Results for ' Symbolical Algebra, Calculus of Operations'

957 found
Order:
  1. 19th century logic between philosophy and mathematics.Volker Peckhaus - 1999 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 5 (4):433-450.
    The history of modern logic is usually written as the history of mathematical or, more general, symbolic logic. As such it was created by mathematicians. Not regarding its anticipations in Scholastic logic and in the rationalistic era, its continuous development began with George Boole's The Mathematical Analysis of Logic of 1847, and it became a mathematical subdiscipline in the early 20th century. This style of presentation cuts off one eminent line of development, the philosophical development of logic, although logic is (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  2. An algebraic approach to intuitionistic connectives.Xavier Caicedo & Roberto Cignoli - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (4):1620-1636.
    It is shown that axiomatic extensions of intuitionistic propositional calculus defining univocally new connectives, including those proposed by Gabbay, are strongly complete with respect to valuations in Heyting algebras with additional operations. In all cases, the double negation of such a connective is equivalent to a formula of intuitionistic calculus. Thus, under the excluded third law it collapses to a classical formula, showing that this condition in Gabbay's definition is redundant. Moreover, such connectives can not be interpreted (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  3.  45
    An Algebraic Study of Tense Operators on Nelson Algebras.A. V. Figallo, G. Pelaitay & J. Sarmiento - 2020 - Studia Logica 109 (2):285-312.
    Ewald considered tense operators G, H, F and P on intuitionistic propositional calculus and constructed an intuitionistic tense logic system called IKt. In 2014, Figallo and Pelaitay introduced the variety IKt of IKt-algebras and proved that the IKt system has IKt-algebras as algebraic counterpart. In this paper, we introduce and study the variety of tense Nelson algebras. First, we give some examples and we prove some properties. Next, we associate an IKt-algebra to each tense Nelson algebras. This result allowed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  96
    Algebraic Study of Two Deductive Systems of Relevance Logic.Josep Maria Font & Gonzalo Rodríguez - 1994 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 35 (3):369-397.
    In this paper two deductive systems associated with relevance logic are studied from an algebraic point of view. One is defined by the familiar, Hilbert-style, formalization of R; the other one is a weak version of it, called WR, which appears as the semantic entailment of the Meyer-Routley-Fine semantics, and which has already been suggested by Wójcicki for other reasons. This weaker consequence is first defined indirectly, using R, but we prove that the first one turns out to be an (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  5.  8
    Symbolic Algebra as a Semiotic System.Ladislav Kvasz - 2024 - In Bharath Sriraman (ed.), Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Cham: Springer. pp. 3101-3133.
    The invention of symbolic algebra in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries fundamentally changed the way we do mathematics. If we want to understand this change and appreciate its importance, we must analyze it on two levels. One concerns the compositional function of algebraic symbols as tools for representing complexity; the other concerns the referential function of algebraic symbols, which enables their use as tools for describing objects (such as polynomials), properties (such as irreducibility), relations (such as divisibility), and operations (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  49
    Projective algebra and the calculus of relations.A. R. Bednarek & S. M. Ulam - 1978 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 43 (1):56-64.
  7.  35
    The laws of thought (1854).George Boole - 1854 - London,: The Open court publishing company.
    This groundbreaking work on logic by the brilliant 19th-century English mathematician George Boole remains influential to this day. Boole's major contribution was to demonstrate conclusively that the symbolic expressions of algebra could be adapted to convey the fundamental principles and operations of logic, which hitherto had been expressed only in words. Boole was thus the founder of today's science of symbolic logic. Summing up his innovative approach, Boole stated, "We ought no longer to associate Logic and Metaphysics, but Logic (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  8.  61
    (1 other version)A Gentzen-type calculus of sequents for single-operator propositional logic.John Riser - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (1):75-80.
  9.  51
    Ilijas Farah, Bradd Hart, and David Sherman. Model theory of operator algebras I: stability. Bulletin of the London Mathematical Society, vol. 45 (2013), no. 4, pp. 825–838, doi:10.1112/blms/bdt014. - Ilijas Farah, Bradd Hart, and David Sherman. Model theory of operator algebras II: model theory. Israel Journal of Mathematics, vol. 201 (2014), no. 1, pp. 477–505, doi:10.1007/s11856-014-1046-7. - Ilijas Farah, Bradd Hart, and David Sherman. Model theory of operator algebras III: elementary equivalence and II 1 factors. Bulletin of the London Mathematical Society, vol. 46 (2014), no. 3, pp. 609–628, doi:10.1112/blms/bdu012. - Isaac Goldbring, Bradd Hart, and Thomas Sinclair. The theory of tracial von Neumann algebras does not have a model companion. Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 78 (2013), no. 3, pp. 1000–1004. [REVIEW]Itaï Ben Yaacov - 2015 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 21 (4):425-427.
