Results for ' Wilkosz’s axioms'

966 found
Order:
  1. On Certain Axiomatizations of Arithmetic of Natural and Integer Numbers.Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska - 2019 - Axioms 2019 (Deductive Systems).
    The systems of arithmetic discussed in this work are non-elementary theories. In this paper, natural numbers are characterized axiomatically in two di erent ways. We begin by recalling the classical set P of axioms of Peano’s arithmetic of natural numbers proposed in 1889 (including such primitive notions as: set of natural numbers, zero, successor of natural number) and compare it with the set W of axioms of this arithmetic (including the primitive notions like: set of natural numbers and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  36
    Martin's Axiom and the Dual Distributivity Number.Jörg Brendle - 2000 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 46 (2):241-248.
    We show that it is consistent that Martin's axiom holds, the continuum is large, and yet the dual distributivity number ℌ is κ1. This answers a question of Halbeisen.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  47
    Woodin's axiom , bounded forcing axioms, and precipitous ideals on ω 1.Benjamin Claverie & Ralf Schindler - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (2):475-498.
    If the Bounded Proper Forcing Axiom BPFA holds, then Mouse Reflection holds at N₂ with respect to all mouse operators up to the level of Woodin cardinals in the next ZFC-model. This yields that if Woodin's ℙ max axiom (*) holds, then BPFA implies that V is closed under the "Woodin-in-the-next-ZFC-model" operator. We also discuss stronger Mouse Reflection principles which we show to follow from strengthenings of BPFA, and we discuss the theory BPFA plus "NS ω1 is precipitous" and strengthenings (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  4. Martin's axiom, omitting types, and complete representations in algebraic logic.Tarek Sayed Ahmed - 2002 - Studia Logica 72 (2):285 - 309.
    We give a new characterization of the class of completely representable cylindric algebras of dimension 2 #lt; n w via special neat embeddings. We prove an independence result connecting cylindric algebra to Martin''s axiom. Finally we apply our results to finite-variable first order logic showing that Henkin and Orey''s omitting types theorem fails for L n, the first order logic restricted to the first n variables when 2 #lt; n#lt;w. L n has been recently (and quite extensively) studied as a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  5.  50
    Zermelo's Axiom of Choice. Its Origins, Development, and Influence.Gregory H. Moore - 1984 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 49 (2):659-660.
  6.  55
    Freiling's axioms of symmetry in a general setting and some applications.Athanassios Tzouvaras - 2001 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 40 (2):131-145.
    We formulate C. Freiling's axioms of symmetry for general second-order structures with respect to a certain ideal of small sets contained in them and find several equivalent formulations of the principles. Then we focus on particular models, namely saturated and recursively saturated ones, and show that they are symmetric with respect to appropriate classes of small sets when their second-order part consists of definable sets. Some asymmetric models are also exhibited as well as partial asymmetric ones constructed by forcing.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7. Martin's axioms, measurability and equiconsistency results.Jaime I. Ihoda & Saharon Shelah - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (1):78-94.
    We deal with the consistency strength of ZFC + variants of MA + suitable sets of reals are measurable (and/or Baire, and/or Ramsey). We improve the theorem of Harrington and Shelah [2] repairing the asymmetry between measure and category, obtaining also the same result for Ramsey. We then prove parallel theorems with weaker versions of Martin's axiom (MA(σ-centered), (MA(σ-linked)), MA(Γ + ℵ 0 ), MA(K)), getting Mahlo, inaccessible and weakly compact cardinals respectively. We prove that if there exists r ∈ (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  8.  77
    Martin’s Axiom and embeddings of upper semi-lattices into the Turing degrees.Wang Wei - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (10):1291-1298.
    It is shown that every locally countable upper semi-lattice of cardinality the continuum can be embedded into the Turing degrees, assuming Martin’s Axiom.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  48
    Fraenkel's axiom of restriction: Axiom choice, intended models and categoricity.Georg Schiemer - 2010 - In Benedikt Löwe & Thomas Müller (eds.), PhiMSAMP: philosophy of mathematics: sociological aspsects and mathematical practice. London: College Publications. pp. 307{340.
