Results for ' supercompact cardinal'

967 found
Order:
  1. Supercompact cardinals, trees of normal ultrafilters, and the partition property.Julius B. Barbanel - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):701-708.
    Suppose κ is a supercompact cardinal. It is known that for every λ ≥ κ, many normal ultrafilters on P κ (λ) have the partition property. It is also known that certain large cardinal assumptions imply the existence of normal ultrafilters without the partition property. In [1], we introduced the tree T of normal ultrafilters associated with κ. We investigate the distribution throughout T of normal ultrafilters with and normal ultrafilters without the partition property.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  36
    Reflection in Second-Order Set Theory with Abundant Urelements Bi-Interprets a Supercompact Cardinal.Joel David Hamkins & Bokai Yao - 2024 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 89 (3):1007-1043.
    After reviewing various natural bi-interpretations in urelement set theory, including second-order set theories with urelements, we explore the strength of second-order reflection in these contexts. Ultimately, we prove, second-order reflection with the abundant atom axiom is bi-interpretable and hence also equiconsistent with the existence of a supercompact cardinal. The proof relies on a reflection characterization of supercompactness, namely, a cardinal κ is supercompact if and only if every Π11 sentence true in a structure M (of any (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  31
    Supercompact cardinals and trees of normal ultrafilters.Julius B. Barbanel - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (1):89-109.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  66
    Some structural results concerning supercompact cardinals.Arthur Apter - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (4):1919-1927.
    We show how the forcing of [5] can be iterated so as to get a model containing supercompact cardinals in which every measurable cardinal δ is δ + supercompact. We then apply this iteration to prove three additional theorems concerning the structure of the class of supercompact cardinals.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5.  31
    Supercompact cardinals, elementary embeddings and fixed points.Julius B. Barbanel - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (1):84-88.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  54
    Forcing axioms, supercompact cardinals, singular cardinal combinatorics.Matteo Viale - 2008 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 14 (1):99-113.
    The purpose of this communication is to present some recent advances on the consequences that forcing axioms and large cardinals have on the combinatorics of singular cardinals. I will introduce a few examples of problems in singular cardinal combinatorics which can be fruitfully attacked using ideas and techniques coming from the theory of forcing axioms and then translate the results so obtained in suitable large cardinals properties.The first example I will treat is the proof that the proper forcing axiom (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  66
    On a combinatorial property of Menas related to the partition property for measures on supercompact cardinals.Kenneth Kunen & Donald H. Pelletier - 1983 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (2):475-481.
    T. K. Menas [4, pp. 225-234] introduced a combinatorial property χ (μ) of a measure μ on a supercompact cardinal κ and proved that measures with this property also have the partition property. We prove here that Menas' property is not equivalent to the partition property. We also show that if α is the least cardinal greater than κ such that P κ α bears a measure without the partition property, then α is inaccessible and Π 2 (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  8.  21
    The HOD Hypothesis and a supercompact cardinal.Yong Cheng - 2017 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 63 (5):462-472.
    In this paper, we prove that: if κ is supercompact and the math formula Hypothesis holds, then there is a proper class of regular cardinals in math formula which are measurable in math formula. Woodin also proved this result independently [11]. As a corollary, we prove Woodin's Local Universality Theorem. This work shows that under the assumption of the math formula Hypothesis and supercompact cardinals, large cardinals in math formula are reflected to be large cardinals in math formula (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  35
    Supercompactness and measurable limits of strong cardinals II: Applications to level by level equivalence.Arthur W. Apter - 2006 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 52 (5):457-463.
    We construct models for the level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness in which for κ the least supercompact cardinal and δ ≤ κ any cardinal which is either a strong cardinal or a measurable limit of strong cardinals, 2δ > δ+ and δ is < 2δ supercompact. In these models, the structure of the class of supercompact cardinals can be arbitrary, and the size of the power set of κ can essentially (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10.  55
    Telis K. Menas. A combinatorial property of pkλ. The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 41 , pp. 225–234. - Donald H. Pelletier. The partition property for certain extendible measures on supercompact cardinals. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 81 , pp. 607–612. - Kenneth Kunen and Donald H. Pelletier. On a combinatorial property of Menas related to the partition property for measures on supercompact cardinals. The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 48 , pp. 475–481. - Julius B. Barbanel. Supercompact cardinals, trees of normal ultrafilters, and the partition property. The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 51 , pp. 701–708. [REVIEW]Carlos Di Prisco - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (3):1098.
