogaśāstra and Abhidharmakośabhāṣya: A Mirrored Argument.Karen O’Brien-Kop - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (4):505-529.
    This paper focuses on Sāṃkhya-Yoga and Buddhist Abhidharma ontologies and their engagement. A close reading of two hitherto uncompared passages from _Pātañjalayogaśāstra_ 2.13 and Vasubandhu’s _Abhidharmakośabhāṣya_ 4.94 suggests that they are intertextual or interdiscursive. A mirrored argument form in the texts explains ethical causality (karma) in relation to rebirth (_punarjanman_). The arguments in both texts are similar in form, sequence, and even conclusion, although not in terms of the doctrinal basis of reasoning. On first examination, both arguments analyse how action (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  3
    Should a Yogi Be Healthy? Health Concepts in Early Haṭhayoga Texts.Hagar Shalev - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (4):485-504.
    Haṭhayoga texts, influential in the development of modern posture-based yoga, offer a conceptual framework intertwining physical cultivation, health, and soteriological aims. This article explores two interconnected inquiries regarding early Haṭhayoga texts: How do they conceptualize health, and how do they perceive the relationship between health and soteriology? These investigations illuminate the place of health in early yoga texts within Hindu traditions prior to its global recognition. This article reveals that early _haṭha_ texts present a holistic approach to health, highlighting the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  5
    Māyājāla-sūtra: A Canonical Proto-Yogācāra Sūtra?Gleb Sharygin - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (4):359-401.
    In our study of the development of Buddhist ideas over time, one of the major problems is the absence of the links, connecting different strata, strands or schools of the Buddhist thought. Perhaps, the most extreme example of this is the origin of the Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda tradition, a complex teaching that emerged almost “full-grown” in the _Saṃdhinirmocana-sūtra_. Our knowledge of the historical antecedents of Yogācāra is very scarce and, what concerns the school Sautrāntika/Dārṣṭāntika, contradictory. The _Māyājāla-sūtra_ very likely reveals important details (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  13
    From Anekānta-vāda to Sarva-tantra-sva-tantra: Pluralism About Views and Philosophical Systems.Dimitry Shevchenko - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (4):403-422.
    This article discusses the unique practice of many philosophers in classical India to write on several philosophical and religious systems, each time adopting a sympathetic point of view for a different tradition. The article describes the development of this phenomenon in the context of interreligious debates between Buddhists, Jains, and Brahmins in the course of three distinct historical periods, transitioning from pluralism about views to pluralism about philosophical systems and culminating in the ideal of _sarva-tantra-sva-tantra_, a polyvocal philosopher and a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  7
    On the Notion of anabhihite in the Cāndra Grammar.Chōjun Yazaki - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (4):263-278.
    Comparing the _kāraka_ theory as presented in Pāṇiniʼs (_ca_. fifth-fourth century BC) and Candragominʼs (_ca_. fifth century AD) systems of grammar, Joshi and Roodbergen observed that in the _Cāndrasūtra_, the heading rule Pāṇ 2.3.1 (_anabhihite_), which plays an important role for all the _kāraka_ rules, is missing. Deshpande, however, criticized their understanding. According to him, Patañjali (_ca_. second century BC), in his _Mahābhāṣya_, already dealt with the question of whether the general principle _uktārthānām aprayogaḥ_ can justify the omission of this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  27
    A Buddhist Critique of Desire: The Notion of Kāma in Aśvaghoṣa’s Saundarananda.Nir Feinberg - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (3):143-160.
    The critical analysis of desire is a staple of classical Buddhist thought; however, modern scholarship has focused primarily on doctrinal and scholastic texts that explain the Buddhist understanding of desire. As a result, the contribution of _kāvya_ (poetry) to the classical Buddhist philosophy of desire has not received much scholarly attention. To address this dearth, I explore in this article the notion of _kāma_ (desire or love) in Aśvaghoṣa’s epic poem, the _Saundarananda_ (_Beautiful Nanda_). I begin by framing the poem’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  16
    On Validity of Causal Statements.Nirmalya Guha - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (3):181-199.
    The Old Nyāya believes that a cause has a causal power of some kind, and it is possible to have valid cognition of a causal event. But Nāgārjuna (2nd century) challenged the very idea of causality. Also, he attacked the concept of epistemic instruments (_pramāṇa_). Śrīharṣa (12th century) too found counterexamples to the Nyāya definition of valid cognition. These attacks raised fundamental questions about the Naiyāyika’s take on the validity of causal statements. In 14 th century, Gaṅgeśa defended the Nyāya (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  12
    Theseus’ Ship: A Possible Response from an Indian Realist.Nirmalya Guha & Bhaskaranand Jha - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (3):201-217.
    This article will critically examine the Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika theory of substance (_dravya_). The Buddhists are reductionists, who believe that there is no substance over and above its attributes (_guṇa_) or parts (_avayava_). Thus, a pot is a set of a certain shape, size, color, texture, etc. But the Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika philosopher thinks that a pot is a substance that houses all of its attributes and actions (_karman_). It holds all these together. Also, it binds its parts. Although the Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika school defines a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  37
    Is Reflection Real According to Abhinavagupta? Dynamic Realism Versus Naïve Realism.Mrinal Kaul - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (3):115-142.
