6 found

View year:

  1.  18
    Contradictions and emptiness all the way down?Pedro Augusto De Oliveira Barbalho - 2024 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 33 (4):649-655.
    Markus Gabriel’s pluralism and Graham Priest’s monism can be considered new forms of skepticism in contemporary philosophy. Gabriel considers ‘emptiness’ and Priest ‘nothingness’ as safe havens for logic and philosophy. In the same way, traditional skeptics also considered nothing secure. Furthermore, we observe in this book that whilst both Priest and Gabriel present rather eloquent theories, they nevertheless lack more substantial proofs, much like many important theories in philosophy, such as Leibniz’s monadology.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  9
    Strong Kleene Logics as a Tool for Modelling Formal Epistemic Norms.Agustina Borzi, Federico Pailos & Joaquín T. Toranzo Calderón - 2024 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 33 (4):615-648.
    In this paper, we present two ways of modelling every epistemic formal conditional commitment that involves (at most) three key epistemic attitudes: acceptance, rejection and neither acceptance nor rejection. The first one consists of adopting the plurality of every mixed Strong Kleene logic (along with an epistemic reading of the truth-values), and the second one involves the use of a unified system of six-sided inferences, named 6SK, that recovers the validities of each mixed Strong Kleene logic. We also introduce a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  5
    A Note on Gödel’s First Disjunct Formalised in DTK System.Antonella Corradini & Sergio Galvan - 2024 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 33 (4):555-565.
    This note clarifies the significance of the proof of Gödel’s first disjunct obtained through the formalisation of Penrose’s second argument within the DTK system. It analyses two formulations of the first disjunct – one general and the other restricted – and dwells on the demonstration of the restricted version, showing that it yields the following result: if by F we denote the set of propositions derivable from any formalism and by K the set of mathematical propositions humanly knowable, then, given (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  4
    Uniform Cut-Free Bisequent Calculi for Three-Valued Logics.Andrzej Indrzejczak & Yaroslav Petrukhin - 2024 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 33 (3):463-506.
    We present a uniform characterisation of three-valued logics by means of a bisequent calculus (BSC). It is a generalised form of a sequent calculus (SC) where rules operate on the ordered pairs of ordinary sequents. BSC may be treated as the weakest kind of system in the rich family of generalised SC operating on items being some collections of ordinary sequents, like hypersequent and nested sequent calculi. It seems that for many non-classical logics, including some many-valued, paraconsistent and modal logics, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  4
    ZF-Class Nominalism and the Küng-Armstrong Trilemma. A Plea for Moderate Ineffabilism.Francesco F. Calemi - 2024 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 33 (2):205--2023.
    This paper will examine the Küng-Armstrong trilemma against Class Nominalism. We will see that combining Class Nominalism and Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory (ZF) can provide us with a sophisticated version of Class Nominalism, namely ZF-Class Nominalism, which successfully addresses the objection and leads to a moderate version of ineffabilism about the putative set-membership relation.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  85
    Justification Logic and the Epistemic Contribution of Deduction.Nancy Abigail Nuñez Hernández & Francisco Hernández-Quiroz - 2024 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 33:381-402.
    Accounting for the epistemic contribution of deduction has been a pervasive problem for logicians interested in deduction, such as, among others, Jakko Hintikka. The problem arises because the conclusion validly deduced from a set of premises is said to be “contained” in that set; because of this containment relation, the conclusion would be known from the moment the premises are known. Assuming this, it is problematic to explain how we can gain knowledge by deducing a logical consequence implied by a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
 Previous issues
  
Next issues