    Reviewed Works:Telis K. Menas, A Combinatorial Property of $p_\kappa\lambda$.Donald H. Pelletier, The Partition Property for Certain Extendible Measures on Supercompact Cardinals.Kenneth Kunen, Donald H. Pelletier, On a Combinatorial Property of Menas Related to the Partition Property for Measures on Supercompact Cardinals.Julius B. Barbanel, Supercompact Cardinals, Trees of Normal Ultrafilters, and the Partition Property.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  45
    The κ-closed unbounded Filter and supercompact cardinals.Mitchell Spector - 1981 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (1):31-40.
  12.  24
    Indestructible Weakly Compact Cardinals and the Necessity of Supercompactness for Certain Proof Schemata.J. D. Hamkins & A. W. Apter - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (4):563-572.
    We show that if the weak compactness of a cardinal is made indestructible by means of any preparatory forcing of a certain general type, including any forcing naively resembling the Laver preparation, then the cardinal was originally supercompact. We then apply this theorem to show that the hypothesis of supercompactness is necessary for certain proof schemata.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  13.  29
    The large cardinals between supercompact and almost-huge.Norman Lewis Perlmutter - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (3-4):257-289.
    I analyze the hierarchy of large cardinals between a supercompact cardinal and an almost-huge cardinal. Many of these cardinals are defined by modifying the definition of a high-jump cardinal. A high-jump cardinal is defined as the critical point of an elementary embedding j:V→M\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}j:VM{j: V \to M}\end{document} such that M is closed under sequences of length sup{j|f:κ→κ}\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\sup\{{j\,|\,f: \kappa \to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  14.  46
    The least weakly compact cardinal can be unfoldable, weakly measurable and nearly θ{\theta} θ -supercompact.Brent Cody, Moti Gitik, Joel David Hamkins & Jason A. Schanker - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (5-6):491-510.
    We prove from suitable large cardinal hypotheses that the least weakly compact cardinal can be unfoldable, weakly measurable and even nearly θ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}θ{\theta}\end{document}-supercompact, for any desired θ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}θ{\theta}\end{document}. In addition, we prove several global results showing how the entire class of weakly compactcardinals, a proper class, can be made to coincide with the class of unfoldable cardinals, with the class of weakly (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  57
    Donald A. Martin and John R. Steel. Projective determinacy. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, vol. 85 , pp. 6582–6586. - W. Hugh Woodin. Supercompact cardinals, sets of reals, and weakly homogeneous trees. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, vol. 85 , pp. 6587–6591. - Donald A. Martin and John R. Steel. A proof of projective determinacy. Journal of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 2 , pp. 71–125. [REVIEW]Matthew D. Foreman - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (3):1132-1136.
  16.  28
    Indestructibility and measurable cardinals with few and many measures.Arthur W. Apter - 2008 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 47 (2):101-110.
    If κ < λ are such that κ is indestructibly supercompact and λ is measurable, then we show that both A = {δ < κ | δ is a measurable cardinal which is not a limit of measurable cardinals and δ carries the maximal number of normal measures} and B = {δ < κ | δ is a measurable cardinal which is not a limit of measurable cardinals and δ carries fewer than the maximal number of normal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  17.  63
    Supercompactness and Measurable Limits of Strong Cardinals.Arthur W. Apter - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (2):629-639.
    In this paper, two theorems concerning measurable limits of strong cardinals and supercompactness are proven. This generalizes earlier work, both individual and joint with Shelah.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18.  63
    Supercompactness and level by level equivalence are compatible with indestructibility for strong compactness.Arthur W. Apter - 2007 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 46 (3-4):155-163.