  10. Sidgwick's Axioms and Consequentialism.Robert Shaver - 2014 - Philosophical Review 123 (2):173-204.
    Sidgwick gives various tests for highest certainty. When he applies these tests to commonsense morality, he finds nothing of highest certainty. In contrast, when he applies these tests to his own axioms, he finds these axioms to have highest certainty. The axioms culminate in Benevolence: “Each one is morally bound to regard the good of any other individual as much as his own, except in so far as he judges it to be less, when impartially viewed, or (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  66
    A characterization of Martin's axiom in terms of absoluteness.Joan Bagaria - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (2):366-372.
    Martin's axiom is equivalent to the statement that the universe is absolute under ccc forcing extensions for Σ 1 sentences with a subset of $\kappa, \kappa , as a parameter.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  12.  20
    Peano's axioms in their historical context.Michael Segre - 1994 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 48 (3-4):201-342.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  13.  89
    Martin's axiom in the model theory of LA.W. Richard Stark - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (1):172 - 176.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  48
    Fragments of Martin's axiom and δ13 sets of reals.Joan Bagaria - 1994 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 69 (1):1-25.
    We strengthen a result of Harrington and Shelah by showing that, unless ω1 is an inaccessible cardinal in L, a relatively weak fragment of Martin's axiom implies that there exists a δ13 set of reals without the property of Baire.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  15.  19
    Martin's axiom and ordinal graphs: Large independent sets or infinite paths.Jean A. Larson - 1990 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 47 (1):31.
  16. (1 other version)Peirce's axioms for propositional calculus.A. N. Prior - 1958 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 23 (2):135-136.
  17.  98
    Martin's axiom and $\Delta^2_1$ well-ordering of the reals.Uri Abraham & Saharon Shelah - 1996 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 35 (5):287-298.
    Assuming an inaccessible cardinal $\kappa$ , there is a generic extension in which $MA + 2^{\aleph_0} = \kappa$ holds and the reals have a $\Delta^2_1$ well-ordering.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  72
    Martin's axiom and the continuum.Haim Judah & Andrzej Rosłanowski - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (2):374-391.
  19.  64
    Martin's axiom and a regular topological space with uncountable net weight whose countable product is hereditarily separable and hereditarily lindelöf.Krzysztof Ciesielski - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (2):396-399.
  20. The point of Kant's axioms of intuition.Daniel Sutherland - 2005 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86 (1):135–159.
    Kant's Critique of Pure Reason makes important claims about space, time and mathematics in both the Transcendental Aesthetic and the Axioms of Intuition, claims that appear to overlap in some ways and contradict in others. Various interpretations have been offered to resolve these tensions; I argue for an interpretation that accords the Axioms of Intuition a more important role in explaining mathematical cognition than it is usually given. Appreciation for this larger role reveals that magnitudes are central to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  21. 100 years of Zermelo’s axiom of choice: what was the problem with it?Per Martin-Löf - 2006 - Computer Journal 49 (3):345–350.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  20
    The grounded Martin's axiom.Miha E. Habič - 2017 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 63 (5):437-453.
    We introduce a variant of Martin's axiom, called the grounded Martin's axiom, or math formula, which asserts that the universe is a c.c.c. forcing extension in which Martin's axiom holds for posets in the ground model. This principle already implies several of the combinatorial consequences of math formula. The new axiom is shown to be consistent with the failure of math formula and a singular continuum. We prove that math formula is preserved in a strong way when adding a Cohen (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  43
    Piron's axioms for quantum mechanics: A reply to Foulis and Randall. [REVIEW]N. Hadjisavvas & F. Thieffine - 1984 - Foundations of Physics 14 (1):83-88.
    In their paper “A note on Misunderstandings of Piron's Axioms for Quantum Mechanics,” Foulis and Randall undertake a reply to our critique of Piron's “question-proposition system” (qp-s) which appeared in previous issues of this journal. In the present paper, we want briefly to refute the points of criticism raised by Foulis and Randall (FR). We argue that the “misunderstandings” are not ours, and we prove it.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  70
    Strong analogues of Martin's axiom imply axiom R.Robert E. Beaudoin - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (1):216-218.
