Results for 'Riemann geometry'

951 found
Order:
  1.  47
    Kant, Riemann, and Reichenbach on Space and Geometry.William L. Harper - 1995 - Proceedings of the Eighth International Kant Congress 1:423-454.
    Classic examples of ostensive geometrical constructions are used to clarify Kant’s account of how they provide knowledge of claims about rigid bodies we can observe and manipulate. It is argued that on Kant’s account claims warranted by ostensive constructions must be limited to scales and tolerances corresponding to our perceptual competencies. This limitation opens the way to view Riemann’s work as contributing valuable conceptual resources for extending geometrical knowledge beyond the bounds of observation. It is argued that neither Reichenbach’s (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  55
    Riemann’s Geometry and Eternal Recurrence as Cosmological Hypothesis.George J. Stack - 1989 - International Studies in Philosophy 21 (2):37-40.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  73
    Geometries in Collision: Einstein, Klein and Riemann.John D. Norton - 1982 - In John Norton (ed.).
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  4.  53
    Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincaré.Nicholas Griffin - 1981 - Philosophical Quarterly 31 (125):374.
  5.  14
    Riemanns frühe Notizen zum Mannigfaltigkeitsbegriff und zu den Grundlagen der Geometrie.E. Scholz - 1982 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 27 (3):213-232.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  6.  7
    Riemann’s Philosophy of Geometry and Kant’s Pure Intuition.Dinçer çevik - 2024 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 31 (2):114-140.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  50
    From Gauss to Riemann Through Jacobi: Interactions Between the Epistemologies of Geometry and Mechanics?Maria de Paz & José Ferreirós - 2020 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 51 (1):147-172.
    The aim of this paper is to argue that there existed relevant interactions between mechanics and geometry during the first half of the nineteenth century, following a path that goes from Gauss to Riemann through Jacobi. By presenting a rich historical context we hope to throw light on the philosophical change of epistemological categories applied by these authors to the fundamental principles of both disciplines. We intend to show that presentations of the changing status of the principles of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  39
    Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincare. By Roberto Torretti. [REVIEW]Steven James Bartlett - 1981 - Modern Schoolman 58 (2):136-136.
    A review of Roberto Torretti's book, "Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincare.".
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  33
    Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincaré.J. Alberto Coffa - 1983 - Noûs 17 (4):683-689.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  10. Die axiome der Geometrie, eine philosophische Untersuchung der Riemann-Helmholtz'schen Raumtheorie.Benno Erdmann - 1877 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 4:524-530.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11. (1 other version)Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincaré.Roberto Torretti - 1978 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 172 (3):565-572.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  12. Riemann, B. - Ueber Die Hypothesen Welche Der Geometrie Zu Grunde Liegen. [REVIEW]G. Loria - 1920 - Scientia 14 (27):405.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Roberto Torretti," Philosophy of geometry from Riemann to Poincaré".José Pedro Ubeda Rives - 1980 - Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 10 (1):89-93.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Die Axiome der Geometry Eine Philosophische Untersuchung der Riemann-Helmholtz'schen Raumtheorie.Benno Erdmann - 1877 - L. Voss.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  52
    Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincaré Roberto Torretti Dordrecht and Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1978. Pp. xiii, 459. $50.00 U.S. [REVIEW]Roger B. Angel - 1982 - Dialogue 21 (2):384-391.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  67
    Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincaré. [REVIEW]S. L. - 1982 - Review of Metaphysics 35 (3):633-634.
    This deeply researched, carefully constructed and very thoughtful book is fascinating in its own right as well as being indispensable background material for anyone interested in current philosophical thought about space, time, and geometry.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. TORRETTI, ROBERTO: "Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann Poincaré". [REVIEW]J. L. Lucas - 1980 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31:414.
  18. TORRETTI, R., "Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincare". [REVIEW]G. Nerlich - 1980 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 58:185.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  57
    Some Mathematical, Epistemological, and Historical Reflections on the Relationship Between Geometry and Reality, Space–Time Theory and the Geometrization of Theoretical Physics, from Riemann to Weyl and Beyond.Luciano Boi - 2019 - Foundations of Science 24 (1):1-38.
    The history and philosophy of science are destined to play a fundamental role in an epoch marked by a major scientific revolution. This ongoing revolution, principally affecting mathematics and physics, entails a profound upheaval of our conception of space, space–time, and, consequently, of natural laws themselves. Briefly, this revolution can be summarized by the following two trends: by the search for a unified theory of the four fundamental forces of nature, which are known, as of now, as gravity, electromagnetism, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  20.  34
    The Mathematics of Continuous Multiplicities: The Role of Riemann in Deleuze's Reading of Bergson.Nathan Widder - 2019 - Deleuze and Guattari Studies 13 (3):331-354.
