Results for ' mathematical objectivity, mathematical structuralism, experimental epistemology, didactics of mathematics'

961 found
Order:
  1.  7
    Des modes d’objectivité dans l’apprentissage des mathématiques : le structuralisme mathématique à la lumière d’une épistémologie expérimentale.Thomas Hausberger - 2024 - Noesis 38:139-159.
    La présente étude questionne l’objectivité des mathématiques à travers l’analyse de la pratique mathématique, dans une modalité didactique. À travers des dialogues en classe (dans l’esprit de Lakatos), nous examinons la thèse, inspirée des travaux de Granger, que le développement de mathématiques formelles selon la méthode abstraite structuraliste ne se réduit pas à un langage mais engage un « contenu formel » qui se déploie dans une intuition symbolique. La didactique ou épistémologie expérimentale contribue ainsi à la philosophie par un (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  52
    Why Pragmaticism is Neither Mathematical Structuralism nor Fictionalism.AhtiVeikko Pietarinen - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 41:19-25.
    Despite some surface similarities, Charles Peirce’s philosophy of mathematics, pragmaticism, is incompatible with both mathematical structuralism and fictionalism. Pragmaticism has to do with experimentation and observation concerning the forms of relations in diagrammatic and iconic representations ofmathematical entities. It does not presuppose mathematical foundations although it has these representations as its objects of study. But these objects do have a reality which structuralism and fictionalism deny.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Structuralism's unpaid epistemological debts.Bob Hale - 1996 - Philosophia Mathematica 4 (2):124--47.
    One kind of structuralism holds that mathematics is about structures, conceived as a type of abstract entity. Another denies that it is about any distinctively mathematical entities at all—even abstract structures; rather it gives purely general information about what holds of any collection of entities conforming to the axioms of the theory. Of these, pure structuralism is most plausibly taken to enjoy significant advantages over platonism. But in what appears to be its most plausible—modalised—version, even restricted to elementary (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  4. Mathematical Thought and its Objects.Peter Smith - 2009 - Analysis 69 (3):549 - 557.
    Needless to say, Charles Parsons’s long awaited book1 is a must-read for anyone with an interest in the philosophy of mathematics. But as Parsons himself says, this has been a very long time in the writing. Its chapters extensively “draw on”, “incorporate material from”, “overlap considerably with”, or “are expanded versions of” papers published over the last twenty-five or so years. What we are reading is thus a multi-layered text with different passages added at different times. And this makes (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  21
    Lo strutturalismo scientifico. Matematica, Fisica e Biologia nell’ottica piagetiana.Francesco Crapanzano - 2019 - Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia 10 (2):208-223.
    Riassunto: Lo strutturalismo piagetiano, segnatamente quello in matematica, fisica e biologia alla luce dell’epistemologia genetica, rappresenta una declinazione peculiare e feconda dell’eterogeneo movimento strutturalista. Dopo una fortunata stagione, le strutture matematiche, rintracciate e indagate sotto diverse prospettive, hanno finito per costituire un “paradigma” didattico e di ricerca utilizzato su più livelli; in modo non dissimile, perché collegata alla matematica, la fisica ha considerato i propri “oggetti” dotati di una struttura: ma se originariamente era una struttura intesa in senso materiale, adesso (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  15
    What Is Structuralism? and Other Questions.Michael D. Resnik - 1997 - In Michael David Resnik, Mathematics as a science of patterns. New York ;: Oxford University Press.
    I explore the relation between structuralism and other theses that I have presented in the rest of the book, in particular, my holism, realism about mathematical objects, and the disquotational account of truth. In developing my theory, I have claimed that there is no fact of the matter as to whether the patterns that the various mathematical theories describe are themselves mathematical objects, so I first try to explain what the locution ‘there is no fact of the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  55
    How are Mathematical Objects Constituted? A Structuralist Answer.Wolfgang Spohn - unknown
    The paper proposes to amend structuralism in mathematics by saying what places in a structure and thus mathematical objects are. They are the objects of the canonical system realizing a categorical structure, where that canonical system is a minimal system in a specific essentialistic sense. It would thus be a basic ontological axiom that such a canonical system always exists. This way of conceiving mathematical objects is underscored by a defense of an essentialistic version of Leibniz’ principle (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8. Mathematical Structuralism.Geoffrey Hellman & Stewart Shapiro - 2018 - Cambridge University Press.
