Results for 'Naturalist philosophy of science'

956 found
Order:
  1.  77
    The Radical Naturalism of Naturalistic Philosophy of Science.Joseph Rouse - 2023 - Topoi 42 (3):719-732.
    Naturalism in the philosophy of science has proceeded differently than the familiar forms of meta-philosophical naturalism in other sub-fields, taking its cues from “science as we know it” (Cartwright in The Dappled World, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1999, p. 1) rather than from a philosophical conception of “the Scientific Image.” Its primary focus is scientific practice, and its philosophical analyses are complementary and accountable to empirical studies of scientific work. I argue that naturalistic philosophy of (...) is nevertheless criterial for other versions of meta-philosophical naturalism; relying on a conflicting conception of scientific understanding would constitute a “first philosophy” imposed on the sciences. Moreover, naturalistic philosophy of science provides the basis for a “radically” naturalistic alternative to the familiar forms of orthodox or liberal naturalism. Goodman, Sellars and Hempel had previously challenged empiricist scruples against causal connections or nomological necessity by arguing that scientific concepts already had modal import. The radical naturalism I defend similarly challenges meta-philosophical naturalists’ conception of the Scientific Image as anormative, and instead shows how the normativity of scientific understanding in practice is a scientifically intelligible natural phenomenon. This account then provides a basis for naturalistic reflection on how other practices and normative concerns fit together with the best scientific understanding of human ways of life. (shrink)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  15
    The pragmatic turn in naturalist philosophy of science.Miriam Solomon - 1995 - Perspectives on Science 3 (2):206-230.
    Creative approaches in recent work in science studies can be usefully connected with ideas from the pragmatic tradition. This article both criticizes and builds on the contemporary pragmatic views of Hacking, Stich, and others. It selects a theme from the work of James and Dewey as a heuristic for a new, and necessary, pragmatic epistemology of science.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3. The future of naturalistic philosophy of science.Werner Callebaut - 1995 - Ludus Vitalis 3:19-52.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  60
    Philosophy of Science Naturalized? Some Problems with Giere's Naturalism.Harvey Siegel - 1989 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 20 (3):365.
    The main thesis is that the study of science must itself be a science. the only viable philosophy of science is a naturalized philosophy of science.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  5.  53
    (1 other version)The normative issue in naturalistic philosophy of science.Werner Callebaut - 1995 - Theoria 10 (1):101-116.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. The golden age of philosophy of science 1945 to 2000: logical reconstructionism, descriptivism, normative naturalism and foundationalism.John Losee - 2019 - London, UK: Bloomsbury Academic.
    The Golden Age of Philosophy of Science, 1945 to 2000 offers the reader a guide to the major philosophical approaches to science since World War Two. Considering the bases, arguments and conclusions of the four main movements - Naturalism, Descriptivism, Foundationalism, and Logical Reconstructionism - John P. Losee explores how philosophy has both shaped and expanded our understanding of science. The volume features major figures of twentieth century science, and engages with the work of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. Constructing a Philosophy of Science of Cognitive Science.William Bechtel - 2009 - Topics in Cognitive Science 1 (3):548-569.
    Philosophy of science is positioned to make distinctive contributions to cognitive science by providing perspective on its conceptual foundations and by advancing normative recommendations. The philosophy of science I embrace is naturalistic in that it is grounded in the study of actual science. Focusing on explanation, I describe the recent development of a mechanistic philosophy of science from which I draw three normative consequences for cognitive science. First, insofar as cognitive mechanisms (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  8. (1 other version)Philosophy of Science.Stathos Psillos - unknown
    Philosophy of science emerged as a distinctive part of philosophy in the twentieth century. It set its own agenda, the systematic study of the metaphysical and epistemological foundations of science, and acquired its own professional structure, departments and journals. Its defining moment was the meeting (and the clash) of two courses of events: the breakdown of the Kantian philosophical tradition and the crisis in the sciences and mathematics in the beginning of the century. The emergence of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  32
    Taking the Naturalistic Turn, or How Real Philosophy of Science is Done.Werner Callebaut (ed.) - 1993 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    Philosophers of science traditionally have ignored the details of scientific research, and the result has often been theories that lack relevance either to science or to philosophy in general. In this volume, leading philosophers of biology discuss the limitations of this tradition and the advantages of the "naturalistic turn"—the idea that the study of science is itself a scientific enterprise and should be conducted accordingly. This innovative book presents candid, informal debates among scholars who examine the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  10.  19
    20th Century Philosophy of Science in Focus: The Golden Age of Philosophy of Science 1945 to 2000: Logical Reconstructionism, Descriptivism, Normative Naturalism, and Foundationalism, by John Losee, London, Bloomsbury, 2019, 328 pp., ISBN: 9781350071513, £85.00.Theodore Arabatzis - 2020 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 33 (1):53-57.