    This essay is one more attempt of understanding the non-dual philosophical position of Abhinavagupta viz-a-viz the problem of reflection. Since when my first essay on ‘Abhinavagupta on Reflection’ appeared in JIP, I have once again focused on the non-dual Śaiva theory of reflection (_pratibimbavāda_) (3.1-65) as discussed by Abhinavagupta (_fl.c._ 975-1025 CE) in the _Tantrāloka_ and his commentator Jayaratha (_fl.c._ 1225-1275 CE). The present attempt is to understand their philosophical position in the context of Nyāya realism where a reflection is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  13
    Not Even Absent: Dependent Origination, Emptiness, and the Two Truths in the Thought of Nāgārjuna.Jackson Cole Macor - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (3):161-179.
    As one of the most pivotal thinkers in the history Mahāyāna Buddhism, the writings of Nāgārjuna have long attracted the attention of scholars aiming to interpret in declarative terms the meaning of the arguments contained therein. However, the very aim of such an endeavor that seeks to ascribe to Nāgārjuna a philosophical position is fundamentally at odds with the unwaveringly critical nature of his project. In order to illustrate the singular character of Nāgārjuna’s methodology, this article seeks to clarify three (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  17
    ‘Play’ of Meanings: Avivakṣitavācyadhvani, Vivakṣitavācyadhvani and Différance: Concordance or Conflict?Ashima Shrawan - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (3):101-114.
    The paper attempts to answer a very obstinate fundamental problem—is literary meaning determinable at all? Would it be determinable if it were constructed by the language of the text? Or is this meaning open-ended, constantly deferred or shifted as a result of the very nature of signification? In this paper, I argue that the levels of _dhvani-ṣ Avivakṣitavācya dhvani _ and_ Vivakṣitavācya dhvani_ and their sub-levels are far more comprehensive than the concept of ‘_differance_’, both based on the play of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  13
    ‘Not a Name Given by Mother’: The Buddha’s Epithet Bhagavat.Paolo Visigalli - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (3):219-243.
    This paper explores how Indic and Indic-derived linguistic analyses of the Buddha’s epithet _bhagavat_ influenced the epithet’s interpretations and translations in the Sanskrit, Pali, Chinese, and Tibetan traditions. The paper consists of three parts. The first part examines and classifies the evidence into four types of analyses that ultimately reflect analytical models afforded by the Indic linguistic disciplines of grammar (_vyākaraṇa_) and etymology (_nirvacana_). The second part explores how these linguistic analyses coordinate with pronouncements emphasizing the epithet’s extraordinary status as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  43
    Vedānta: A Survey of Recent Scholarship (II).Michael S. Allen - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (1):41-71.
    This article surveys recent work on Vedānta, focusing on English-language secondary scholarship since the year 2000. The article consists of two parts. The first part (published previously) identified trends within recent scholarship, highlighting several promising areas of new research: the social history of Vedānta, Vedānta in the early modern period, vernacular Vedānta, Persian Vedānta, colonial and post-colonial Vedānta, and pedagogy and practice. It also covered edited volumes, special journal issues, and ongoing collaborative research projects. The second part (published here) provides (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  37
    Contradiction, Negation, and the Catuṣkoṭi: Just Several Passages from Dharmapāla’s Commentary on Āryadeva’s Catuḥśataka. [REVIEW]Chih-Chiang Hu - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (1):1-20.
    Using logic-laden terms to translate and interpret what the ancient Indian Buddhist thinkers said when we are not sure what they spoke about when they spoke about ‘contradictions’, etc. in natural languages can sometimes make things frustrating. Keeping in mind Wittgenstein’s exhortation, “don’t think, but look!”, I approach the issues of contradiction, negation, and the _catuṣkoṭi_ via case-by-case study on several pertinent passages in Dharmapāla’s _Dasheng Guangbailun Shilun_. The following are some interrelated observations which should not be overgeneralized, especially considering (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  25
    Candrakīrti on lokaprasiddhi: A Bad Hand, or an Ace in the Hole?John Newman - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (1):73-99.
    The Indian Buddhist Mādhyamika master Candrakīrti (ca. 7th century CE) grounds his philosophy in _lokaprasiddhi_ / -_prasiddha_, “that which is common knowledge / generally accepted among people in the world.” This raises the question of whether Candrakīrti accepts _everything_ that is “common knowledge” or instead distinguishes and privileges certain justifiable beliefs within common knowledge. Tom J.F. Tillemans has argued that Candrakīrti advocates a “lowest common denominator” version of _lokaprasiddhi_ instead of a model which promotes “in some areas at least, more (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  27
    Discerning Philosophy in the Uttarāmnāya Liturgies of the Newars.Pongsit Pangsrivongse - 2024 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 52 (1):21-40.
    Although the Kaula literature of the Newars did not give rise to a systematic philosophical school like that of their Kashmiri counterparts, I will argue in this article that philosophical thinking can be detected in Newar ritual texts. I do this by translating and analysing the unpublished _Kālīsūtra_, an important hymn found in Newar Uttarāmnāya liturgies whose transmission and composition will also be touched upon. This hymn indicates that the cult of Kālī in Nepal had a distinct ontological stance tending (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
 Previous issues
  
Next issues