Results for 'God’s name'

976 found
Order:
  1.  71
    On God’s Names and Attributes.Mohamad Nasrin Nasir - 2009 - Journal of Islamic Philosophy 5:59-74.
    This article examines ḥikma as it was practiced by Ṣadr al-Dīn Shīrāzī, or Mullā Ṣadrā (d. 1640), in explaining the connection between the divine names and the attributes of God. This is done via a translation of the fourth part of his al-Maẓāhir al-ilāhiyya fī asrār al-ʿulūm al-kamāliyya [The loci of divine manifestations in the secrets of the knowledge of perfection]. Ḥikma, philosophy, as it is defined here, is the combination of rational demonstrations and spiritual unveiling. Shīrāzī’s philosophy is a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  39
    Gathered in God's Name: New Horizons in Australian Religious Life, Carmel Leavey and Rosalie O'Neill.Terence Veling - forthcoming - The Australasian Catholic Record.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  14
    The (Im)possibility of God’s Name. Levinas, Derrida, Marion.Alice De Rochechouart - 2020 - Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 76 (2-3):639-660.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4. Rahasia Asmaul Husna (Ibn Arabi: The Secret of God's Names).Zainul Maarif - 2015 - Jakarta, Indonesia: Turos Pustaka.
    This is a book on a positive theology according to Ibn Arabi: a Spain Muslim mystics, His theology is a cure for an atheist. You will find from this book that belief in God is not alienation.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  39
    What’s in God’s name: literary forerunners and philosophical allies of the imjaslavie debate. [REVIEW]Nel Grillaert - 2012 - Studies in East European Thought 64 (3-4):163-181.
    The aim of this paper is to explore the interaction between a tradition that belongs originally to the realm of orthodox contemplative monasticism (i.e., hesychasm) and nineteenth-and early twentieth-century Russian intellectuals. In the first part, this paper will explore how hesychasm gradually penetrated nineteenthcentury secular culture; a special focus will be on the hermitage of Optina Pustyn' and its renowned elders, as well as their appeal to members of the Optina-intelligentsia, especially Fëdor Dostoevskij. Then, attention will shift to the imjaslavie (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  15
    Naming God’s presence in preaching.Gerrit Immink - 2019 - HTS Theological Studies 75 (4):1-7.
    Does preaching bring God on stage? Protestants assume an intimate relationship between the ‘Word of God’ and preaching. However, the principle that ‘preaching of the Word of God is the Word of God’ caused intense debates about the status of God language. The author highlights the classic disputes of the 19th and 20th centuries and argues that the old dilemma must be overcome. Sermons address the subjective-contextual conditions of the listeners, and this in no way precludes the attention for divine (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Missional Worship, Worshipful Mission: Gathering as God’s People, Going Out in God’s Name.[author unknown] - 2014
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  28
    Abbād b. Sulaymān’s Emphasis of Divine Trancendence: God’s Names and Attributes.Abdulkerim İskender Sarica - 2020 - Kader 18 (2):539-569.
    Muʻtazilite thinkers put forward the first systematic ideas for the relationship of essence and attributes, one of the most fundamental and complicated issues of Islamic theology, and comprehensive explanations to the question of God’s names. Although almost all the thinkers agreed on uṣūl al-khamsa, they differed in their approach to the principle of unity (tawḥīd). ‘Abbād b. Sulaymān, who lived in the period when these approaches emerged, is a scholar who reveals his distinctive view of God’s names and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  13
    Hospitality and Islam: Welcoming in God's Name.Mona Siddiqui - 2015 - Yale University Press.
