Deception as treatment: the case of depression

Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (1):13-16 (2011)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Is it ever right to prescribe placebos to patients in clinical practice? The General Medical Council is ambivalent about the issue; the American Medical Association asserts that placebos can be administered only if the patient is (somehow) ‘informed’. The potential problem with placebos is that they may involve deception: indeed, if this is the case, an ethical tension arises over the patient's autonomy and the physician's requirement to be open and honest, and the notion that medical care should be the primary concern. This paper examines the case of depression as an entry point for understanding the complexities of the prescription of placebos. Recent important meta-analyses of antidepressants claim that they are not significantly more effective in a clinical setting than placebos. Given that antidepressants have numerous adverse side effects and are hugely expensive, this provocative research has serious potential ethical and practical implications for patients and medical providers. Should placebos be prescribed in place of antidepressants? The case of depression highlights another important issue which medical ethical codes have hitherto overlooked: well-being is not synonymous with being realistic about oneself, one's circumstances and the future. While severely depressed individuals are unduly pessimistic about themselves and the world around them, treatment of depressed individuals can be deemed successful when patients have successfully attained those positive illusions that are indicative of psychological health. This is exactly what successful psychological treatments of depression seem to achieve. It is therefore possible that there may be a limited unavoidable role for deception in medicine

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive

    This entry is not archived by us. If you are the author and have permission from the publisher, we recommend that you archive it. Many publishers automatically grant permission to authors to archive pre-prints. By uploading a copy of your work, you will enable us to better index it, making it easier to find.

    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 106,168

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

The concise argument.W. E. Cayley Jr - 2011 - Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (1):1-1.
The concise argument.Sarah Chan - 2009 - Journal of Medical Ethics 35 (10):589-589.
A Duty to Deceive: Placebos in Clinical Practice.Bennett Foddy - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (12):4-12.
Physician perspectives on placebo ethics.John Bliamptis & Anne Barnhill - 2022 - Journal of Medical Ethics 48 (10):759-763.
The duty to be Well-informed: The case of depression.Charlotte Blease - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (4):225-229.
What it takes to defend deceptive placebo use.Anne Barnhill - 2011 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 21 (3):219-250.

Analytics

Added to PP
2013-11-22

Downloads
66 (#349,877)

6 months
30 (#122,592)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

References found in this work

Creating mental illness.Allan V. Horwitz - 2002 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
A Duty to Deceive: Placebos in Clinical Practice.Bennett Foddy - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (12):4-12.
The ethics of the placebo in clinical practice.P. Lichtenberg - 2004 - Journal of Medical Ethics 30 (6):551-554.
When Doctors Deceive.Richard Kanaan - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (12):29-30.

View all 7 references / Add more references