  10.  29
    Tsutomu Hosoi. Algebraic proof of the separation theorem on classical propositional calculus. Proceedings of the Japan Academy, vol. 42 , pp. 67–69. - Tsutomu Hosoi. Algebraic proof of the separation theorem on Dummett's LC. Proceedings of the Japan Academy, vol. 42 , pp. 693–695. [REVIEW]Alfred Horn - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (1):128-129.
  11.  40
    Calculus of Contextual Rough Sets in Contextual Spaces.Edward Bryniarski & Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska - 1998 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 8 (1):9-26.
    The work broadens – to a considerable extent – Z. Pawlak’s original method (1982, 1992) of approximation of sets. The approximation of sets included in a universum U goes on in the contextual approximation space CAS which consists of: 1) a sequence of Pawlak’s approximation spaces (U,Ci), where indexes i from set I are linearly ordered degrees of contexts (I, <), and Ci is the universum partition U, 2) a sequence of binary relations on sets included in U, relations called (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  30
    (1 other version)Butler Jean W.. On complete and independent sets of truth functions in multi-valued logics. Summaries of talks presented at the Summer Institute for Symbolic Logic, Cornell University, 1957, 2nd edn., Communications Research Division, Institute for Defense Analyses, Princeton, N.J., 1960, pp. 78–80.Butler Jean W.. On complete and independent sets of operations in finite algebras. Pacific journal of mathematics, vol. 10 , pp. 1169–1179. [REVIEW]Atwell R. Turquette - 1965 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 30 (2):246-246.
  13.  45
    An Algebraic Characterization of Equivalent Preferential Models.Zhaohui Zhu & Rong Zhang - 2007 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 72 (3):803 - 833.
    Preferential model is one of the important semantical structures in nonmonotonic logic. This paper aims to establish an isomorphism theorem for preferential models, which gives us a purely algebraic characterization of the equivalence of preferential models. To this end, we present the notions of local similarity and local simulation. Based on these notions, two operators Δ(·) and μ(·) over preferential models are introduced and explored respectively. Together with other two existent operators ρ(·) and ΠD(·), we introduce an operator ∂D(·). Then (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  21
    Undecidable Varieties of Semilattice—ordered Semigroups, of Boolean Algebras with Operators, and logics extending Lambek Calculus.A. Kurucz, I. Nemeti, I. Sain & A. Simon - 1993 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 1 (1):91-98.
    We prove that the equational theory of a semigroups becomes undecidable if we add a semilattice structure with a ‘touch of symmetric difference’. As a corollary we obtain that the variety of all Boolean algebras with an associative binary operator has a ‘hereditarily’ undecidable equational theory. Our results have implications in logic, e.g. they imply undecidability of modal logics extending the Lambek Calculus and undecidability of Arrow Logics with an associative arrow modality.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  44
    Simon Kochen and E. P. Specker. Logical structures arising in quantum theory. A reprint of XL 507. The logieo-algebraic approach to quantum mechanics, Volume I, Historicale evolution, edited by C. A. Hooker, The University of Western Ontario series in philosophy of science, vol. 5, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht and Boston1975, pp. 263–276. - Simon Kochen and E. P. Specker. The calculus of partial propositional functions. A reprint of XL 508. The logieo-algebraic approach to quantum mechanics, Volume I, Historical evolution, edited by C. A. Hooker, The University of Western Ontario series in philosophy of science, vol. 5, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht and Boston1975, pp. 277–292. - P.D. Finch. On the structure of quantum logic. The logieo-algebraic approach to quantum mechanics, Volume I, Historical evolution, edited by C. A. Hooker, The University of Western Ontario series in philosophy of science, vol. 5, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht and Boston1975, pp. [REVIEW]R. I. G. Hughes - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (2):558-566.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  52
    John Riser. A Gentzen-type calculus of sequents for single-operator propositional logic. The Journal of symbolic logic, vol. 32 , pp. 75–80. [REVIEW]Gene F. Rose - 1968 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 33 (1):129-129.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  35
    Ockham’s Calculus of Strict Implication.Wolfgang Lenzen - 2015 - Logica Universalis 9 (2):181-191.