    _A groundbreaking examination of a crucial concept in Islamic thought and tradition from an author noted for her work on interfaith and intercultural dialogue_ Considering its prominent role in many faith traditions, surprisingly little has been written about hospitality within the context of religion, particularly Islam. In her new book, Mona Siddiqui, a well-known media commentator, makes the first major contribution to the understanding of hospitality both within Islam and beyond. She explores and compares teachings within the various Muslim traditions (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  15
    Hospitality and Islam: Welcoming in God’s Name. By MonaSiddiqui. Pp. 274. New Haven/London, Yale University Press, 2015, $38.00. [REVIEW]Michelle Rebidoux - 2019 - Heythrop Journal 60 (3):518-519.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Christ is God's middle name.Edward Seccomb Fox - 1971 - Garden City, N.Y.,: Doubleday. Edited by Elizabeth H. Fox.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  6
    God's Triune Life: Engaging Thomas Joseph White's Recent Study.Christophe Chalamet - 2024 - Nova et Vetera 22 (2):475-491.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:God's Triune Life:Engaging Thomas Joseph White's Recent StudyChristophe Chalamet"Deus, ut nos in sobrietate contineat, parce de sua essentia disserit."1At almost seven-hundred pages, Thomas Joseph White's book is an impressive achievement in size and scope, and one of the persons who endorsed the book, Rowan Williams, accurately describes it as "encyclopedic." There are repetitions in it, but these are not easy to avoid in a book that includes a number (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  26
    God’s Knowledge: A Study on The Idea of Al-Ghazālī And Maimonides.Özcan Akdağ - 2018 - Cumhuriyet İlahiyat Dergisi 22 (1):9-32.
    Whether God has a knowledge is a controversial issue both philosophy and theology. Does God have a knowledge? If He has, does He know the particulars? When we assume that God knows particulars, is there any change in God’s essence? In the theistic tradition, it is accepted that God is wholly perfect, omniscience, omnipotent and wholly good. Therefore, it is not possible to say that there is a change in God. Because changing is a kind of imperfection. On (...) knowledge, another controversial issue is whether God knows particulars or not. Most of theist thinkers argued that God is wholly perfect; because of perfectness, He must have perfect attributes. Knowing and goodness are a kind of perfect attributes. Ignoring and evil are a kind of imperfectness. If God is perfect being, He should have the perfect attributes and must know the particulars. For me in this subject, there are some similarities between al-Ghazālī and Maimonides. In this study I took into consideration the idea of al-Ghazālī and Maimonides on this subject. Based on Griffel and Stroumsa’s argument, I tried to show similarity between al-Ghazālī and Maimonides on God’s knowledge. Summary: Whether God has a knowledge is a controversial issue both philosophy and theology. Does God have a knowledge? If He has, does He know the particulars? When we assume that God knows particulars, is there any change in God’s essence? In this study I took into consideration the idea of al-Ghazālī and Maimonides on this subject. Based on Griffel’s and Stroumsa’s arguments, I tried to show similarity between al-Ghazālī and Maimonides on God’s knowledge.In the theistic tradition, it is accepted that God is wholly perfect, omniscience, omnipotent and wholly good. Therefore, it is not possible to say that there is a change in God because changing is a kind of imperfection. On God’s knowledge, another controversial issue is whether God knows particulars or not. Most of theist thinkers argued that God is wholly perfect; because of perfectness, He must have perfect attributes. Knowing and goodness are a kind of perfect attributes. Ignoring and evil are kinds of imperfectness. If God is perfect being, He should have the perfect attributes and must know the particulars. Based on God’s immutability, some thinkers argued that God does not knows particulars. Particulars occurs due to the matter. Matter and its functions are continually changing. Therefore, to know the particulars requires changing in God’s essence. If God is the most perfect being, it is impossible that He is subject to affection. Thus, God does not know the particulars. Other thinkers, like Avicenna, argued that God knows the particulars as a universal way. For example, God knows only humanity and He cannot know Zayd as a particular person. al-Ghazālī criticizes Avicenna’s idea in Tahafut al-Falasifa (The Incoherence of the Philosophers) and argues that God is a perfect being and He should know particulars as a particulars. For al-Ghazālī, God should know everything, and His knowledge is different from our knowledge. In order to explain this matter, he says in Ninety-Nine Names of God;“But this can be understood only through an example. Perhaps you have seen the clock which informs one of the hour of worship. If you have not seen it, then, generally speaking, (it is constructed in this manner). There must be a mechanism in the form of a cylinder which contains a known amount of water. There must also be another hollow mechanism which is placed within the cylinder (but) above the water, and a string which has one of its ends tied to this hollow mechanism. The other end is tied to the part of a small container which is placed above the hollow cylinder. In (this container) there is a ball. Under the ball there is another bowl (placed) in such a manner that if the ball drops will fall into the bowl, and its jingle will be heard. Then the bottom of