    The present work is a systematic study of five frameworks or perspectives articulating mathematical structuralism, whose core idea is that mathematics is concerned primarily with interrelations in abstraction from the nature of objects. The first two, set-theoretic and category-theoretic, arose within mathematics itself. After exposing a number of problems, the book considers three further perspectives formulated by logicians and philosophers of mathematics: sui generis, treating structures as abstract universals, modal, eliminating structures as objects in favor of (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  9.  48
    Structuralism and informal provability.Georg Schiemer & John Wigglesworth - 2023 - Synthese 202 (2):1-26.
    Mathematical structuralism can be understood as a theory of mathematical ontology, of the objects that mathematics is about. It can also be understood as a theory of the semantics for mathematical discourse, of how and to what mathematical terms refer. In this paper we propose an epistemological interpretation of mathematical structuralism. According to this interpretation, the main epistemological claim is that mathematical knowledge is purely structural in character; mathematical statements contain purely structural (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  48
    Mathematical structuralism and bundle theory.Bahram Assadian - 2024 - Ratio 37 (2-3):123-133.
    According to the realist rendering of mathematical structuralism, mathematical structures are ontologically prior to individual mathematical objects such as numbers and sets. Mathematical objects are merely positions in structures: their nature entirely consists in having the properties arising from the structure to which they belong. In this paper, I offer a bundle-theoretic account of this structuralist conception of mathematical objects: what we normally describe as an individual mathematical object is the mereological bundle of its (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Haecceities and Mathematical Structuralism.Christopher Menzel - 2018 - Philosophia Mathematica 26 (1):84-111.
    Recent work in the philosophy of mathematics has suggested that mathematical structuralism is not committed to a strong form of the Identity of Indiscernibles (II). José Bermúdez demurs, and argues that a strong form of II can be warranted on structuralist grounds by countenancing identity properties, or haecceities, as legitimately structural. Typically, structuralists dismiss such properties as obviously non-structural. I will argue to the contrary that haecceities can be viewed as structural but that this concession does not warrant (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12. Structuralism and the Applicability of Mathematics.Jairo José da Silva - 2010 - Global Philosophy 20 (2-3):229-253.
    In this paper I argue for the view that structuralism offers the best perspective for an acceptable account of the applicability of mathematics in the empirical sciences. Structuralism, as I understand it, is the view that mathematics is not the science of a particular type of objects, but of structural properties of arbitrary domains of entities, regardless of whether they are actually existing, merely presupposed or only intentionally intended.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13. Charles Parsons. Mathematical thought and its objects.John P. Burgess - 2008 - Philosophia Mathematica 16 (3):402-409.
    This long-awaited volume is a must-read for anyone with a serious interest in philosophy of mathematics. The book falls into two parts, with the primary focus of the first on ontology and structuralism, and the second on intuition and epistemology, though with many links between them. The style throughout involves unhurried examination from several points of view of each issue addressed, before reaching a guarded conclusion. A wealth of material is set before the reader along the way, but a (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  52
    Mathematical Structuralism and the Third Man.Michael Hand - 1993 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 23 (2):179 - 192.
    Plato himself would be pleased at the recent emergence of a certain highly Platonic variety of platonism concerning mathematics, viz., the structuralism of Michael Resnik and Stewart Shapiro. In fact, this species of platonism is so Platonic that it is susceptible to an objection closely related to one raised against Plato by Parmenides in the dialogue of that name. This is the Third Man Argument against a view about the relation of Forms to particulars. My objection is not a (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15. Foundations for Mathematical Structuralism.Uri Nodelman & Edward N. Zalta - 2014 - Mind 123 (489):39-78.
    We investigate the form of mathematical structuralism that acknowledges the existence of structures and their distinctive structural elements. This form of structuralism has been subject to criticisms recently, and our view is that the problems raised are resolved by proper, mathematics-free theoretical foundations. Starting with an axiomatic theory of abstract objects, we identify a mathematical structure as an abstract object encoding the truths of a mathematical theory. From such foundations, we derive consequences that address the main (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  16.  1
    Mathematical Structuralism and Purely Formal Theory.Marcin Czakon - 2020 - Analele Universitatii Din Craiova, Seria Filozofie (Issn: 1841-8325) 46 (2):117-134.
    In this paper we put a thesis that it is possible to perceive mathematics as a science of structures, where the difference between structure as the object of study and theory as something which describes this object is blurred. We discusses the view of set-theoretical structuralism with a special emphasis placed on a certain gradual development of set theory as a formal theory. We proposes a certain view concerning the methodology of formal sciences, which is an attempt at describing (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  65
    Reassessing the Epistemological Challenge to Mathematical Platonism.William J. Melanson - 2011 - Croatian Journal of Philosophy 11 (3):295-304.