    In his main work Summa Logicae written around 1323, William of Ockham developed a system of propositional modal logic which contains almost all theorems of a modern calculus of strict implication. This calculus is formally reconstructed here with the help of modern symbols for the operators of conjunction, disjunction, implication, negation, possibility, and necessity.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  56
    K. Menger. The algebra of functions: past, present, future. Rendiconti di matematica, vol. 20 , pp. 409–430. - Karl Menger. Function algebra and propositional calculus. Self-organizing systems 1962, edited by Marshall C. Yovits, George T. Jacobi, and Gordon D. Goldstein, Spartan Books, Washington, D.C., 1962, pp. 525–532. - Karl Menger and Martin Schultz. Postulates for the substitutive algebra of the 2-place functors in the 2-valued calculus of propositions. Notre Dame journal of formal logic, vol. 4 no. 3 , pp. 188–192. - Robert E. Seall. Truth-valued fluents and qualitative laws. Philosophy of science, vol. 30 , pp. 36–10. [REVIEW]Bruce Lercher - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (2):272.
  19.  29
    Aubert Daigneault. Operations in polyadic algebras. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 158 , pp. 219–229. [REVIEW]Stephen D. Comer - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (2):337-338.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  25
    Tsao-Chen Tang. Algebraic postulates and a geometric interpretation for the Lewis calculus of strict implication. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 44 , pp. 737–744. [REVIEW]Charles A. Baylis - 1939 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 4 (1):27-27.
  21.  35
    Arto Salomaa. On infinitely generated sets of operations infinite algebras. Annales Universitatis Turkuensis, series A, I, Astronomica-chemica-physica-mathematica, no. 74. Turun Yliopisto, Turku1964, 13 pp. [REVIEW]Atwell R. Turquette - 1966 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 31 (1):119-120.
  22.  60
    Charles Sanders Peirce. Insolubilia. A reprint of 2813. Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volume II, Elements of logic, edited by Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss, The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass., and Oxford University Press, London, 1960, pp. 370–371. - C. S. Peirce. On an improvement in Boole's calculus of logic. A reprint of 281. Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volume III, Exact logic, pp. 3–15. - C. S. Peirce. Upon the logic of mathematics. A reprint of 282. Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volume III, Exact logic, pp. 16–26. - C. S. Peirce. Description of a notation for the logic of relatives, resulting from an amplification of the conceptions of Boole's calculus of logic. A reprint of 284. Collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volume III, Exact logic, pp. 27–98. - C. S. Peirce. On the algebra of logic. Part I.—Syllogistic. Part II.—The logic of non-relative terms. Part III.—The logic of relatives. A reprint o. [REVIEW]Alonzo Church - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (3):494-495.
  23.  65
    Kiyoshi Iséki. An algebra related with a propositional calculus. Proceedings of the Japan Academy, vol. 42 , pp. 26–29. - Yoshinari Arai, Kiyoshi Iséki, and Shôtarô Tanaka. Characterizations of BCI, BCK-algebras. Proceedings of the Japan Academy, vol. 42 , pp. 105–107. - Kiyoshi Iséki. Algebraic formulation of propositional calculi with general detachment rule. Proceedings of the Japan Academy, vol. 43 , pp. 31–34. [REVIEW]R. B. Angell - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (3):465-466.
  24.  27
    Kirin Vladimir G.. On the polynomial representation of operators in the n-valued propositional calculus. Glasnik matematičko-fizički i astronomski , ser. 2 vol. 18 , pp. 3–12. [REVIEW]R. L. Graham - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (4):756-756.
  25. Positive logic with adjoint modalities: Proof theory, semantics, and reasoning about information: Positive logic with adjoint modalities.Mehrnoosh Sadrzadeh - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (3):351-373.