the cylindrical mechanism must be pierced to a determined extent so that the water can escape through it little by little…. All of this can be determined by a determination of the extent of cause which neither increases nor decreases. It is possible to make the falling of the ball into the bowl a cause of another action and this other action a cause of a third action, and to continue this process indefinitely so that from it are generated remarkable and predetermined movements (actions) of circumscribed extent. The first cause was the falling of the water in a determined quantity…. All of that happens in a determined quantity and to a determined extent which causes the determination of all of it by (adding at this point) the determination of the first movement which is the movement of the water. When you understand that these mechanisms are the principles from which movements must result, and that the movement must be determined if the result is to be regulated, then certainly that which has been determined must proceed from them….Even as the movement of the mechanism, the string, and the ball are not external to the will of the inventor of the mechanism -on the contrary, that is what He willed when He invented the mechanism- so also all the events which occur in the world, both the evil and the good and the beneficial and harmful, are not external to the will of God Most High. Rather (all of) that is the intention of God Most High for the sake of which He has planned its causes.” For Maimonides, as in al-Ghazālī, God is a perfect being and He must have the perfect attributes. Because of knowing is a perfect attribute, He should know everything, and His knowledge is different from human knowledge. In order to explain the difference between God’s knowledge and human knowledge Maimonides gives a parable in The Guide of the Perplexed. “Suppose a thing is produced in accordance with the knowledge of the producer, the producer was then guided by his knowledge in the act of producing the thing. Other people, however, who examine this work and acquire a knowledge of the whole of it, depend for that knowledge on the work itself. An artisan makes a box in which weights move with the running of the water, and thus indicate how many hours have passed of the day and of the night. The whole quantity of the water that is to run out, the different ways in which it runs, every thread that is drawn, and every little ball that descends -all this is fully perceived by him who makes the clock; and his knowledge is not the result of observing the movements as they are actually going on; but, on the contrary, the movements are produced in accordance with his knowledge. But another person who looks at that instrument will receive fresh knowledge at every movement he perceives; the longer he looks on, the more knowledge does he acquire; he will gradually increase his knowledge till he fully understands the machinery…Our knowledge is acquired and increased in proportion to the things known by us. This is not the case with God. His knowledge of things is not derived from the things themselves; if this were the case, there would be change and plurality in His knowledge…” As can be seen from above, when Maimonides is explaining the difference of God’s and human knowledge, he uses the same example what al-Ghazālī used. Even though Maimonides does not mention al-Ghazālī’s name in his works, it could be seen that there are a lot of similarities between al-Ghazālī’s and Maimonides’s ideas. Based on Griffel and Stroumsa’s argument, in this paper, I tried to show that there is a similarity between al-Ghazālī’s and Maimonides’s ideas on God’s knowledge. In my opinion, therefore, in the formation of Maimonides’s thought, as he thanks to Muslim philosophers like al-Farābī, Avicenna and Averroes, he also thanks to al-Ghazālī. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  25
    Naming the God beyond names: Wisdom from the tradition on the old problem of God‐language.Mark S. Burrows & Dr Mark S. Burrows - 1993 - Modern Theology 9 (1):37-53.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  57
    God’s Place in Philosophy (Non in philosophia recurrere est ad deum).Nicholas Rescher - 2000 - Philosophy and Theology 12 (1):95-105.
    (1) Diametrically opposed standpoints can be maintained regarding God’s place in philosophy, namely that God has a central place here and, contrariwise, that philosophers should do their explanatory work without recourse to God. (2) The distinction between theistic and naturalistic issues is crucial here, because (3) the naturalistic sphere is substantially secular in orientation and is, in general, explanatorily closed. (4) A recourse to theistic considerations is not in order in the naturalistic domain insofar as the issues are local (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  24
    Theodicy, God´s pathos and the Crucified in the Cross´ theology by Jürgen Moltmann. A contemporary reading.Heyner Hernández-Díaz - 2018 - Veritas: Revista de Filosofía y Teología 40:121-144.
    Resumen En este estudio se pretende hacer una lectura contemporánea de tres categorías centrales en el pensamiento del teólogo alemán Jürgen Moltmann, a saber: la teodicea, el pathos de Dios y el Crucificado. Inicialmente, se presentan los principales autores relacionados con la teología de la cruz para así enmarcar históricamente la pregunta por Dios ante el sufrimiento humano y la consecuente interpretación de la cruz de Cristo como escenario trinitario en el que se manifiesta la pasión de Dios, ambos, pregunta (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  79
    The Name of God and the Linguistic Theory of the Kabbala: (Part 2).G. Scholem & S. Pleasance - 1972 - Diogenes 20 (80):164-194.