    A central claim of Deleuze's reading of Bergson is that Bergson's distinction between space as an extensive multiplicity and duration as an intensive multiplicity is inspired by the distinction between discrete and continuous manifolds found in Bernhard Riemann's 1854 thesis on the foundations of geometry. Yet there is no evidence from Bergson that Riemann influences his division, and the distinction between the discrete and continuous is hardly a Riemannian invention. Claiming Riemann's influence, however, allows Deleuze to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  21. Bernhard Riemann: Riemanniana Selecta.Jose Ferreiros - 2000 - Madrid: CSIC.
    A book-length study of Riemann's multi-dimensional work (in Spanish), which considers his contributions to physics, philosophy and mathematics. Plus a bi-lingual edition (German-Spanish) of some of his landmark papers: the lecture on geometry, with Weyl's comments; the paper introducing the Riemann Conjecture, part of his 1857 paper on function theory; all of the philosophical fragments, etc. These different contributions, and their interconnections, are carefully studied in the introductory essay of 150 pages.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  32
    Is There Any Room for Spatial Intuition in Riemann’s Philosophy of Geometry?Dinçer Çevik - 2015 - Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy 5 (1):81.
  23. From geometry to phenomenology.Mirja Helena Hartimo - 2008 - Synthese 162 (2):225-233.
    Richard Tieszen [Tieszen, R. (2005). Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXX(1), 153–173.] has argued that the group-theoretical approach to modern geometry can be seen as a realization of Edmund Husserl’s view of eidetic intuition. In support of Tieszen’s claim, the present article discusses Husserl’s approach to geometry in 1886–1902. Husserl’s first detailed discussion of the concept of group and invariants under transformations takes place in his notes on Hilbert’s Memoir Ueber die Grundlagen der Geometrie that Hilbert wrote during the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  24.  50
    Space, Number, and Geometry From Helmholtz to Cassirer.Francesca Biagioli - 2016 - Cham: Springer Verlag.
    This book offers a reconstruction of the debate on non-Euclidean geometry in neo-Kantianism between the second half of the nineteenth century and the first decades of the twentieth century. Kant famously characterized space and time as a priori forms of intuitions, which lie at the foundation of mathematical knowledge. The success of his philosophical account of space was due not least to the fact that Euclidean geometry was widely considered to be a model of certainty at his time. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  25. Thomas Reid’s Geometry of Visibles.James Van Cleve - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (3):373-416.
    In a brief but remarkable section of the Inquiry into the Human Mind, Thomas Reid argued that the visual field is governed by principles other than the familiar theorems of Euclid—theorems we would nowadays classify as Riemannian. On the strength of this section, he has been credited by Norman Daniels, R. B. Angell, and others with discovering non-Euclidean geometry over half a century before the mathematicians—sixty years before Lobachevsky and ninety years before Riemann. I believe that Reid does (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  26.  27
    La vérité en géométrie: sur le rejet mathématique de la doctrine conventionnaliste.Scott A. Walter - 1997 - Philosophia Scientiae 2 (3):103-135.
    The reception of Poincaré’s conventionalist doctrine of space by mathematicians is studied for the period 1891–1911. The opposing view of Riemann and Helmholtz, according to which the geometry of space is an empirical question, is shown to have swayed several geometers. This preference is considered in the context of changing views of the nature of space in theoretical physics, and with respect to structural and social changes within mathematics. Included in the latter evolution is the emergence of non-Euclidean (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  27.  87
    The Forgotten Tradition: How the Logical Empiricists Missed the Philosophical Significance of the Work of Riemann, Christoffel and Ricci.Marco Giovanelli - 2013 - Erkenntnis 78 (6):1219-1257.
    This paper attempts to show how the logical empiricists’ interpretation of the relation between geometry and reality emerges from a “collision” of mathematical traditions. Considering Riemann’s work as the initiator of a 19th century geometrical tradition, whose main protagonists were Helmholtz and Poincaré, the logical empiricists neglected the fact that Riemann’s revolutionary insight flourished instead in a non-geometrical tradition dominated by the works of Christoffel and Ricci-Curbastro roughly in the same years. I will argue that, in the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  28.  24
    Lizhen Ji; Athanase Papadopoulos; Sumio Yamada . From Riemann to Differential Geometry and Relativity. xxxiv + 647 pp., index. Berlin: Springer, 2017. €139 . ISBN 9783319600383. [REVIEW]Yvette Kosmann-Schwarzbach - 2019 - Isis 110 (1):183-184.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  63
    (1 other version)Husserl’s Conception of Physical Theories and Physical Geometry in the Time of the Prolegomena: A Comparison with Duhem’s and Poincaré’s Views.Guillermo E. Rosado Haddock - 2012 - Global Philosophy 22 (1):171-193.