    It is known that if $\kappa < \lambda$ are such that κ is indestructibly supercompact and λ is 2λ supercompact, then level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness fails. We prove a theorem which points towards this result being best possible. Specifically, we show that relative to the existence of a supercompact cardinal, there is a model for level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness containing a supercompact cardinal κ in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19. Exactly controlling the non-supercompact strongly compact cardinals.Arthur W. Apter & Joel David Hamkins - 2003 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 68 (2):669-688.
    We summarize the known methods of producing a non-supercompact strongly compact cardinal and describe some new variants. Our Main Theorem shows how to apply these methods to many cardinals simultaneously and exactly control which cardinals are supercompact and which are only strongly compact in a forcing extension. Depending upon the method, the surviving non-supercompact strongly compact cardinals can be strong cardinals, have trivial Mitchell rank or even contain a club disjoint from the set of measurable cardinals. (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  20.  30
    Universal indestructibility for degrees of supercompactness and strongly compact cardinals.Arthur W. Apter & Grigor Sargsyan - 2008 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 47 (2):133-142.
    We establish two theorems concerning strongly compact cardinals and universal indestructibility for degrees of supercompactness. In the first theorem, we show that universal indestructibility for degrees of supercompactness in the presence of a strongly compact cardinal is consistent with the existence of a proper class of measurable cardinals. In the second theorem, we show that universal indestructibility for degrees of supercompactness is consistent in the presence of two non-supercompact strongly compact cardinals, each of which exhibits a significant amount (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  36
    Consecutive Singular Cardinals and the Continuum Function.Arthur W. Apter & Brent Cody - 2013 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 54 (2):125-136.
    We show that from a supercompact cardinal $\kappa$, there is a forcing extension $V[G]$ that has a symmetric inner model $N$ in which $\mathrm {ZF}+\lnot\mathrm {AC}$ holds, $\kappa$ and $\kappa^{+}$ are both singular, and the continuum function at $\kappa$ can be precisely controlled, in the sense that the final model contains a sequence of distinct subsets of $\kappa$ of length equal to any predetermined ordinal. We also show that the above situation can be collapsed to obtain a model (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22. Inner models with large cardinal features usually obtained by forcing.Arthur W. Apter, Victoria Gitman & Joel David Hamkins - 2012 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 51 (3-4):257-283.
    We construct a variety of inner models exhibiting features usually obtained by forcing over universes with large cardinals. For example, if there is a supercompact cardinal, then there is an inner model with a Laver indestructible supercompact cardinal. If there is a supercompact cardinal, then there is an inner model with a supercompact cardinal κ for which 2κ = κ+, another for which 2κ = κ++ and another in which the least strongly (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  23.  40
    Inaccessible Cardinals, Failures of GCH, and Level-by-Level Equivalence.Arthur W. Apter - 2014 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 55 (4):431-444.
    We construct models for the level-by-level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness containing failures of the Generalized Continuum Hypothesis at inaccessible cardinals. In one of these models, no cardinal is supercompact up to an inaccessible cardinal, and for every inaccessible cardinal $\delta $, $2^{\delta }\gt \delta ^{++}$. In another of these models, no cardinal is supercompact up to an inaccessible cardinal, and the only inaccessible cardinals at which GCH holds are also measurable. These (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24.  30
    Strongly compact cardinals and ordinal definability.Gabriel Goldberg - 2023 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 24 (1).
    This paper explores several topics related to Woodin’s HOD conjecture. We improve the large cardinal hypothesis of Woodin’s HOD dichotomy theorem from an extendible cardinal to a strongly compact cardinal. We show that assuming there is a strongly compact cardinal and the HOD hypothesis holds, there is no elementary embedding from HOD to HOD, settling a question of Woodin. We show that the HOD hypothesis is equivalent to a uniqueness property of elementary embeddings of levels of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  29
    (1 other version)More on the Least Strongly Compact Cardinal.Arthur W. Apter - 1997 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 43 (3):427-430.