    As indicated by its title, this book provides an overview of philosophy of science in the twentieth century. It focuses mostly on post-WWII philosophy of science, but it discusses earlier developme...
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  23
    The golden age of philosophy of science 1945 to 2000: logical reconstructionism, descriptivism, normative naturalism and foundationalism.John Losee - 2019 - London, UK: Bloomsbury Academic.
    The Golden Age of Philosophy of Science, 1945 to 2000 offers the reader a guide to the major philosophical approaches to science since World War Two. Considering the bases, arguments and conclusions of the four main movements - Naturalism, Descriptivism, Foundationalism, and Logical Reconstructionism - John P. Losee explores how philosophy has both shaped and expanded our understanding of science. The volume features major figures of twentieth century science, and engages with the work of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Naturalized philosophy of science with a plurality of methods.David Stump - 1992 - Philosophy of Science 59 (3):456-460.
    Naturalism implies unity of method--an application of the methods of science to the methodology of science itself and to value theory. Epistemological naturalists have tried to find a privileged discipline to be the methodological model of philosophy of science and epistemology. However, since science itself is not unitary, the use of one science as a model amounts to a reduction and distorts the philosophy of science just as badly as traditional philosophy (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  13.  48
    Two Cheers for Naturalised Philosophy of Science or: Why Naturalised Philosophy of Science is Not the Cat’s Whiskers.John Worrall - 1999 - Science & Education 8 (4):339-361.
  14.  21
    Political Philosophy of Science in Nineteenth-Century France: From Comte’s Positivism to Renouvier’s Conventionalism.Warren Schmaus - 2017 - In Marcus P. Adams, Zvi Biener, Uljana Feest & Jacqueline Anne Sullivan (eds.), Eppur Si Muove: Doing History and Philosophy of Science with Peter Machamer: A Collection of Essays in Honor of Peter Machamer. Dordrecht: Springer.
    Recent controversy over whether the Vienna Circle can provide a model for today’s political turn in the philosophy of science indicates the need to clarify just what is meant by the term political philosophy of science. This paper finds fourteen different meanings of the term, including both descriptive and normative usages, having to do with the roles of political values in the sciences, the political consequences and significance of the sciences and scientific modes of thought, and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Philosophy of the Social Sciences: Naturalism and Anti-Naturalism in the Philosophy of Social Science.Francesco Guala - 2014 - In Paul Humphreys (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Science. New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press. pp. 43-64.
    Naturalism is still facing a strong opposition in the philosophy of social science from influential scholars who argue that philosophical analysis must be autonomous from scientific investigation. The opposition exploits philosophers’ traditional diffidence toward social science and fuels the ambition to provide new foundations for social research. A classic anti-naturalist strategy is to identify a feature of social reality that prevents scientific explanation and prediction. An all-time favorite is the dependence of social phenomena on human representation. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  16. Philosophy of science naturalized.Ronald N. Giere - 1985 - Philosophy of Science 52 (3):331-356.
    In arguing a "role for history," Kuhn was proposing a naturalized philosophy of science. That, I argue, is the only viable approach to the philosophy of science. I begin by exhibiting the main general objections to a naturalistic approach. These objections, I suggest, are equally powerful against nonnaturalistic accounts. I review the failure of two nonnaturalistic approaches, methodological foundationism (Carnap, Reichenbach, and Popper) and metamethodology (Lakatos and Laudan). The correct response, I suggest, is to adopt an (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  17.  21
    The Golden Age of Philosophy of Science, 1945 to 2000: Logical Reconstruction, Descriptivism, Normative, Naturalism, and Foundationalism by John Losee. [REVIEW]Daniel J. McKaughan - 2020 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 58 (2):413-414.