    This paper discusses Husserl’s views on physical theories in the first volume of his Logical Investigations, and compares them with those of his contemporaries Pierre Duhem and Henri Poincaré. Poincaré’s views serve as a bridge to a discussion of Husserl’s almost unknown views on physical geometry from about 1890 on, which in comparison even with Poincaré’s—not to say Frege’s—or almost any other philosopher of his time, represented a rupture with the philosophical tradition and were much more in tune with (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  71
    Derivation of the Dirac Equation by Conformal Differential Geometry.Enrico Santamato & Francesco De Martini - 2013 - Foundations of Physics 43 (5):631-641.
    A rigorous ab initio derivation of the (square of) Dirac’s equation for a particle with spin is presented. The Lagrangian of the classical relativistic spherical top is modified so to render it invariant with respect conformal changes of the metric of the top configuration space. The conformal invariance is achieved by replacing the particle mass in the Lagrangian with the conformal Weyl scalar curvature. The Hamilton-Jacobi equation for the particle is found to be linearized, exactly and in closed form, by (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31.  47
    Torsion Fields, Cartan–Weyl Space–Time and State-Space Quantum Geometries, their Brownian Motions, and the Time Variables.Diego L. Rapoport - 2007 - Foundations of Physics 37 (4-5):813-854.
    We review the relation between spacetime geometries with trace-torsion fields, the so-called Riemann–Cartan–Weyl (RCW) geometries, and their associated Brownian motions. In this setting, the drift vector field is the metric conjugate of the trace-torsion one-form, and the laplacian defined by the RCW connection is the differential generator of the Brownian motions. We extend this to the state-space of non-relativistic quantum mechanics and discuss the relation between a non-canonical quantum RCW geometry in state-space associated with the gradient of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32.  97
    Hermann Weyl on Minkowskian Space–Time and Riemannian Geometry.Yvon Gauthier - 2005 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 19 (3):261 – 269.
    Hermann Weyl as a founding father of field theory in relativistic physics and quantum theory always stressed the internal logic of mathematical and physical theories. In line with his stance in the foundations of mathematics, Weyl advocated a constructivist approach in physics and geometry. An attempt is made here to present a unified picture of Weyl's conception of space-time theories from Riemann to Minkowski. The emphasis is on the mathematical foundations of physics and the foundational significance of a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  27
    La réflexion de Poincaré sur l’espace, dans l’histoire de la géométrie.Alain Michel - 2004 - Philosophiques 31 (1):89-114.
    Les conceptions de Poincaré en matière de physique mathématique demandent à être mises en relation avec son travail mathématique. Ce qu’on a appelé son « conventionnalisme géométrique » est étroitement lié à ses premiers travaux mathématiques et à son intérêt pour la géométrie de Plücker et la théorie des groupes continus de Lie. Sa conception profonde de l’espace et son insertion dans un environnement post-kantien concourent à composer les traits d’une doctrine dont on a souvent sous-estimé l’originalité, dans ses différences (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. Frege on the Foundation of Geometry in Intuition.Jeremy Shipley - 2015 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 3 (6).
    I investigate the role of geometric intuition in Frege’s early mathematical works and the significance of his view of the role of intuition in geometry to properly understanding the aims of his logicist project. I critically evaluate the interpretations of Mark Wilson, Jamie Tappenden, and Michael Dummett. The final analysis that I provide clarifies the relationship of Frege’s restricted logicist project to dominant trends in German mathematical research, in particular to Weierstrassian arithmetization and to the Riemannian conceptual/geometrical tradition at (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  35.  14
    Felix Klein’s early contributions to anschauliche Geometrie.David E. Rowe - 2024 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 78 (4):401-477.
    Between 1873 and 1876, Felix Klein published a series of papers that he later placed under the rubric anschauliche Geometrie in the second volume of his collected works (1922). The present study attempts not only to follow the course of this work, but also to place it in a larger historical context. Methodologically, Klein’s approach had roots in Poncelet’s principle of continuity, though the more immediate influences on him came from his teachers, Plücker and Clebsch. In the 1860s, Clebsch reworked (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  60
    Local and Non-Local Aspects of Quantum Gravity.H.-H. V. Borzeszkowski, B. K. Datta, V. De Sabbata, L. Ronchetti & H.-J. Treder - 2002 - Foundations of Physics 32 (11):1701-1716.
    The analysis of the measurement of gravitational fields leads to the Rosenfeld inequalities. They say that, as an implication of the equivalence of the inertial and passive gravitational masses of the test body, the metric cannot be attributed to an operator that is defined in the frame of a local canonical quantum field theory. This is true for any theory containing a metric, independently of the geometric framework under consideration and the way one introduces the metric in it. Thus, to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37. Strict Finitism and the Logic of Mathematical Applications, Synthese Library, vol. 355.Feng Ye - 2011 - Springer.