    We show that it is consistent, relative to a supercompact limit of supercompact cardinals, for the least strongly compact cardinal k to be both the least measurable cardinal and to be > 2k supercompact.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  26.  30
    More on HOD-supercompactness.Arthur W. Apter, Shoshana Friedman & Gunter Fuchs - 2021 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 172 (3):102901.
    We explore Woodin's Universality Theorem and consider to what extent large cardinal properties are transferred into HOD (and other inner models). We also separate the concepts of supercompactness, supercompactness in HOD and being HOD-supercompact. For example, we produce a model where a proper class of supercompact cardinals are not HOD-supercompact but are supercompact in HOD. Additionally we introduce a way to measure the degree of HOD-supercompactness of a supercompact cardinal, and we develop methods (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  36
    An L-like model containing very large cardinals.Arthur W. Apter & James Cummings - 2008 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 47 (1):65-78.
    We force and construct a model in which level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness holds, along with a strong form of diamond and a version of square consistent with supercompactness. This generalises a result due to the first author. There are no restrictions in our model on the structure of the class of supercompact cardinals.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  29
    A Cardinal Pattern Inspired by AD.Arthur W. Apter - 1996 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 42 (1):211-218.
    Assuming Con, a model in which there are unboundedly many regular cardinals below Θ and in which the only regular cardinals below Θ are limit cardinals was previously constructed. Using a large cardinal hypothesis far beyond Con, we construct in this paper a model in which there is a proper class of regular cardinals and in which the only regular cardinals in the universe are limit cardinals.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29.  30
    Removing Laver functions from supercompactness arguments.Arthur W. Apter - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (2):154.
    We show how the use of a Laver function in the proof of the consistency, relative to the existence of a supercompact cardinal, of both the Proper Forcing Axiom and the Semiproper Forcing Axiom can be eliminated via the use of lottery sums of the appropriate partial orderings.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  20
    Subcompact Cardinals, Type Omission, and Ladder Systems.Yair Hayut & Menachem Magidor - 2022 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 87 (3):1111-1129.
    We provide a model theoretical and tree property-like characterization of $\lambda $ - $\Pi ^1_1$ -subcompactness and supercompactness. We explore the behavior of these combinatorial principles at accessible cardinals.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31.  64
    Large cardinals and locally defined well-orders of the universe.David Asperó & Sy-David Friedman - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 157 (1):1-15.
    By forcing over a model of with a class-sized partial order preserving this theory we produce a model in which there is a locally defined well-order of the universe; that is, one whose restriction to all levels H is a well-order of H definable over the structure H, by a parameter-free formula. Further, this forcing construction preserves all supercompact cardinals as well as all instances of regular local supercompactness. It is also possible to define variants of this construction which, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  32. Strong Cardinals can be Fully Laver Indestructible.Arthur W. Apter - 2002 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 48 (4):499-507.
    We prove three theorems which show that it is relatively consistent for any strong cardinal κ to be fully Laver indestructible under κ-directed closed forcing.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  33.  39
    Failure of GCH and the level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness.Arthur W. Apter - 2003 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 49 (6):587.
    We force and obtain three models in which level by level equivalence between strong compactness and supercompactness holds and in which, below the least supercompact cardinal, GCH fails unboundedly often. In two of these models, GCH fails on a set having measure 1 with respect to certain canonical measures. There are no restrictions in all of our models on the structure of the class of supercompact cardinals.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  34. C(n)-cardinals.Joan Bagaria - 2012 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 51 (3-4):213-240.
    For each natural number n, let C(n) be the closed and unbounded proper class of ordinals α such that Vα is a Σn elementary substructure of V. We say that κ is a C(n)-cardinal if it is the critical point of an elementary embedding j : V → M, M transitive, with j(κ) in C(n). By analyzing the notion of C(n)-cardinal at various levels of the usual hierarchy of large cardinal principles we show that, starting at the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  35.  43
    Indestructibility, measurability, and degrees of supercompactness.Arthur W. Apter - 2012 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 58 (1):75-82.