    Should philosophers of science offer methodological prescriptions about how science ought to be practiced, or should they rest content with describing ways it has actually been practiced over time? Do the standards by which good science is assessed remain stable over time? How should rival philosophies of science be evaluated, and what role ought history of science play in such assessments? This book engages such questions while introducing a range of key ideas and debates by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Philosophy of Science A Personal Peek into the Future.Steven French & Michela Massimi - 2013 - Metaphilosophy 44 (3):230-240.
    In this opinion piece, the authors offer their personal and idiosyncratic views of the future of the philosophy of science, focusing on its relationship with the history of science and metaphysics, respectively. With regard to the former, they suggest that the Kantian tradition might be drawn upon both to render the history and philosophy of science more relevant to philosophy as a whole and to overcome the challenges posed by naturalism. When it comes to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  19. Philosophy of Science as First Philosophy: The Liberal Polemics of Ernest Nagel.Eric Schliesser - 2021 - In Matthias Neuber & Adam Tamas Tuboly (eds.), Ernest Nagel: Philosophy of Science and the Fight for Clarity. Springer. pp. 233-253.
    This chapter explores Nagel’s polemics. It shows these have a two-fold character: to defend liberal civilization against all kinds of enemies. And to defend what he calls ‘contextual naturalism.’ And the chapter shows that reinforce each other and undermine alternative political and philosophical programs. The chapter’s argument responds to an influential argument by George Reisch that Nagel’s professional stance represents a kind of disciplinary retreat from politics. In order to respond to Reisch the relationship between Nagel’s philosophy of (...) and his politics is explored and this chapter shows how both are anchored in what Nagel once called his ‘contextual naturalism’—a metaphysics that resists imposing the unity of the world and treats all entities as embedded in a wider network of entities. Part of the argument traces out how Nagel’s views on responsible speech and professionalism reflect a distinct understanding of the political role of philosophers of science. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20.  87
    New philosophies of science in north America — twenty years later.Joseph Rouse - 1998 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 29 (1):71-122.
    This survey of major developments in North American philosophy of science begins with the mid-1960s consolidation of the disciplinary synthesis of internalist history and philosophy of science (HPS) as a response to criticisms of logical empiricism. These developments are grouped for discussion under the following headings: historical metamethodologies, scientific realisms, philosophies of the special sciences, revivals of empiricism, cognitivist naturalisms, social epistemologies, feminist theories of science, studies of experiment and the disunity of science, and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  21.  12
    Toward a Naturalistic Philosophy of Institutions.Cyril Hédoin - unknown
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  59
    Feminist Philosophy of Science.Lynn Hankinson Nelson - 2002 - In Peter K. Machamer & Michael Silberstein (eds.), The Blackwell guide to the philosophy of science. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell. pp. 312–331.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Highlights of Past Literature Current Work Future Work.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  19
    Naturalism in the Contemporary Philosophy of Science (in Polish).Ierzy Bres - 2003 - Studia Philosophiae Christianae 39 (1):157-165.
    In der Philosophie der Wissenschaft wird die Konzeption der Supervenienz fur einen Vorschlag, der die bisherigen Lucken in den konzeptualen Schemen uberwindet, betrachtet. Die Unmoglichkeit der Reduzierung der Daseinsebenen erzwingt die Notwendigkeit der Annahme der Begrenzung bei der Benutzung des methodologischen Naturalismus. Der methodologische Naturalismus bildete das Postulat der Autonomie der Naturwissenschaften im Gegensatz zu Metaphysik. Zur Zeit kommt die Frage der Trennung der Naturwissenschaften von der Asthetik und der Ethik. Die Versuche, die beiden in die Erklarungssysteme einzufugen, ohne das (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  75
    Conceptual Analysis in the Philosophy of Science.Martin Zach - 2019 - Balkan Journal of Philosophy 11 (2):107-124.
    Conceptual analysis as a method of inquiry has long enjoyed popularity in analytic philosophy, including the philosophy of science. In this article I offer a perspective on the ways in which the method of conceptual analysis has been used, and distinguish two broad kinds, namely philosophical and empirical conceptual analysis. In so doing I outline a historical trend in which non-naturalized approaches to conceptual analysis are being replaced by a variety of naturalized approaches. I outline the basic (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  97
    Disagreement, Democracy, and the Goals of Science: Is a Normative Philosophy of Science Possible, If Ethical Inquiry Is Not?Arnon Keren - 2011 - Philosophy 86 (4):525-544.