    We show that either PFA + or Martin's maximum implies Fleissner's Axiom R, a reflection principle for stationary subsets of P ℵ 1 (λ). In fact, the "plus version" (for one term denoting a stationary set) of Martin's axiom for countably closed partial orders implies Axiom R.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25. Relativizing the relativized a priori: Reichenbach’s axioms of coordination divided.Flavia Padovani - 2011 - Synthese 181 (1):41-62.
    In recent years, Reichenbach's 1920 conception of the principles of coordination has attracted increased attention after Michael Friedman's attempt to revive Reichenbach's idea of a "relativized a priori". This paper follows the origin and development of this idea in the framework of Reichenbach's distinction between the axioms of coordination and the axioms of connection. It suggests a further differentiation among the coordinating axioms and accordingly proposes a different account of Reichenbach's "relativized a priori".
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  26.  16
    A Note on Götlind's Axiom System for the Calculus of Propositions.R. K. P. Singh & R. Shukla - 1952 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 17 (1):66-67.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  40
    Provable forms of Martin's axiom.Gary P. Shannon - 1990 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 31 (3):382-388.
  28. Some weak fragments of Martin’s axiom related to the rectangle refining property.Teruyuki Yorioka - 2008 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 47 (1):79-90.
    We introduce the anti-rectangle refining property for forcing notions and investigate fragments of Martin’s axiom for ℵ1 dense sets related to the anti-rectangle refining property, which is close to some fragment of Martin’s axiom for ℵ1 dense sets related to the rectangle refining property, and prove that they are really weaker fragments.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29.  61
    Transitivity follows from Dummett's axiom.J. F. A. K. Van Benthem & W. J. Blok - 1978 - Theoria 44 (2):117-118.
  30.  53
    A note on misunderstandings of Piron's axioms for quantum mechanics.D. J. Foulis & C. H. Randall - 1984 - Foundations of Physics 14 (1):65-81.
    Piron's axioms for a realistically interpreted quantum mechanics are analyzed in detail within the context of a formal mathematical structure expressed in the conventional set-theoretic idiom of mathematics. As a result, some of the serious misconceptions that have encouraged recent criticisms of Piron's axioms are exposed.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  31.  44
    Independence of rose's axioms for m-valued implication.Ernest Edmonds - 1969 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (2):283-284.
    Rose has shown in [2] that the following axioms are sufficient, with modus ponens, for m-valued Łukasiewiczian implication.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  16
    Transitivity follows from Dummett's axiom.J. F. A. K. van Benthem - 1978 - Theoria 44 (2):117-118.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  33.  40
    Vico’s Axioms: The Geometry of the Human World.Angus S. Fletcher - 1996 - New Vico Studies 14:86-90.
  34.  49
    Is it always rational to satisfy Savage's axioms?Itzhak Gilboa, Andrew Postlewaite & David Schmeidler - 2009 - Economics and Philosophy 25 (3):285-296.
    This note argues that, under some circumstances, it is more rational not to behave in accordance with a Bayesian prior than to do so. The starting point is that in the absence of information, choosing a prior is arbitrary. If the prior is to have meaningful implications, it is more rational to admit that one does not have sufficient information to generate a prior than to pretend that one does. This suggests a view of rationality that requires a compromise between (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  35.  15
    Zermelo's Axiom of Choice: Its Origins, Development, and Influence by Gregory H. Moore. [REVIEW]Garrett Birkhof & William Aspray - 1984 - Isis 75:401-402.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  86
    Quantum Theory from Four of Hardy's Axioms.Rüdiger Schack - 2003 - Foundations of Physics 33 (10):1461-1468.
    In a recent paper [e-print quant-ph/0101012], Hardy has given a derivation of “quantum theory from five reasonable axioms.” Here we show that Hardy's first axiom, which identifies probability with limiting frequency in an ensemble, is not necessary for his derivation. By reformulating Hardy's assumptions, and modifying a part of his proof, in terms of Bayesian probabilities, we show that his work can be easily reconciled with a Bayesian interpretation of quantum probability.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  37.  66
    Gregory trees, the continuum, and Martin's axiom.Kenneth Kunen & Dilip Raghavan - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (2):712-720.