    In his Realism, Mathematics, and Modality, Hartry Field attempted to revitalize the epistemological case against mathematical platontism by challenging mathematical platonists to explain how we could be epistemically reliable with regard to the abstract objects of mathematics. Field suggested that the seeming impossibility of providing such an explanation tends to undermine belief in the existence of abstract mathematical objects regardless of whatever reason we have for believing in their existence. After more than two decades, Field’s (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18. Objectivity in Mathematics, Without Mathematical Objects†.Markus Pantsar - 2021 - Philosophia Mathematica 29 (3):318-352.
    I identify two reasons for believing in the objectivity of mathematical knowledge: apparent objectivity and applications in science. Focusing on arithmetic, I analyze platonism and cognitive nativism in terms of explaining these two reasons. After establishing that both theories run into difficulties, I present an alternative epistemological account that combines the theoretical frameworks of enculturation and cumulative cultural evolution. I show that this account can explain why arithmetical knowledge appears to be objective and has scientific applications. Finally, I will (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  19. Bunge’s Mathematical Structuralism Is Not a Fiction.Jean-Pierre Marquis - 2019 - In Michael Robert Matthews, Mario Bunge: A Centenary Festschrift. Springer. pp. 587-608.
    In this paper, I explore Bunge’s fictionism in philosophy of mathematics. After an overview of Bunge’s views, in particular his mathematical structuralism, I argue that the comparison between mathematical objects and fictions ultimately fails. I then sketch a different ontology for mathematics, based on Thomasson’s metaphysical work. I conclude that mathematics deserves its own ontology, and that, in the end, much work remains to be done to clarify the various forms of dependence that are involved (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  52
    Self-reference: Theory and didactics between language and literature.Svend Erik Larsen - 2005 - Journal of Aesthetic Education 39 (1):13-30.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Self-Reference:Theory and Didactics between Language and LiteratureSvend Erik Larsen (bio)Semiotics of Self-ReferenceLiterary metafiction constitutes the extreme case of self-referential texts. Therefore we can either discard it as generally irrelevant for the understanding of the cultural functions of texts, or use it as a point of departure for the formulation of both general and basic aspects of such functions. The position taken in this essay will opt for the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Invariants and Mathematical Structuralism.Georg Schiemer - 2014 - Philosophia Mathematica 22 (1):70-107.
    The paper outlines a novel version of mathematical structuralism related to invariants. The main objective here is twofold: first, to present a formal theory of structures based on the structuralist methodology underlying work with invariants. Second, to show that the resulting framework allows one to model several typical operations in modern mathematical practice: the comparison of invariants in terms of their distinctive power, the bundling of incomparable invariants to increase their collective strength, as well as a heuristic principle (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  70
    Applying mathematics to empirical sciences: flashback to a puzzling disciplinary interaction.Raphaël Sandoz - 2018 - Synthese 195 (2):875-898.
    This paper aims to reassess the philosophical puzzle of the “applicability of mathematics to physical sciences” as a misunderstood disciplinary interplay. If the border isolating mathematics from the empirical world is based on appropriate criteria, how does one explain the fruitfulness of its systematic crossings in recent centuries? An analysis of the evolution of the criteria used to separate mathematics from experimental sciences will shed some light on this question. In this respect, we will highlight the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  60
    What has Chihara's mathematical nominalism gained over mathematical realism?Tomohiro Hoshi - unknown
    The indispensability argument, which claims that science requires beliefs in mathematical entities, gives a strong motivation for mathematical realism. However, mathematical realism bears Benacerrafian ontological and epistemological problems. Although recent accounts of mathematical realism have attempted to cope with these problems, it seems that, at least, a satisfactory account of epistemology of mathematics has not been presented. For instance, Maddy's realism with perceivable sets and Resnik's and Shapiro's structuralism have their own epistemological problems. This fact (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  62
    Category Theory and Mathematical Structuralism.Andrei Rodin - 2008 - Proceedings of the Xxii World Congress of Philosophy 41:37-40.
    Category theory doesn't support Mathematical Structuralism but suggests a new philosophical view on mathematics, which differs both from Structuralism and from traditional Substantialism about mathematical objects. While Structuralism implies thinking of mathematical objects up to isomorphism the new categorical view implies thinking up to general morphism.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Mathematical Explanation and Epistemology: Please Mind the Gap.Sam Baron - 2015 - Ratio 29 (2):149-167.
