Aristotle’s Methodology for Natural Science in Physics 1-2: a New Interpretation

Journal of Ancient Philosophy 14 (2):130-146 (2020)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

In this essay I will argue for an interpretation of the remarks of Physics 1.1 that both resolves some of the confusion surrounding the precise nature of methodology described there and shows how those remarks at 184a15-25 serve as important programmatic remarks besides, as they help in the structuring of books 1 and 2 of the Physics. I will argue that “what is clearer and more knowable to us” is what Aristotle goes on to describe in 1.2—namely, that nature exists and that natural things change—his basic starting-point for natural science. This, I shall hope to show, is the kind of “immediate” sense datum which Aristotle thinks must be further analyzed in terms of principles and then causes over the course of Physics books 1 and 2 to lead to knowledge about the natural world.[1] Such an analysis arrives at, as I shall show, a definition of nature not initially available from the starting-point just mentioned, and which is clearer by nature.[2] It is not my aim here to resolve longstanding debates surrounding Aristotle’s original intent in the ordering and composition of the first two books of the Physics, nor how the Physics is meant to fit into the Aristotelian corpus taken as a coherent whole, but rather to show that the first two books of the Physics, as they stand, fit with the picture of methodology for natural science presented to us in 1.1. [1] An interesting consequence of this, and one which I shall not pursue in this paper at any length, is that the progression from what is clearer to us and what is clearer by nature is by necessity a form of revision: i.e., the Physics should not be seen as a work validating the “starting-point” of 1.2 contra the monists, but a work which gradually builds to the language of matter and form as what is clearer by nature. [2] Viz., what we find at the beginning of 2.1: “this suggests that nature is a sort of source and cause of change and remaining unchanged in that to which it belongs primarily of itself, that is, not by virtue of concurrence”.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 100,561

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Albertus Magnus and Thomas Aquinas on What is “Better-Known” in Natural Science.John H. Boyer & Daniel C. Wagner - 2019 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 93:199-225.
Aristotle's Motivation for Matter.David Ebrey - 2007 - Dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles
Aristotle’s theory of language in the light of Phys. I.1.Pavol Labuda - 2018 - Aither. Journal for the Study of Greek and Latin Philosophical Traditions 10 (20/2018 - International Issue 5):66-77.
Aristotle's Concept of Nature.Stasinos Stavrianeas - 2004 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 7.
What "becomes" in temporal becoming?James Harrington - 2009 - American Philosophical Quarterly 46 (3):249-265.
On Aristotle's "Physics 1.1-3".John Philoponus & Catherine Osborne - 2006 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. Edited by Catherine Osborne.

Analytics

Added to PP
2020-10-26

Downloads
16 (#1,170,848)

6 months
4 (#1,227,078)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Evan Dutmer
Culver Academies

Citations of this work

No citations found.

Add more citations

References found in this work

Aristotle's first principles.Terence Irwin - 1988 - New York: Oxford University Press.
Philosophy of science.Richard J. Hankinson - 1995 - In Jonathan Barnes (ed.), The Cambridge companion to Aristotle. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 109--39.
Physics: Books I and II. Aristotle - 1992 - In W. Charlton (ed.). Oxford University Press.

View all 8 references / Add more references