    The linguistic theory of the Kabbala, as it is explained in the writings of the Kabbalists of the 13th century—or at least basically implied in them—comes to rest upon a combination of the above-mentioned interpretations of the Book of Yetsira with the doctrine of the Name of God as a basis of that language. What is essentially new in this is the way in which the scope and range of a divine language—as understood by the Kabbalists—is brought into unique (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18.  24
    Bonhoeffer: God’s Conspirator in a State of Exception.Petra Brown - 2019 - Cham: Springer Verlag.
    Theologian. Conspirator. Martyr. Saint. Dietrich Bonhoeffer was killed in the waning days of World War II, having been implicated in the July 20th assassination attempt on Hitler. Since his death, Bonhoeffer’s life and writings have inspired contradictory responses. He is often seen as a model for Christian pacifist resistance, and more recently for violent direct political action. Bonhoeffer’s name has been invoked by violent anti-abortion protestors as well as political leaders calling for support on a ‘war on terror’ in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19.  54
    God's Simplicity, Evolution and the Origin of Embodied Human Consciousness.Scott Ventureyra - 2016 - Maritain Studies/Etudes Maritainiennes 32 (1):137-154.
    In this paper, I will argue that the best explanation for the origin of embodied human consciousness is grounded in God as understood through the doctrine of divine simplicity. First, I will present a modern expression of Aquinas’ understanding of divine simplicity. I will focus on one of Aquinas’ main contentions, namely, the impossibility that God possesses any spatial or temporal parts. Second, I will offer a modern version of a cosmological argument that will fortify the doctrine of divine simplicity (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  34
    32 Naming God’s Essence: Ineffability, Analogy and Set Theory.Claudio Ternullo - 2024 - In Mirosław Szatkowski (ed.), Ontology of Divinity. Boston: De Gruyter. pp. 697-718.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  11
    Lowalangi: From the name of an ethnic religious figure to the name of God.Sonny E. Zaluchu - 2021 - HTS Theological Studies 77 (4):6.
    This article shows the success of local cultural adaptation strategies in communicating the gospel to people of the Nias ethnicity in North Sumatra, Indonesia. This adaptation is the name Lowalangi, the name of the god of the pre-Christian era, to become the name of God, the creator and saviour of the world incarnated in the person of Jesus Christ. As a result, the use of this name was not limited to a translation process. Still, the whole (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  7
    Language and Myth: A Contribution to the Problem of the Names of the Gods.S. G. Lofts & Ernst Cassirer - 2013 - In The Warburg Years : Essays on Language, Art, Myth, and Technology. New Haven: Yale University Press. pp. 130-213.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  16
    "One Nation under God" Or Taking the Lord's Name in Vain?Grace Y. Kao - 2007 - Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 27 (1):183-204.
    BY EXPLORING THE ONGOING CONTROVERSY WHETHER TEACHER-LED recitation of the Pledge of Allegiance in public schools is constitutional, this paper demonstrates how and why Christians have much to gain from reverting the pledge to its pre-1954 text. I expose critical weaknesses in recent strategies to retain the contested words "under God" in the pledge employed by litigants, amici curiae, several Supreme Court justices, and other interested parties. I additionally interrogate the prominent place the American flag holds in public life and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  15
    God(s) Many and One: On Polytheism and Monotheism.William Desmond - 2008 - In God and the Between. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 171–190.
    This chapter contains section titled: Gods Religious Imagination and Porosity to Archaic Manifestation Sacred Namings and the Hyperboles of Being Naming the Agapeic God From Polytheism to Monotheism Metaxological Monotheism The Praise of Paganism.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  6
    God(s) Gnostic: On Passing through the Counterfeit Doubles of the Divine.William Desmond - 2008 - In God and the Between. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 205–224.
    This chapter contains section titled: Gnosticism and Religious Plurivocity Divinities Doubled Below and Above Gnostic Equivocity and the Fourfold Naming The Equivocal World as a Counterfeit Double? Passing Beyond the Counterfeit Doubles Agonistics: Divine and Human Doubling Back, Backing Out— Reversing Release Gnosticism and Metaxology: On Saving Knowing in the Equivocal Matrix.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  38
    In the name of God: How children and adults judge agents who act for religious versus secular reasons.Larisa Heiphetz, Elizabeth S. Spelke & Liane L. Young - 2015 - Cognition 144 (C):134-149.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  11
    The Question of God’s Existence: Partial Evidence, Disagreement and Intellectual Humility.Juliomar Marques Silva - 2024 - Dissertatio 59:150-167.