    This paper draws together two strands in the debate over the existence of mathematical objects. The first strand concerns the notion of extra-mathematical explanation: the explanation of physical facts, in part, by facts about mathematical objects. The second strand concerns the access problem for platonism: the problem of how to account for knowledge of mathematical objects. I argue for the following conditional: if there are extra-mathematical explanations, then the core thesis of the access problem is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26.  34
    Algorithmic rationality: Epistemology and efficiency in the data sciences.Ian Lowrie - 2017 - Big Data and Society 4 (1).
    Recently, philosophers and social scientists have turned their attention to the epistemological shifts provoked in established sciences by their incorporation of big data techniques. There has been less focus on the forms of epistemology proper to the investigation of algorithms themselves, understood as scientific objects in their own right. This article, based upon 12 months of ethnographic fieldwork with Russian data scientists, addresses this lack through an investigation of the specific forms of epistemic attention paid to algorithms by data scientists. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  27.  68
    Introduction to Special Issue: Foundations of Mathematical Structuralism.Georg Schiemer & John Wigglesworth - 2020 - Philosophia Mathematica 28 (3):291-295.
    Structuralism, the view that mathematics is the science of structures, can be characterized as a philosophical response to a general structural turn in modern mathematics. Structuralists aim to understand the ontological, epistemological, and semantical implications of this structural approach in mathematics. Theories of structuralism began to develop following the publication of Paul Benacerraf’s paper ‘What numbers could not be’ in 1965. These theories include non-eliminative approaches, formulated in a background ontology of sui generis structures, such as Stewart (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  27
    Kitcher’s Circumlocutionary Structuralism.Michael Hand - 1991 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (1):81-89.
    Philip Kitcher has proposed an account of mathematical truth which he hopes avoids platonistic commitment to abstract mathematical objects. His idea is that the truth-conditions of mathematical statements consist in certain general structural features of physical reality. He codifies these structural features by reference to various operations which are performable on objects: the world is structured in such a way that these operations are possible. Which operations are performable cannot be known a priori; rather, we hypothesize, conjecture, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Mathematical Intuition and Natural Numbers: A Critical Discussion.Felix Mühlhölzer - 2010 - Erkenntnis 73 (2):265-292.
    Charles Parsons’ book “Mathematical Thought and Its Objects” of 2008 (Cambridge University Press, New York) is critically discussed by concentrating on one of Parsons’ main themes: the role of intuition in our understanding of arithmetic (“intuition” in the specific sense of Kant and Hilbert). Parsons argues for a version of structuralism which is restricted by the condition that some paradigmatic structure should be presented that makes clear the actual existence of structures of the necessary sort. Parsons’ paradigmatic structure is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Structuralism and Meta-Mathematics.Simon Friederich - 2010 - Erkenntnis 73 (1):67 - 81.
    The debate on structuralism in the philosophy of mathematics has brought into focus a question about the status of meta-mathematics. It has been raised by Shapiro (2005), where he compares the ongoing discussion on structuralism in category theory to the Frege-Hilbert controversy on axiomatic systems. Shapiro outlines an answer according to which meta-mathematics is understood in structural terms and one according to which it is not. He finds both options viable and does not seem to prefer one (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  31.  26
    Ptolemaic Revolutions: Mathematical Objectivity in Jean Cavaillès and Gilles-Gaston Granger.Jean-Paul Cauvin - 2024 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 14 (2):397-434.
    I argue that Gilles-Gaston Granger (1920–2016) broadly incorporates the central affirmations of Jean Cavaillès’s (1903–44) philosophy of the concept into his own epistemological program. Cavaillès and Granger share three interrelated epistemological commitments: they claim (1) that mathematics has its own content and is therefore autonomous from and irreducible to logic, (2) that conceptual transformations in the history of mathematics can only be explained by an internal dialectic of concepts, and (3) that the objectivity of mathematics is an (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Remarks on the structuralistic epistemology of mathematics* Izabela bondecka-krzykowska and Roman Murawski.Izabela Bondecka-Krzykowska - 2006 - Logique Et Analyse 49:31-41.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Logical structuralism and Benacerraf’s problem.Audrey Yap - 2009 - Synthese 171 (1):157-173.