    W.V.Quine and Philip Kitcher have both developed naturalistic approaches to the philosophy of science which are partially based on a skeptical view about the possibility of rational inquiry into certain questions of value. Nonetheless, both Quine and Kitcher do not wish to give up on the normative dimension of the philosophy of science. I argue that Kitcher's recent argument against the specification of the goal of science in terms of truth raises a problem for Quine's (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. Rationalizing Epistemology: An Argument Against Naturalism in Feminist Philosophy of Science.Maureen Linker - 1996 - Dissertation, City University of New York
    The dissertation involves an examination of recent work in Social Epistemology. In particular, I am concerned with the question of how one's social position could affect judgments regarding evidence and confirmation. To answer this question I undertake an investigation of feminist epistemology and philosophy of science. Feminist epistemologists have raised criticisms of the traditional analysis of knowledge by arguing against the primacy of the individual and for a more thorough-going analysis of the community in accounts of knowledge. This (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  16
    Ferment in Philosophy of Science Revisited.Paul T. Durbin - 1994 - The Thomist 58 (4):655-675.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:FERMENT IN PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE REVISITED PAUL T. DURBIN University of Delaware Newark, Delaware I N 1986 I published a survey of some then-recent works in academic philosophy of science, primarily in the United States (The Thomist 50/4 (Oct. 1986): 689-700). My theme was continuity amid change, with a secondary focus on the diversity of philosophers' discussions of science-a diversity much greater than many (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  93
    The naturalist conception of methodological standards in science: A critique.Gerald Doppelt - 1990 - Philosophy of Science 57 (1):1-19.
    In this essay, I criticize Laudan's view that methodological rules in science are best understood as hypothetical imperatives, for example, to realize cognitive aim A, follow method B. I criticize his idea that such rules are best evaluated by a naturalized philosophy of science which collects the empirical evidence bearing on the soundness of these rules. My claim is that this view yields a poor explanation of (1) the role of methodological rules in establishing the rationality of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  29.  72
    The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Science.Paul Humphreys (ed.) - 2014 - New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press.
    This handbook provides both an overview of state-of-the-art scholarship in philosophy of science, as well as a guide to new directions in the discipline. Section I contains broad overviews of the main lines of research and the state of established knowledge in six principal areas of the discipline, including computational, physical, biological, psychological and social sciences, as well as general philosophy of science. Section II covers what are considered to be the traditional topics in the (...) of science, such as causation, probability, models, ethics and values, and explanation. Section III identifies new areas of investigation that show promise of becoming important areas of research, including the philosophy of astronomy and astrophysics, data, complexity theory, neuroscience, simulations, post-Kuhnian philosophy, post-empiricist epistemology, and emergence. Most chapters are accessible to scientifically educated non-philosophers as well as to professional philosophers, and the contributors - all leading researchers in their field -- bring diverse perspectives from the North American, European, and Australasian research communities. This volume is an essential resource for scholars and students. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30. Putting philosophy of political science on the map.Harold Kincaid & Jeroen Van Bouwel - 2022 - In Harold Kincaid & Jeroen Van Bouwel (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Political Science. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 1-14.
    Contrary to economics or history, for example, there does not exist an organized field dedicated to the philosophy of political science. Given that the philosophical issues raised by political science research are just as pressing and vibrant as those raised in these more organized fields, fostering a field that labels itself Philosophy of Political Science (PoPS) is important. PoPS is advanced here as a fruitful meeting place where both philosophers and practicing political scientists contribute and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  70
    Naturalism and social science: a post-empiricist philosophy of social science.David Thomas - 1979 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    This 1979 text addresses the ways in which the dominant theories in large areas of Western social science have been subject to strong criticisms, particularly ...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  32. A feminist naturalized philosophy of science.Lynn Hankinson Nelson - 1995 - Synthese 104 (3):399 - 421.
    Building on developments in feminist science scholarship and the philosophy of science, I advocate two methodological principles as elements of a naturalized philosophy of science. One principle incorporates a holistic account of evidence inclusive of claims and theories informed by and/or expressive of politics and non-constitutive values; the second takes communities, rather than individual scientists, to be the primary loci of scientific knowledge. I use case studies to demonstrate that these methodological principles satisfy three criteria (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  33.  38
    The Philosophy of Ordinary Language Is a Naturalistic Philosophy.Jonathan Trigg - 2010 - Essays in Philosophy 11 (2):197-215.