    In this article, I begin by arguing that justification of religious beliefs can involve at least two types of defeaters, namely partial evidence and peer disagreements. Belief in the existence (or nonexistence) of God, for example, is based on partial evidence. The body of evidence for this question is huge. No one is apt to consider all information and all arguments about the topic. In topics like this we have only partial evidence. Besides, there is persistent disagreement on the question (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  14
    God’s City: ‘Civic Humanism’ and the Self-Construction of the Ecclesia in Late Fifteenth- and Early Sixteenth-Century England.David Rundle - 2021 - Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes 84 (1):97-121.
    This article considers one element within the long tradition of the church’s self-identification as a city. It focuses on England, c. 1450 to c. 1510, and considers how the civic rhetoric developed by Italian humanists, pre-eminently Leonardo Bruni, was refracted through an ecclesiastical lens and so appropriated for English clerical use. It describes how two useful elements were quarried from recent writings imported from Italy: the first was the emphasis on the city and its buildings as a locus of virtue; (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  61
    Kierkegaard on Names, Concepts, and Proofs for God's Existence.John H. Whittaker - 1979 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 10 (2):117 - 129.
  30.  75
    What more in the name of God?: Theologies and theodicies of faith healing.Courtney S. Campbell - 2010 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 20 (1):pp. 1-25.
    The recent deaths of two children from parental decisions to rely on faith healing rather than medical treatment raises fundamental questions about the extent and limits of religious liberty in a liberal democratic society. This essay seeks to identify and critically examine three central issues internal to the ethics of religious communities that engage in faith healing regarding children: (1) the various forms of religious and nonreligious justification for faith healing; (2) the moral, institutional, or metaphysical wrong of medical practice (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  83
    On grounding God's knowledge of the probable.Jennifer Jensen - 2013 - Religious Studies 49 (1):65-83.
    A common objection to the Molinist account of divine providence states that counterfactuals of creaturely freedom lack grounds. Some Molinists appeal to brute counterfactual facts about the subject of the CCF in order to ground CCFs. Others argue that CCFs are grounded by the subject's actions in nearby worlds. In this article, I argue that Open Theism's account of divine providence employs would-probably conditionals that are most plausibly grounded by either brute facts about the subject of these conditionals or non-actual (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  18
    Naming God: Addressing the Divine in Philosophy, Theology and Scripture. By Janet Soskice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2023. Pp. ix, 247–256. £30.00. [REVIEW]S. J. Matthew Dunch - 2024 - Heythrop Journal 65 (3):330-331.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Is God's Belief Requirement Rational?Greg Janzen - 2011 - Religious Studies 47 (4):465-478.
    This paper sketches an evidential atheological argument that can be answered only if one of the central tenets of some theistic traditions is rejected, namely, that (propositional) belief in God is a necessary condition for salvation. The basic structure of the argument is as follows. Under theism, God is essentially omniscient, but no one can be both omniscient and irrational. So, if there is reason to hold that God is irrational, then it would follow that God doesn’t exist. And there (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34.  23
    Powerless? Modelling God’s Acting in the World in Eschatological Terms.Lisanne Teuchert - 2019 - Neue Zeitschrift für Systematicsche Theologie Und Religionsphilosophie 61 (3):316-332.
    This essay deals with the fundamental problem in which the doctrine of providence, that is God’s acting in nature, history and individual life, is still stuck: the dilemma of theism or deism, God’s superiority or powerlessness. I introduce an eschatological perspective to find alternative approaches to power. I name six concrete modes of action, four of them drawn from different authors and theories such as Romano Guardini, Open Theism and Christian Link. Two more are developed out of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Could God's purpose be the source of life's meaning?Thaddeus Metz - 2000 - Religious Studies 36 (3):293-313.
