Abstract
When Michael Smith published The Moral Problem, he advocated only Weak Moral
Rationalism: the view that moral requirements always provide us with reasons that
are relevant to the rationality of our action. But in the intervening years he has
changed his position. He now holds Strong Moral Rationalism: the view that moral
requirements are all-things-considered rational requirements. In this paper I argue
that his change in view was motivated by two things. The first is his correct view
that acting as one is morally required to act is never irrational. The second is what
David Copp has called The Unitary View of Reasons: the idea that there are both
moral reasons for action, and non-moral ones, and both sorts count as reasons that
determine what is rational to do. This combination of views pushes Smith to hold
that an act counts as morally required just in case the moral reasons that favor it
outweigh all other reasons, both moral and non-moral. But, I argue, there is an
attractive position between Weak and Strong Moral Rationalism, which I call Moral
Permissibilism. On such a view, moral requirements, while not always rational
requirements (as against Strong Moral Rationalism), are always rationally permissible
(as against Moral Anti-Rationalism). In order to advocate this common-sensical
position, however, one must abandon the Unitary View of Reasons, and recognize
that reasons of different kinds contribute to different kinds of normative verdicts.