    It is argued that the only response to the mereological objections of the ordinary language philosopher available to the scientistic philosopher of mind requires the adoption of the view that ordinary psychological talk is theoretical and falsified by the findings of brain science. The availability of this sort of response produces a kind of stalemate between these opposed views and viewpoints: the claim that attribution of psychological predicates to parts of organisms is nonsense is met with the claim that (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34. Philosophy in the trenches: from naturalized to experimental philosophy (of science).Karola Stotz - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 40 (2):225-226.
    Recent years have seen the development of an approach both to general philosophy and philosophy of science often referred to as ‘experimental philosophy’ or just ‘X-Phi’. Philosophers often make or presuppose empirical claims about how people would react to hypothetical cases, but their evidence for claims about what ‘we’ would say is usually very limited indeed. Philosophers of science have largely relied on their more or less intimate knowledge of their field of study to draw (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  35. Naturalizing the Philosophy of Science.Michael A. Bishop - 1990 - Dissertation, University of California, San Diego
    Normative apriorist philosophers of science build purely normative a priori reconstructions of science, whereas descriptive naturalists eliminate the normative elements of the philosophy of science in favor of purely descriptive endeavors. I hope to exhibit the virtues of an alternative approach that appreciates both the normative and the natural in the philosophy of science. ;Theory ladenness. Some philosophers claim that a plausible view about how our visual systems work either undermines or facilitates our ability (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  23
    Naturalized Philosophy of Science and Economic Method.Christoph Luetge - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 37:165-179.
    This paper draws a connection between recent developments in naturalized philosophy of science and in economics. Social epistemology is one part of the naturalistic enterprise that has become especially important. Some approaches in this field use methods borrowed from economics, a fact that has often been overlooked. But there are also genuinely economic approaches to the problems of science and knowledge. Some of these approaches can be seen as contributions to an "economic epistemology." While these contributions are (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Artificial Language Philosophy of Science.Sebastian Lutz - 2011 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 2 (2):181–203.
    Abstract Artificial language philosophy (also called ‘ideal language philosophy’) is the position that philosophical problems are best solved or dissolved through a reform of language. Its underlying methodology—the development of languages for specific purposes—leads to a conventionalist view of language in general and of concepts in particular. I argue that many philosophical practices can be reinterpreted as applications of artificial language philosophy. In addition, many factually occurring interrelations between the sciences and philosophy of science are (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  38. Taking the naturalistic turn, or, How real philosophy of science is done: conversations with William Bechtel... [et al.].William Bechtel & Werner Callebaut (eds.) - 1993 - Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  76
    Philosophy of biology: Naturalistic or transcendental?Filip Kolen & Gertrudis Van de Vijver - 2007 - Acta Biotheoretica 55 (1):35-46.
    The aim of this article is to clarify the meaning of a naturalistic position within philosophy of biology, against the background of an alternative view, founded on the basic insights of transcendental philosophy. It is argued that the apparently minimal and neutral constraints naturalism imposes on philosophy of science turn out to involve a quite heavily constraining metaphysics, due to the naturalism’s fundamental neglect of its own perspective. Because of its intrinsic sensitivity to perspectivity and historicity, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  66
    New waves in philosophy of science.P. D. Magnus & Jacob Busch (eds.) - 2009 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Introduction 1 P. D. Magnus and Jacob Busch 1. Form-driven vs. Content-driven Arguments for Realism 8 Juha Saatsi 2. Optimism about the Pessimistic Induction 29 Sherrilyn Roush 3. Metaphysics between the Sciences and Philosophies of Science 59 Anjan Chakravartty 4. Nominalism and Inductive Generalizations 78 Jessica Pfeifer 5. Models and Scientific Representations 94 Otávio Bueno 6. The Identical Rivals Response to Underdetermination 112 Gregory Frost-Arnold and P. D. Magnus 7. Scientific Representation and the Semiotics of Pictures 131 Laura Perini (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41. Instrumental rationality and naturalized philosophy of science.Harvey Siegel - 1996 - Philosophy of Science 63 (3):124.
    In two recent papers, I criticized Ronald N. Giere's and Larry Laudan's arguments for 'naturalizing' the philosophy of science (Siegel 1989, 1990). Both Giere and Laudan replied to my criticisms (Giere 1989, Laudan 1990b). The key issue arising in both interchanges is these naturalists' embrace of instrumental conceptions of rationality, and their concomitant rejection of non-instrumental conceptions of that key normative notion. In this reply I argue that their accounts of science's rationality as exclusively instrumental fail, and (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  42. The context distinction: controversies over feminist philosophy of science.Monica Aufrecht - 2011 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 1 (3):373-392.