    We consider a simple modal logic whose nonmodal part has conjunction and disjunction as connectives and whose modalities come in adjoint pairs, but are not in general closure operators. Despite absence of negation and implication, and of axioms corresponding to the characteristic axioms of _T_, _S4_, and _S5_, such logics are useful, as shown in previous work by Baltag, Coecke, and the first author, for encoding and reasoning about information and misinformation in multiagent systems. For the propositional-only fragment of such (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  26.  39
    Halmos Paul R.. Predicates, terms, operations, and equality in polyadic Boolean algebras. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, t. 42 , p. 130–136. [REVIEW]Roland Fraïssé - 1960 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 25 (2):168-168.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  19
    Heaviside's operational calculus and the attempts to rigorise it.Jesper Lützen - 1979 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 21 (2):161-200.
    At the end of the 19th century Oliver Heaviside developed a formal calculus of differential operators in order to solve various physical problems. The pure mathematicians of his time would not deal with this unrigorous theory, but in the 20th century several attempts were made to rigorise Heaviside's operational calculus. These attempts can be grouped in two classes. The one leading to an explanation of the operational calculus in terms of integral transformations (Bromwich, Carson, Vander Pol, Doetsch) (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  28. is a set B with Boolean operations a∨ b (join), a∧ b (meet) and− a (complement), partial ordering a≤ b defined by a∧ b= a and the smallest and greatest element, 0 and 1. By Stone's Representation Theorem, every Boolean algebra is isomorphic to an algebra of subsets of some nonempty set S, under operations a∪ b, a∩ b, S− a, ordered by inclusion, with 0=∅. [REVIEW]Mystery Of Measurability - 2006 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 12 (2).
  29.  38
    Complexity of equations valid in algebras of relations part I: Strong non-finitizability.Hajnal Andréka - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 89 (2):149-209.
    We study algebras whose elements are relations, and the operations are natural “manipulations” of relations. This area goes back to 140 years ago to works of De Morgan, Peirce, Schröder . Well known examples of algebras of relations are the varieties RCAn of cylindric algebras of n-ary relations, RPEAn of polyadic equality algebras of n-ary relations, and RRA of binary relations with composition. We prove that any axiomatization, say E, of RCAn has to be very complex in the following (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  30.  26
    Completions of μ-algebras.Luigi Santocanale - 2008 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 154 (1):27-50.
    A μ-algebra is a model of a first-order theory that is an extension of the theory of bounded lattices, that comes with pairs of terms where μx.f is axiomatized as the least prefixed point of f, whose axioms are equations or equational implications.Standard μ-algebras are complete meaning that their lattice reduct is a complete lattice. We prove that any nontrivial quasivariety of μ-algebras contains a μ-algebra that has no embedding into a complete μ-algebra.We then focus on modal μ-algebras, i.e. algebraic (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31.  35
    Bernstein B. A.. Postulates for Boolean algebra involving the operation of complete disjunction. Annals of mathematics, 2 s. vol. 37 , pp. 317–325. [REVIEW]Barkley Rosser - 1936 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 1 (2):68-68.
  32.  34
    Halmos Paul R.. Algebraic logic, III. Predicates, terms, and operations in polyadic algebras. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, t. 83 , pp. 430–470. [REVIEW]Roland Fraïssé - 1958 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 23 (4):448-449.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  39
    Complexity of equations valid in algebras of relations part II: Finite axiomatizations.Hajnal Andréka - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 89 (2-3):211-229.
    We study algebras whose elements are relations, and the operations are natural “manipulations” of relations. This area goes back to 140 years ago to works of De Morgan, Peirce, Schröder . Well known examples of algebras of relations are the varieties RCAn of cylindric algebras of n-ary relations, RPEAn of polyadic equality algebras of n-ary relations, and RRA of binary relations with composition. We prove that any axiomatization, say E, of RCAn has to be very complex in the following (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34.  63
    A Characterization of the free n-generated MV-algebra.Daniele Mundici - 2006 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 45 (2):239-247.
    An MV-algebra A=(A,0,¬,⊕) is an abelian monoid (A,0,⊕) equipped with a unary operation ¬ such that ¬¬x=x,x⊕¬0=¬0, and y⊕¬(y⊕¬x)=x⊕¬(x⊕¬y). Chang proved that the equational class of MV-algebras is generated by the real unit interval [0,1] equipped with the operations ¬x=1−x and x⊕y=min(1,x+y). Therefore, the free n-generated MV-algebra Free n is the algebra of [0,1]-valued functions over the n-cube [0,1] n generated by the coordinate functions ξ i ,i=1, . . . ,n, with pointwise operations. Any such function f (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35. Dividing in the algebra of compact operators.Alexander Berenstein - 2004 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (3):817-829.
