The Variety of Consequence, According to Bolzano

Studia Logica 44 (4):389-403 (1985)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Contemporary historians of logic tend to credit Bernard Bolzano with the invention of the semantic notion of consequence, a full century before Tarski. Nevertheless, Bolzano's work played no significant rôle in the genesis of modern logical semantics. The purpose of this paper is to point out three highly original, and still quite relevant themes in Bolzano's work, being a systematic study of possible types of inference, of consistency, as well as their meta-theory. There are certain analogies with Tarski's concerns here, although the main thrust seems to be different, both philosophically and technically. Thus, if only obliquely, we also provide some additional historical perspective on Tarski's achievement.

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 100,154

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Etchemendy and Bolzano on Logical Consequence.Paul Rusnock & Mark Burke - 2010 - History and Philosophy of Logic 31 (1):3-29.
Bolzano's deducibility and tarski's logical consequence.Paul B. Thompson - 1981 - History and Philosophy of Logic 2 (1-2):11-20.
Bolzano versus Kant: mathematics as a scientia universalis.Paola Cantù - 2011 - Philosophical Papers Dedicated to Kevin Mulligan.
Early Bolzano on ground-consequence proofs.Stefania Centrone - 2016 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 22 (2):215-237.
Husserl and Bolzano.Ettore Casari - 2017 - In Stefania Centrone (ed.), Essays on Husserl’s Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics. Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer Verlag.
Bernard Bolzano: Theory of Science.Paul Rusnock & Rolf George (eds.) - 2014 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
What is Tarski's common concept of consequence?Ignacio Jané - 2006 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 12 (1):1-42.
On a fallacy attributed to Tarski.Mario Gómez-Torrente - 1998 - History and Philosophy of Logic 19 (4):227-234.

Analytics

Added to PP
2017-02-21

Downloads
19 (#1,063,092)

6 months
7 (#673,909)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Johan Van Benthem
University of Amsterdam

Citations of this work

Logical constants across varying types.Johan van Benthem - 1989 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 30 (3):315-342.
The Deduction Theorem (Before and After Herbrand).Curtis Franks - 2021 - History and Philosophy of Logic 42 (2):129-159.
Logic in Philosophy.Johan van Benthem - 2002 - In Dale Jacquette (ed.), Philosophy of Logic. Malden, Mass.: North Holland. pp. 65-99.
McCarthy variations in a modal key.Johan van Benthem - 2011 - Artificial Intelligence 175 (1):428-439.
The many faces of interpolation.Johan van Benthem - 2008 - Synthese 164 (3):451-460.

View all 9 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

Philosophy of Logic.Michael Jubien & W. V. Quine - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (1):303.
On engendering an illusion of understanding.Dana Scott - 1971 - Journal of Philosophy 68 (21):787-807.
Bolzano's Logic.Jan Berg - 1965 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 155:248-248.
Ramsey eliminability.J. F. A. K. van Benthem - 1978 - Studia Logica 37 (4):321-336.
Foundations of Conditional Logic.Johan Van Benthem - 1984 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 13 (3):303-349.

View all 8 references / Add more references