    Suppose that κ is indestructibly supercompact and there is a measurable cardinal λ > κ. It then follows that A1 = {δ < κ∣δ is measurable, δ is not a limit of measurable cardinals, and δ is not δ+ supercompact} is unbounded in κ. If in addition λ is 2λ supercompact, then A2 = {δ < κ∣δ is measurable, δ is not a limit of measurable cardinals, and δ is δ+ supercompact} is unbounded in κ (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  36.  26
    Strong compactness and the ultrapower axiom I: the least strongly compact cardinal.Gabriel Goldberg - 2022 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 22 (2).
    Journal of Mathematical Logic, Volume 22, Issue 02, August 2022. The Ultrapower Axiom is a combinatorial principle concerning the structure of large cardinals that is true in all known canonical inner models of set theory. A longstanding test question for inner model theory is the equiconsistency of strongly compact and supercompact cardinals. In this paper, it is shown that under the Ultrapower Axiom, the least strongly compact cardinal is supercompact. A number of stronger results are established, setting (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  16
    Two-Cardinal Derived Topologies, Indescribability and Ramseyness.Brent Cody, Chris Lambie-Hanson & Jing Zhang - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-29.
    We introduce a natural two-cardinal version of Bagaria’s sequence of derived topologies on ordinals. We prove that for our sequence of two-cardinal derived topologies, limit points of sets can be characterized in terms of a new iterated form of pairwise simultaneous reflection of certain kinds of stationary sets, the first few instances of which are often equivalent to notions related to strong stationarity, which has been studied previously in the context of strongly normal ideals. The non-discreteness of these (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  34
    Indestructibility and destructible measurable cardinals.Arthur W. Apter - 2016 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 55 (1-2):3-18.
    Say that κ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}κ{\kappa}\end{document}’s measurability is destructible if there exists a κ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}κ{\kappa}\end{document}. It then follows that A1={δ<κ∣δ\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}A1={δ<κδ{A_{1} = \{\delta < \kappa \mid \delta}\end{document} is measurable, δ is not a limit of measurable cardinals, δ is not δ+ strongly compact, and δ’s measurability is destructible when forcing with partial orderings having rank below λδ} is unbounded (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  84
    Large cardinals and large dilators.Andy Lewis - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (4):1496-1510.
    Applying Woodin's non-stationary tower notion of forcing, I prove that the existence of a supercompact cardinal κ in V and a Ramsey dilator in some small forcing extension V[G] implies the existence in V of a measurable dilator of size κ, measurable by κ-complete measures.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  75
    Small forcing makes any cardinal superdestructible.Joel Hamkins - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (1):51-58.
    Small forcing always ruins the indestructibility of an indestructible supercompact cardinal. In fact, after small forcing, any cardinal κ becomes superdestructible--any further <κ--closed forcing which adds a subset to κ will destroy the measurability, even the weak compactness, of κ. Nevertheless, after small forcing indestructible cardinals remain resurrectible, but never strongly resurrectible.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  41.  47
    Aronszajn trees and failure of the singular cardinal hypothesis.Itay Neeman - 2009 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 9 (1):139-157.
    The tree property at κ+ states that there are no Aronszajn trees on κ+, or, equivalently, that every κ+ tree has a cofinal branch. For singular strong limit cardinals κ, there is tension between the tree property at κ+ and failure of the singular cardinal hypothesis at κ; the former is typically the result of the presence of strongly compact cardinals in the background, and the latter is impossible above strongly compacts. In this paper, we reconcile the two. We (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  42.  49
    Identity crises and strong compactness : II. Strong cardinals.Arthur W. Apter & James Cummings - 2001 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 40 (1):25-38.
    . From a proper class of supercompact cardinals, we force and obtain a model in which the proper classes of strongly compact and strong cardinals precisely coincide. In this model, it is the case that no strongly compact cardinal \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document} $\kappa$\end{document} is \documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document} $2^\kappa = \kappa^+$\end{document} supercompact.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  43.  44
    The failure of GCH at a degree of supercompactness.Brent Cody - 2012 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 58 (1):83-94.