    We interpret the algebra of finite rank operators as imaginaries inside a Hilbert space. We prove that the Hilbert space enlarged with these imaginaries has built-in canonical bases.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  53
    Horrent with Mysterious Spiculæ’. Augustus De Morgan’s Logic Notation of 1850 as a ‘Calculus of Opposite Relations.Anna-Sophie Heinemann - 2018 - History and Philosophy of Logic 39 (1):29-52.
    The present paper expounds the logic notation proposed by Augustus De Morgan in 1850 from within the original context of De Morgan’s account of syllogistic logic and his approach to quantification. The notational system of 1850 is shown to be a flexible tool to state inferences, to prove their validity and to derive formulæ of the respective system by ‘blind’ application of transformation rules. These pertain to the swapping of operator signs, which are of inverse ‘character’ in a two-fold sense: (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. Logics of Formal Inconsistency Enriched with Replacement: An Algebraic and Modal Account.Walter Carnielli, Marcelo E. Coniglio & David Fuenmayor - 2022 - Review of Symbolic Logic 15 (3):771-806.
    One of the most expected properties of a logical system is that it can be algebraizable, in the sense that an algebraic counterpart of the deductive machinery could be found. Since the inception of da Costa's paraconsistent calculi, an algebraic equivalent for such systems have been searched. It is known that these systems are non self-extensional (i.e., they do not satisfy the replacement property). More than this, they are not algebraizable in the sense of Blok-Pigozzi. The same negative results hold (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  29
    Kripke Contexts, Double Boolean Algebras with Operators and Corresponding Modal Systems.Prosenjit Howlader & Mohua Banerjee - 2023 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 32 (1):117-146.
    The notion of a context in formal concept analysis and that of an approximation space in rough set theory are unified in this study to define a Kripke context. For any context (G,M,I), a relation on the set G of objects and a relation on the set M of properties are included, giving a structure of the form ((G,R), (M,S), I). A Kripke context gives rise to complex algebras based on the collections of protoconcepts and semiconcepts of the underlying context. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  6
    A set of five postulates for Boolean algebras in terms of the operation "exception"..James Sturdevant Taylor - 1920 - [Berkeley,: University of California press.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  93
    Relevance logic and the calculus of relations.Roger D. Maddux - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (1):41-70.
    Sound and complete semantics for classical propositional logic can be obtained by interpreting sentences as sets. Replacing sets with commuting dense binary relations produces an interpretation that turns out to be sound but not complete for R. Adding transitivity yields sound and complete semantics for RM, because all normal Sugihara matrices are representable as algebras of binary relations.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41.  9
    Undecidability of Algebras of Binary Relations.Robin Hirsch, Ian Hodkinson & Marcel Jackson - 2021 - In Judit Madarász & Gergely Székely (eds.), Hajnal Andréka and István Németi on Unity of Science: From Computing to Relativity Theory Through Algebraic Logic. Springer. pp. 267-287.
    Let S be a signature of operations and relations definable in relation algebra, let R be the class of all S-structures isomorphic to concrete algebras of binary relations with concrete interpretations for symbols in S, and let F be the class of S-structures isomorphic to concrete algebras of binary relations over a finite base. To prove that membership of R or F for finite S-structures is undecidable, we reduce from a known undecidable problem—here we use the tiling problem, the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Introduction to the Symbolic Plithogenic Algebraic Structures (revisited).Florentin Smarandache - 2023 - Neutrosophic Sets and Systems 53.
    In this paper, we recall and study the new type of algebraic structures called Symbolic Plithogenic Algebraic Structures. Their operations are given under the Absorbance Law and the Prevalence Order.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  78
    Abacus logic: The lattice of quantum propositions as the poset of a theory.Othman Qasim Malhas - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (2):501-515.
    With a certain graphic interpretation in mind, we say that a function whose value at every point in its domain is a nonempty set of real numbers is an Abacus. It is shown that to every collection C of abaci there corresponds a logic, called an abacus logic, i.e., a certain set of propositions partially ordered by generalized implication. It is also shown that to every collection C of abaci there corresponds a theory JC in a classical propositional calculus (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  28
    Neurath and the Legacy of Algebraic Logic.Jordi Cat - 2019 - In Adam Tuboly & Jordi Cat (eds.), Neurath Reconsidered: New Sources and Perspectives. Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 241-337.
