Don't fear the regress: Cognitive values and epistemic infinitism: Aikin don't fear the regress

Think 8 (23):55-61 (2009)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

We are rational creatures, in that we are beings on whom demands of rationality are appropriate. But by our rationality it doesn't follow that we always live up to those demands. In those cases, we fail to be rational, but it is in a way that is different from how rocks, tadpoles, and gum fail to be rational. For them, we use the term ‘arational.’ They don't have the demands, but we do. The demands of rationality bear on us because we have minds that can move us to act, inspire us to create, and bring us to believe in ways that are responsible and directed. My interests here are the demands rationality places on our beliefs. Beliefs aim at the truth, and so one of the demands of being a rational creature with beliefs is that we manage them in a way that is pursuant of the truth. Reasons and reasoning play the primary role in that management – we ought to believe on the basis of good reasons. That is, if you believe something, you think that you're right about the world in some way or another. You believe because you think that something is true. Now, p's truth is different from all ways it could be false, and your being right about p isn't just some arbitrary commitment, one that could just as well have been its negation. This non-arbitrary specificity of beliefs is constituted by the fact that they are held on the basis of reasons. Arguments are our model for how these reasons go – we offer some premises and show how they support a conclusion. Of course, arbitrary premises won't do, so you've got to have some reason for holding them as opposed to some others. Every premise, then, is a conclusion in need of an argument, and for arguments to be acceptable, we've got to do due diligence on the premises. This, however, leads to a disturbing pattern – for every premise we turn into a conclusion, we've got at least one other premise in need of another argument. Pretty soon, even the simplest arguments are going to get very, very complicated.

Other Versions

manuscript Aikin, Scott F. (manuscript) "Don't fear the regress: Epistemic infinitism and cognitive value".

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 100,809

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Epistemic Risk and the Demands of Rationality.Richard Pettigrew - 2022 - Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
Why Thinking Critically is Important.John Capps & Donald Capps - 2009 - In John Capps & Donald Capps (eds.), You've Got to Be Kidding!: How Jokes Can Help You Think. Malden MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 1–12.
Unavoidability and Commitment.Christopher Reich Taylor - 2002 - Dissertation, The University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill
Humean Testimony.Saul Traiger - unknown - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 74 (2):135-149.
No Commitment to the Truth.Anna-Maria A. Eder - 2021 - Synthese 198:7449-7472.
The fundamental principle of practical reasoning.Ralph Wedgwood - 1998 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 6 (2):189 – 209.
Why be rational.Niko Kolodny - 2005 - Mind 114 (455):509-563.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-10-15

Downloads
313 (#88,308)

6 months
16 (#185,084)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Scott Aikin
Vanderbilt University

Citations of this work

Creative reasoning.John Turri - 2014 - In John Turri & Peter D. Klein (eds.), Ad infinitum: new essays on epistemological infinitism. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. pp. 210-226.

Add more citations

References found in this work

No references found.

Add more references