    There are two general questions which many views in the philosophy of mathematics can be seen as addressing: what are mathematical objects, and how do we have knowledge of them? Naturally, the answers given to these questions are linked, since whatever account we give of how we have knowledge of mathematical objects surely has to take into account what sorts of things we claim they are; conversely, whatever account we give of the nature of mathematical objects (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  34.  33
    Understanding mathematical texts: a hermeneutical approach.Merlin Carl - 2022 - Synthese 200 (6):1–31.
    The work done so far on the understanding of mathematical (proof) texts focuses mostly on logical and heuristical aspects; a proof text is considered to be understood when the reader is able to justify inferential steps occurring in it, to defend it against objections, to give an account of the “main ideas”, to transfer the proof idea to other contexts etc. (see, e.g., Avigad in The philosophy of mathematical practice, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2008). In contrast, there is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  15
    Introduction.Michael D. Resnik - 1997 - In Michael David Resnik, Mathematics as a science of patterns. New York ;: Oxford University Press.
    Mathematics has often been described as the ‘Queen of Sciences’, yet philosophical problems arise as soon as one tries to define its subject matter. Anti‐realism concerning mathematical objects has proven to be problematic, but, on the other hand, realism gives rise to well‐known epistemological problems. In this book, I offer a type of mathematical realism according to which mathematical objects exist independently of our constructions, and mathematical truths are obtained independently of our beliefs. Central to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. The structuralist view of mathematical objects.Charles Parsons - 1990 - Synthese 84 (3):303 - 346.
  37.  28
    (1 other version)Problematic Objects between Mathematics and Mechanics.Emily R. Grosholz - 1990 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1990:385 - 395.
    The existence of mathematical objects may be explained in terms of their occurrence in problems. Especially interesting problems arise at the overlap of domains, and the items that intervene in them are hybrids sharing the characteristics of both domains in an ambiguous way. Euclid's geometry, and Leibniz' work at the intersection of geometry, algebra and mechanics in the late seventeenth century, provide instructive examples of such problems and items. The complex and yet still formal unity of these items calls (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Truth as a Mathematical Object DOI:10.5007/1808-1711.2010v14n1p31.Jean-Yves Béziau - 2010 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 14 (1):31-46.
    In this paper we discuss in which sense truth is considered as a mathematical object in propositional logic. After clarifying how this concept is used in classical logic, through the notions of truth-table, truth-function and bivaluation, we examine some generalizations of it in non-classical logics: many-valued matrix semantics with three and four values, non-truth-functional bivalent semantics, Kripke possible world semantics. • DOI:10.5007/1808-1711.2010v14n1p31.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  64
    Is mathematical knowledge a precedent for modal knowledge?: A novel objection to Lewis’s modal epistemology.Joungbin Lim - 2018 - SATS 19 (2):183-199.
    The goal of this paper is to raise a novel objection to Lewis’s modal realist epistemology. After reformulating his modal epistemology, I shall argue that his view that we have necessary knowledge of the existence of counterparts ends up with an absurdity. Specifically, his analogy between mathematical knowledge and modal knowledge leads to an unpleasant conclusion that one’s counterpart exists in all possible worlds. My argument shows that if Lewis’s modal realism is true, we cannot know what is possible. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Mathematical Thought and its Objects.Charles Parsons - 2007 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Charles Parsons examines the notion of object, with the aim to navigate between nominalism, denying that distinctively mathematical objects exist, and forms of Platonism that postulate a transcendent realm of such objects. He introduces the central mathematical notion of structure and defends a version of the structuralist view of mathematical objects, according to which their existence is relative to a structure and they have no more of a 'nature' than that confers on them. Parsons also analyzes the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  41. A logico-mathematic, structural methodology. Part II: Experimental design and epistemological issues.Robert E. Haskell - 2003 - Journal of Mind and Behavior 24 (3-4):401-422.
    In this first of two companion papers to a logico-mathematic, structural methodology , a meta-level analysis of the non metric structure is presented in relation to critiques based on standard experimental, statistical, and computational methods of contemporary psychology and cognitive science. The concept of a non metric methodology is examined as it relates to the epistemological and scientific goals of experimental, statistical, and computational methods. While sharing in these goals, differences and similarities between the two methodological approaches are (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Structuralism, mathematical.Geoffrey Hellman - unknown
    Structuralism is a view about the subject matter of mathematics according to which what matters are structural relationships in abstraction from the intrinsic nature of the related objects. Mathematics is seen as the free exploration of structural possibilities, primarily through creative concept formation, postulation, and deduction. The items making up any particular system exemplifying the structure in question are of no importance; all that matters is that they satisfy certain general conditions—typically spelled out in axioms defining the structure (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  44
    Structuralism and Mathematical Practice in Felix Klein’s Work on Non-Euclidean Geometry†.Biagioli Francesca - 2020 - Philosophia Mathematica 28 (3):360-384.