    In this paper I introduce a broader context, and sketch an integrated account with the purpose of examining the significance of Neurath’s attention to logic in early works and subsequent positions. The specific attention to algebraic logic is important in integrating his own interest in mathematics and combining, since Leibniz, the ideals of a universal language and of a calculus of reasoning. The interest in universal languages constitutes a much broader, so-called tradition of pasigraphy that extended beyond philosophical projects. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45. Storage operators and directed lambda-calculus.René David & Karim Nour - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (4):1054-1086.
    Storage operators have been introduced by J. L. Krivine in [5] they are closed λ-terms which, for a data type, allow one to simulate a "call by value" while using the "call by name" strategy. In this paper, we introduce the directed λ-calculus and show that it has the usual properties of the ordinary λ-calculus. With this calculus we get an equivalent--and simple--definition of the storage operators that allows to show some of their properties: $\bullet$ the stability (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  19
    Fibred algebraic semantics for a variety of non-classical first-order logics and topological logical translation.Yoshihiro Maruyama - 2021 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 86 (3):1189-1213.
    Lawvere hyperdoctrines give categorical algebraic semantics for intuitionistic predicate logic. Here we extend the hyperdoctrinal semantics to a broad variety of substructural predicate logics over the Typed Full Lambek Calculus, verifying their completeness with respect to the extended hyperdoctrinal semantics. This yields uniform hyperdoctrinal completeness results for numerous logics such as different types of relevant predicate logics and beyond, which are new results on their own; i.e., we give uniform categorical semantics for a broad variety of non-classical predicate logics. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  81
    Lingua characterica and calculus ratiocinator: The Leibnizian background of the Frege-Schröder polemic.Joan Bertran-San Millán - 2021 - Review of Symbolic Logic 14 (2):411-446.
    After the publication of Begriffsschrift, a conflict erupted between Frege and Schröder regarding their respective logical systems which emerged around the Leibnizian notions of lingua characterica and calculus ratiocinator. Both of them claimed their own logic to be a better realisation of Leibniz’s ideal language and considered the rival system a mere calculus ratiocinator. Inspired by this polemic, van Heijenoort (1967b) distinguished two conceptions of logic—logic as language and logic as calculus—and presented them as opposing views, but (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  39
    A variety of algebras closely related to subordination algebras.Sergio Celani & Ramon Jansana - 2022 - Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 32 (2):200-238.
    We introduce a variety of algebras in the language of Boolean algebras with an extra implication, namely the variety of pseudo-subordination algebras, which is closely related to subordination algebras. We believe it provides a minimal general algebraic framework where to place and systematise the research on classes of algebras related to several kinds of subordination algebras. We also consider the subvariety of pseudo-contact algebras, related to contact algebras, and the subvariety of the strict implication algebras introduced in Bezhanishvili et al. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  2
    Algebraic Semantics for a Mixed Type Fragment of IPC.Eryk Lipka & Katarzyna Słomczyńska - forthcoming - Studia Logica:1-25.
    We investigate algebraically the fragment of the intuitionistic propositional calculus consisting of equivalence together with conjunction on the intuitionistic regularizations. We find that this fragment is strongly algebraizable with the equivalent algebraic semantics being the variety of equivalential algebras with an additional binary operation that can be interpreted as the meet on regular elements. We give a finite equational base for this variety, and investigate its properties, in particular the commutator. As applications, we prove that the fragment is hereditarily (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  74
    Compatibility operators in abstract algebraic logic.Hugo Albuquerque, Josep Maria Font & Ramon Jansana - 2016 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 81 (2):417-462.
    This paper presents a unified framework that explains and extends the already successful applications of the Leibniz operator, the Suszko operator, and the Tarski operator in recent developments in abstract algebraic logic. To this end, we refine Czelakowski’s notion of an S-compatibility operator, and introduce the notion of coherent family of S-compatibility operators, for a sentential logic S. The notion of coherence is a restricted property of commutativity with inverse images by surjective homomorphisms, which is satisfied by both the Leibniz (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 957