    The “context of discovery” and “context of justification” distinction has been used by Noretta Koertge and Lynn Hankinson Nelson in debates over the legitimacy of feminist approaches to philosophy of science. Koertge uses the context distinction to focus the conversation by barring certain approaches. I contend this focus masks points of true disagreement about the nature of justification. Nonetheless, Koertge raises important questions that have been too quickly set aside by some. I conclude that the context distinction should (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. A Pragmatically Realistic Philosophy of Science.John Shook - 2003 - In John R. Shook (ed.), Pragmatic Naturalism and Realism. Prometheus. pp. 323--344.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  44.  16
    Nietzsche's Naturalism: Philosophy and the Life Sciences in the Nineteenth Century.Christian Emden - 2014 - Cambridge University Press.
    This book explores Nietzsche's philosophical naturalism in its historical context, showing that his position is best understood against the background of encounters between neo-Kantianism and the life sciences in the nineteenth century. Analyzing most of Nietzsche's writings from the late 1860s onwards, Christian J. Emden reconstructs Nietzsche's naturalism and argues for a new understanding of his account of nature and normativity. Emden proposes historical reasons why Nietzsche came to adopt the position he did; his genealogy of values and his account (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  45.  67
    Taking the Naturalistic Turn or How Real Philosophy of Science Is Done. [REVIEW]Ignacio Ayestarán & Nicanor Ursúa - 1994 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 9 (1):216-221.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Naturalism’s maxims and its methods. Is naturalistic philosophy like science?Carin Robinson - 2018 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 22 (3):371-391.
    This paper argues that naturalistic philosophy does not meet its own empiricist mandate. It argues from an empiricist perspective. Naturalists either claim that philosophy is like science in significant ways, or they claim that philosophy ought to be like science. This paper, being chiefly focused on the former claim, argues that naturalistic philosophy is nothing like science. Using Papineau’s markers for the similarities between naturalistic philosophy and science, I argue, counter Papineau, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  31
    Clio meets minerva: Interrelations between history and philosophy of science.Barbara Tuchanska - 2002 - „Pantaneto Forum”,Http (issue 13).
    The idea that science is historical is almost a cliché nowadays. The historical dimensions of science have begun to be appreciated by philosophers of science, for some through the work of Kuhn, and for others through Popper and Lakatos. Does this mean that contemporary philosophy of science understands the historical nature of science? Let me begin with a provocative negative answer. My reason is not the obvious one, namely, that there are several competing models (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Harmless naturalism: The limits of science and the nature of philosophy.Matthias Steup - 2000 - Philosophical Review 109 (3):462-465.
    Should we only believe what science can prove? Robert Almeder analyzes "naturalized epistemology," which holds that the only valid claims that can be made about the world must be proven by the natural sciences and that all philosophical questions are ultimately answered by science. The author examines and refutes different forms of naturalized epistemology before settling on "harmless naturalism," a compromise which implies that certain questions about the world are answerable and have been answered, without appealing to (...). (publisher). (shrink)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  16
    The Importance of Spinoza for the Modern Philosophy of Science: Can the revival of Spinoza's naturalism refute cultural relativism?Nancy Brenner-Golomb - 2010 - De Gruyter.
    The question raised in this book is why Spinoza s work which comes so close to the modern view of natural science is not prominent in the social sciences. The answer suggested is that this is due to the lingering influence of the Cartesian differentiation between the domain of science, dealing with material bodies in space and time, and the realm of thought to which the mind belongs. Spinoza s rejection of this mind/body dualism was based on his (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  37
    (1 other version)Philosophy of Science and Its Rational Reconstructions: Remarks on the VPI Program for Testing Philosophies of Science.Alan W. Richardson - 1992 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992:36 - 46.
    In this paper I argue that the program of L. Laudan et al for empirically testing historiographical philosophies of science ("the VPI program") does not succeed in providing a consistent naturalist program in philosophy of science. In particular, the VPI program endorses a nonnaturalist metamethodology that insists on a hypothetico-deductive structure to scientific testing. But hypothetico-deductivism seems to be both inadequate as an account of scientific theory testing in general and fundamentally at odds with most of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 956