    It is well known that Felix Klein took a decisive step in investigating the invariants of transformation groups. However, less attention has been given to Klein’s considerations on the epistemological implications of his work on geometry. This paper proposes an interpretation of Klein’s view as a form of mathematical structuralism, according to which the study of mathematical structures provides the basis for a better understanding of how mathematical research and practice develop.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  90
    Counterpossibles in science: an experimental study.Brian McLoone, Cassandra Grützner & Michael T. Stuart - 2023 - Synthese 201 (1):1-20.
    A counterpossible is a counterfactual whose antecedent is impossible. The vacuity thesis says all counterpossibles are true solely because their antecedents are impossible. Recently, some have rejected the vacuity thesis by citing purported non-vacuous counterpossibles in science. One limitation of this work, however, is that it is not grounded in experimental data. Do scientists actually reason non-vacuously about counterpossibles? If so, what is their basis for doing so? We presented biologists (N = 86) with two counterfactual formulations of a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45.  47
    Logic, Epistemology, and Scientific Theories – From Peano to the Vienna Circle.Paola Cantù & Georg Schiemer (eds.) - 2023 - Springer Nature Switzerland.
    This book provides a collection of chapters on the development of scientific philosophy and symbolic logic in the early twentieth century. The turn of the last century was a key transitional period for the development of symbolic logic and scientific philosophy. The Peano school, the editorial board of the Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale, and the members of the Vienna Circle are generally mentioned as champions of this transformation of the role of logic in mathematics and in the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. The Structuralist Mathematical Style: Bourbaki as a case study.Jean-Pierre Marquis - 2022 - In Claudio Ternullo Gianluigi Oliveri, Boston Studies in the Philosophy and the History of Science. pp. 199-231.
    In this paper, we look at Bourbaki’s work as a case study for the notion of mathematical style. We argue that indeed Bourbaki exemplifies a mathematical style, namely the structuralist style.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Analytic epistemology and experimental philosophy.Joshua Alexander & Jonathan M. Weinberg - 2006 - Philosophy Compass 2 (1):56–80.
    It has been standard philosophical practice in analytic philosophy to employ intuitions generated in response to thought-experiments as evidence in the evaluation of philosophical claims. In part as a response to this practice, an exciting new movement—experimental philosophy—has recently emerged. This movement is unified behind both a common methodology and a common aim: the application of methods of experimental psychology to the study of the nature of intuitions. In this paper, we will introduce two different views concerning the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   191 citations  
  48. Realistic structuralism's identity crisis: A hybrid solution.Tim Button - 2006 - Analysis 66 (3):216–222.
    Keränen (2001) raises an argument against realistic (ante rem) structuralism: where a mathematical structure has a non-trivial automorphism, distinct indiscernible positions within the structure cannot be shown to be non-identical using only the properties and relations of that structure. Ladyman (2005) responds by allowing our identity criterion to include 'irreflexive two-place relations'. I note that this does not solve the problem for structures with indistinguishable positions, i.e. positions that have all the same properties as each other and exactly the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  49. Experimental Mathematics.Alan Baker - 2008 - Erkenntnis 68 (3):331-344.
    The rise of the field of “ experimental mathematics” poses an apparent challenge to traditional philosophical accounts of mathematics as an a priori, non-empirical endeavor. This paper surveys different attempts to characterize experimental mathematics. One suggestion is that experimental mathematics makes essential use of electronic computers. A second suggestion is that experimental mathematics involves support being gathered for an hypothesis which is inductive rather than deductive. Each of these options turns out (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  50. Ernst Cassirer’s Substanzbegriff und Funktionsbegriff.Jeremy Heis - 2014 - Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 4 (2):241-70.
    Ernst Cassirer’s book Substanzbegriff und Funktionsbegriff is a difficult book for contemporary readers to understand. Its topic, the theory of concept formation, engages with debates and authors that are largely unknown today. And its “historical” style violates the philosophical standards of clarity first propounded by early analytic philosophers. Cassirer, for instance, never says explicitly what he means by “substance-concept” and “function-concept.” In this article, I answer three questions: Why did Cassirer choose to focus on the topic of concept formation? What (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
1 — 50 / 961