    We determine the large cardinal consistency strength of the existence of a λ-supercompact cardinal κ such that equation image fails at λ. Indeed, we show that the existence of a λ-supercompact cardinal κ such that 2λ ≥ θ is equiconsistent with the existence of a λ-supercompact cardinal that is also θ-tall. We also prove some basic facts about the large cardinal notion of tallness with closure.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  60
    Easton’s theorem in the presence of Woodin cardinals.Brent Cody - 2013 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 52 (5-6):569-591.
    Under the assumption that δ is a Woodin cardinal and GCH holds, I show that if F is any class function from the regular cardinals to the cardinals such that (1) ${\kappa < {\rm cf}(F(\kappa))}$ , (2) ${\kappa < \lambda}$ implies ${F(\kappa) \leq F(\lambda)}$ , and (3) δ is closed under F, then there is a cofinality-preserving forcing extension in which 2 γ = F(γ) for each regular cardinal γ < δ, and in which δ remains Woodin. Unlike (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45.  53
    Patterns of compact cardinals.Arthur W. Apter - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 89 (2-3):101-115.
    We show relative to strong hypotheses that patterns of compact cardinals in the universe, where a compact cardinal is one which is either strongly compact or supercompact, can be virtually arbitrary. Specifically, we prove if V “ZFC + Ω is the least inaccessible limit of measurable limits of supercompact cardinals + ƒ : Ω → 2 is a function”, then there is a partial ordering P V so that for , There is a proper class of compact (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  46.  36
    Strong tree properties for small cardinals.Laura Fontanella - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (1):317-333.
    An inaccessible cardinal $\kappa$ is supercompact when $(\kappa, \lambda)$-ITP holds for all $\lambda\geq \kappa$. We prove that if there is a model of ZFC with infinitely many supercompact cardinals, then there is a model of ZFC where for every $n\geq 2$ and $\mu\geq \aleph_n$, we have $(\aleph_n, \mu)$-ITP.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  47.  75
    Making all cardinals almost Ramsey.Arthur W. Apter & Peter Koepke - 2008 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 47 (7-8):769-783.
    We examine combinatorial aspects and consistency strength properties of almost Ramsey cardinals. Without the Axiom of Choice, successor cardinals may be almost Ramsey. From fairly mild supercompactness assumptions, we construct a model of ZF + ${\neg {\rm AC}_\omega}$ in which every infinite cardinal is almost Ramsey. Core model arguments show that strong assumptions are necessary. Without successors of singular cardinals, we can weaken this to an equiconsistency of the following theories: “ZFC + There is a proper class of regular (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48.  19
    N-Berkeley cardinals and weak extender models.Raffaella Cutolo - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (2):809-816.
    For a given inner model N of ZFC, one can consider the relativized version of Berkeley cardinals in the context of ZFC, and ask if there can exist an “N-Berkeley cardinal.” In this article we provide a positive answer to this question. Indeed, under the assumption of a supercompact cardinal $\delta $, we show that there exists a ZFC inner model N such that there is a cardinal which is N-Berkeley, even in a strong sense. Further, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  69
    Identity crises and strong compactness III: Woodin cardinals. [REVIEW]Arthur W. Apter & Grigor Sargsyan - 2006 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 45 (3):307-322.
    We show that it is consistent, relative to n ∈ ω supercompact cardinals, for the strongly compact and measurable Woodin cardinals to coincide precisely. In particular, it is consistent for the first n strongly compact cardinals to be the first n measurable Woodin cardinals, with no cardinal above the n th strongly compact cardinal being measurable. In addition, we show that it is consistent, relative to a proper class of supercompact cardinals, for the strongly compact cardinals (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50.  18
    The first omitting cardinal for Magidority.Shimon Garti & Yair Hayut - 2019 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 65 (1):95-104.
    An infinite cardinal λ is Magidor if and only if. It is known that if λ is Magidor then for some, and the first such α is denoted by. In this paper we try to understand some of the properties of. We prove that can be the successor of a supercompact cardinal, when λ is a Magidor cardinal. From this result we obtain the consistency of being a successor of a singular cardinal with uncountable cofinality.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 967