    We continue the investigation of Gregory trees and the Cantor Tree Property carried out by Hart and Kunen. We produce models of MA with the Continuum arbitrarily large in which there are Gregory trees, and in which there are no Gregory trees.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  13
    Consistent and inconsistent generalizations of Martin’s Axiom, weak square and weak Chang’s Conjecture.David Asperó & Nutt Tananimit - forthcoming - Journal of Mathematical Logic.
    We prove that the forcing axiom [Formula: see text] (stratified) implies [Formula: see text]. Using this implication, we show that the forcing axiom [Formula: see text] is inconsistent. We also derive weak Chang’s Conjecture from [Formula: see text] (stratified) and use this second implication to give another proof of the inconsistency of [Formula: see text].
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  99
    On Quine's axioms of quantification.George D. W. Berry - 1941 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 6 (1):23-27.
  40.  10
    A Note on Reichenbach's Axioms for Probability Implication.J. C. C. Mckinsey - 1940 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 5 (1):42-42.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  42
    The decidability of Hindley's axioms for strong reduction.Bruce Lercher - 1967 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 32 (2):237-239.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  38
    Vico’s Axioms[REVIEW]Andrea Battistini - 1996 - New Vico Studies 14:81-85.
  43.  29
    Who accepts Savage’s axiom now?Steven J. Humphrey & Nadia-Yasmine Kruse - 2023 - Theory and Decision 96 (1):1-17.
    We report the results of an experimental test of whether preaching the normative appeal of the sure-thing principle leads decision-makers to make choices that satisfy it. We use Allais-type decision problems to observe the incentive-compatible choices of 147 subjects, which either violate the sure-thing principle or adhere to it. Subjects are presented with normative arguments that support the counterfactual behaviour and then repeat their decisions. We observe violations of the sure-thing principle are robust to its normative justification. This result replicates (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  48
    Prior A. N.. Peirce's axioms for propositions calculus.Frederic B. Fitch - 1960 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 25 (1):87-87.
  45.  68
    A note on Leśniewski's axiom system for the mereological notion of ingredient or element.C. Lejewski - 1983 - Topoi 2 (1):63-71.
  46.  2
    Consistent and inconsistent generalizations of Martin’s Axiom, weak square and weak Chang’s Conjecture.David Asperó & Nutt Tananimit - forthcoming - Journal of Mathematical Logic.
    Journal of Mathematical Logic, Ahead of Print. We prove that the forcing axiom [math] (stratified) implies [math]. Using this implication, we show that the forcing axiom [math] is inconsistent. We also derive weak Chang’s Conjecture from [math] (stratified) and use this second implication to give another proof of the inconsistency of [math].
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  16
    (2 other versions)The Independence of Quine's Axioms $^ast 200$ and $^ast 201$.Barkley Rosser - 1941 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 6 (3):96-97.
  48.  85
    A correction to “A non-implication between fragments of Martin’s Axiom related to a property which comes from Aronszajn trees”.Teruyuki Yorioka - 2011 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 162 (9):752-754.
    In the paper A non-implication between fragments of Martin’s Axiom related to a property which comes from Aronszajn trees , Proposition 2.7 is not true. To avoid this error and correct Proposition 2.7, the definition of the property is changed. In Yorioka [1], all proofs of lemmas and theorems but Lemma 6.9 are valid about this definition without changing the proofs. We give a new statement and a new proof of Lemma 6.9.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49.  13
    An abbreviation of Croisot's axiom-system for distributive lattices with $I$.Bolesław Sobociński - 1972 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 13 (1):139-141.
  50.  58
    A semantical investigation into leśniewski's axiom of his ontology.Mitio Takano - 1985 - Studia Logica 44 (1):71 - 77.
    A structure A for the language L, which is the first-order language (without equality) whose only nonlogical symbol is the binary predicate symbol , is called a quasi -struoture iff (a) the universe A of A consists of sets and (b) a b is true in A ([p) a = {p } & p b] for every a and b in A, where a(b) is the name of a (b). A quasi -structure A is called an -structure iff (c) {p (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
1 — 50 / 966