    In this paper, I explore the traditional religious account of what can make a life meaningful, namely, the view that one's life acquires significance insofar as one fulfils a purpose God has assigned. Call this view ‘purpose theory’. In the literature, there are objections purporting to show that purpose theory entails the logical absurdities that God is not moral, omnipotent, or eternal. I show that there are versions of purpose theory which are not vulnerable to these reductio arguments. However, I (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  36.  54
    (1 other version)Spinoza’s Theophany - The Expression of God’s Nature by Particular Things.Alexander Douglas - 2023 - Journal of Early Modern Studies 11 (2):49-69.
    What does Spinoza mean when he claims, as he does several times in the Ethics, that particular things are expressions of God’s nature or attributes? This article interprets these claims as a version of what is called theophany in the Neoplatonist tradition. Theophany is the process by which particular things come to exist as determinate manifestations of a divine nature that is in itself not determinate. Spinoza’s understanding of theophany diverges significantly from that of the Neoplatonist John Scottus Eriugena, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37. Tradition: God's future, our past, and the challenge of the present.Richard Lennan - 2017 - The Australasian Catholic Record 94 (1):14.
    Lennan, Richard Among courses that I teach is one entitled simply 'Tradition'. A standard response from colleagues and students when they hear the name of the course is to quote, perhaps even sing, the opening chorus from Fiddler on the Roof. While conclusions drawn from such a small sample are not necessarily definitive, it may be that the lyrics from Fiddler on the Roof encapsulate perfectly the perception of 'tradition' that prevails in our culture and church.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Gift, Spirit, and Being: God's Love in the Metaphysics of C. Bruaire.Antonio Lopez - 2002 - Dissertation, Boston College
    In the concept of "gift," some contemporary thinkers perceive the possibility for a renewal of philosophical and theological reflection. The Parisian philosopher Claude Bruaire innovately proposes to understand "gift" ontologically rather than phenomenologically or sociologically. The purpose of this dissertation is to explore Bruaire's ontology of gift , while testing its ability to elaborate an adequate interpretation of the essence of finite and infinite spirit. ;Bruaire views gift and being as coextensive for two reasons. First, he interprets being in terms (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  7
    Aquinas on God’s Knowledge of Future Contingents.William Lane Craig - 1990 - The Thomist 54 (1):33-79.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:AQUINAS ON GOD'S KNOWLEDGE OF FUTURE CONTINGENTS WILLIAM LANE CRAIG Oatholio University of Louvain Louvain, Belgium IF A THEOLOGICAL fatalist is someone who believes that God's foreknowledge of future events is incompatible with contingency and human freedom, then Thomas Aquinas was a theological fatalist. Unlike Augustine, Boethius, and Anselm, he did not believe that one could accept that God foreknows future events and yet adhere to the contingency of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  25
    How to expect God’s reign to come: From Jesus’ through the ecclesial to the cosmic body.Jakub Urbaniak & Elijah Otu - 2016 - HTS Theological Studies 72 (4):1-11.
    This study seeks to articulate the universality of the eschatological expectation, in its specifically Christian form, by interpreting it from the perspective of a radical embodiment. This can be understood in a twofold manner. Firstly, the mysterious reality of the eschatological reign of God is rooted in – and thus can be more adequately grasped through the lens of – Jesus’ own body seen as distinct yet not separate from his risen body and, mutatis mutandis, from his extended body, both (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  36
    A Long Way to God's Mutability: A Response to Ebrahim Azadegan.Amirhossein Zadyousefi - 2023 - Philosophy East and West 73 (1):166-188.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:A Long Way to God's Mutability:A Response to Ebrahim AzadeganAmirhossein Zadyousefi (bio)I. IntroductionIn his "On the Incompatibility of God's Knowledge of Particulars and the Doctrine of Divine Immutability: Towards a Reform in Islamic Theology" (2020, 2022) Ebrahim Azadegan tries to make room for what he calls a reform in Islamic theology. Affirming that God's knowledge of particulars is inconsistent with God's immutability, Azadegan puts forward a theory of God's (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  16
    The Asymptote of Love: From Mundane to Religious to God's Love.James Kellenberger - 2018 - SUNY Press.
    Discusses the complexities and paradoxes of love as represented in the history of Western philosophy and Christianity. In The Asymptote of Love, James Kellenberger develops a theory of religious love that resists essentialist definitions of the term and brings into conversation historical debates on love in Western philosophy and Christian theology. He argues that if love can be likened to a mathematical asymptote, which is a straight line that infinitely approaches a curve but never quite reaches it, then the asymptote (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  14
    Besorat Hageulah: The Gospel of atonement in metanarrative justice and God’s love.Wahyoe R. Wulandari, Ivan Th J. Weismann, Robi Panggarra, Hengki Wijaya & Daniel Ronda - 2023 - HTS Theological Studies 79 (1):9.
    There are three main types of atonement, namely the ‘classic’ type where Christ is a Victor, the ‘Latin’ type where Christ is satisfaction and the type of ‘humanism’ in which God is Love. These three types contain language of violence. However, the most striking language of violence is the ‘Latin’ type, where God is seen as the Angry one, who is thirsty for blood and asking to be satisfied. The sacrifice of redemption is seen as the idea of ‘bribe to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. God of Many Names. [REVIEW]Robert S. J. Garland - 1994 - Ancient Philosophy 14 (1):200-201.
  45.  12
    A critique of J.S. Sanni’s argument on the role of religion in promoting silence and extortion in contemporary African (Nigerian) society using the name of God.Anthony Chimankpam Ojimba - 2024 - Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions 13 (1):27-46.
    This study examines J.S. Sanni’s argument on the role of religion in promoting silence and extortion in contemporary African (Nigerian) society, leveraging on the name of God, with a view to determining the strengths and weaknesses of this argument. Sanni posits that religion (Christianity and Islam) have played crucial roles in promoting silence and extortion in Africa, with particular reference to Nigeria. He argues that the colonial debris of disempowerment, injustices, manipulation and extortion, using the instrumentality of religion, are (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. The Universe, the ‘body’ of God. About the vibration of matter to God’s command or The theory of divine leverages into matter.Tudor Cosmin Ciocan - 2016 - Dialogo 3 (1):226-254.
    The link between seen and unseen, matter and spirit, flesh and soul was always presumed, but never clarified enough, leaving room for debates and mostly controversies between the scientific domains and theologies of a different type; how could God, who is immaterial, have created the material world? Therefore, the logic of obtaining a result on this concern is first to see how religions have always seen the ratio between divinity and matter/universe. In this part, the idea of a world personality (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  21
    Mystical Foundations of Politics? Luther on God’s Presence and the Place of Human Beings.Martin Wendte - 2018 - Studies in Christian Ethics 31 (4):422-434.
    This article opens up a dialogue between two strands of Luther research, which until now have had limited contact: a German strand interested in the influence of Luther’s mystical education on his Reformation theology, and a German and Anglo-American strand concerned with Luther’s doctrine of the three estates and understanding of politics, emphasising in particular God’s constant activity in our daily life. This article has a twofold aim: first, to undertake a historical reconstruction of the influence of mysticism on (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Skeptheism: Is Knowledge of God’s Existence Possible?Moti Mizrahi - 2017 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 9 (1):41-64.
    In this paper, I sketch an argument for the view that we cannot know (or have good reasons to believe) that God exists. Some call this view “strong agnosticism” but I prefer the term “skeptheism” in order to clearly distinguish between two distinct epistemic attitudes with respect to the existence of God, namely, agnosticism and skepticism. For the skeptheist, we cannot know (or have good reasons to believe) that God exists, since there can be neither conceptual (a priori) nor empirical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. The local problem of God’s hiddenness: a critique of van Inwagen’s criterion of philosophical success. [REVIEW]Jennifer L. Soerensen - 2013 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 74 (3):297-314.
    In regards to the problem of evil, van Inwagen thinks there are two arguments from evil which require different defenses. These are the global argument from evil—that there exists evil in general, and the local argument from evil—that there exists some particular atrocious evil X. However, van Inwagen fails to consider whether the problem of God’s hiddenness also has a “local” version: whether there is in fact a “local” argument from God’s hiddenness which would be undefeated by his (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50. Aquinas's Two Concepts of Analogy and a Complex Semantics for Naming the Simple God.Joshua Hochschild - 2019 - The Thomist 83 (2):155-184.
    This paper makes two main arguments. First, that to understand analogy in St. Thomas Aquinas, one must distinguish two logically distinct concepts he inherited from Aristotle: one a kind of likeness between things, the other a kind of relation between linguistic functions. Second, that analogy (in both of these senses) plays a relatively small role in Aquinas's treatment of divine naming, compared to the realist semantic framework in which questions about divine naming are formulated and resolved, and on which the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 976