    This book intends to show that, in philosophy of mathematics, radical naturalism (or physicalism), nominalism and strict finitism (which does not assume the reality of infinity in any format, not even potential infinity) can account for the applications of classical mathematics in current scientific theories about the finite physical world above the Planck scale. For that purpose, the book develops some significant applied mathematics in strict finitism, which is essentially quantifier-free elementary recursive arithmetic (with real numbers encoded as elementary recursive (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  25
    Strict Finitism and the Logic of Mathematical Applications.Feng Ye - 2011 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    This book intends to show that radical naturalism, nominalism and strict finitism account for the applications of classical mathematics in current scientific theories. The applied mathematical theories developed in the book include the basics of calculus, metric space theory, complex analysis, Lebesgue integration, Hilbert spaces, and semi-Riemann geometry. The fact that so much applied mathematics can be developed within such a weak, strictly finitistic system, is surprising in itself. It also shows that the applications of those classical theories (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39.  13
    Elementare Differentialgeometrie.Christian Bär - 2010 - De Gruyter.
    This textbook presents an introduction to the differential geometry of curves and surfaces. This second, revised edition has been expanded to include solutions and applications in cartography. Topics include Euclidean geometry, curve theory, surface theory, curvature concepts, minimal surfaces, Riemann geometry and the Gauss-Bonnet theorem.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Local and Non-Local Aspects of Quantum Gravity.H. -H. V. Borzeszkowski, B. K. Datta, V. De Sabbata, L. Ronchetti & H. -J. Treder - 2002 - Foundations of Physics 32 (11):1701-1716.
    The analysis of the measurement of gravitational fields leads to the Rosenfeld inequalities. They say that, as an implication of the equivalence of the inertial and passive gravitational masses of the test body, the metric cannot be attributed to an operator that is defined in the frame of a local canonical quantum field theory. This is true for any theory containing a metric, independently of the geometric framework under consideration and the way one introduces the metric in it. Thus, to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  27
    A New Subject-Specific Discriminative and Multi-Scale Filter Bank Tangent Space Mapping Method for Recognition of Multiclass Motor Imagery.Fan Wu, Anmin Gong, Hongyun Li, Lei Zhao, Wei Zhang & Yunfa Fu - 2021 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 15.
    Objective: Tangent Space Mapping using the geometric structure of the covariance matrices is an effective method to recognize multiclass motor imagery. Compared with the traditional CSP method, the Riemann geometric method based on TSM takes into account the nonlinear information contained in the covariance matrix, and can extract more abundant and effective features. Moreover, the method is an unsupervised operation, which can reduce the time of feature extraction. However, EEG features induced by MI mental activities of different subjects are (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  22
    The first gestures of knowledge.Pierre Kerszberg - 2014 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 76 (2):277-306.
    Husserl credited Riemann for bringing the modern idea of “mathesis universalis‘ to its realization. Going beyond the logical ideal of a theory of all possible forms of theories, this paper explores the phenomenological sense of intrinsically physical geometry. Starting from Kant, how can we follow the thread of transcendental idealism in the search for the hidden presuppositions of this kind of geometry? This is achieved by reflecting on the paradigmatic experience of the earth at rest in our (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  61
    On the Unification of Geometric and Random Structures through Torsion Fields: Brownian Motions, Viscous and Magneto-fluid-dynamics.Diego L. Rapoport - 2005 - Foundations of Physics 35 (7):1205-1244.
    We present the unification of Riemann–Cartan–Weyl (RCW) space-time geometries and random generalized Brownian motions. These are metric compatible connections (albeit the metric can be trivially euclidean) which have a propagating trace-torsion 1-form, whose metric conjugate describes the average motion interaction term. Thus, the universality of torsion fields is proved through the universality of Brownian motions. We extend this approach to give a random symplectic theory on phase-space. We present as a case study of this approach, the invariant Navier–Stokes equations (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44.  14
    Geometría diferencial Y teoría de las ideas: La presencia riemanniana en diferencia Y repetición de Deleuze.Gonzalo Santaya - 2021 - Universitas Philosophica 38 (76):49-77.
    This paper contributes to clarifying Deleuze’s theory of the Idea by a commentary on its technical definition: “a defined, continuous, n-dimensional multiplicity”, presented in chapter IV of Difference and Repetition. This definition implicitly intertwines Deleuze’s own metaphysical view of the Idea as a virtual problem with a series of notions taken from the differential geometry developed by the German mathematician Georg B. Riemann. To clarify this influence, we will reconstruct the fundamental elements of the Riemannian notions used by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  20
    The idea of quantity at the origin of the legitimacy of mathematization in physics.Michel Paty - 2003 - In C. Gould (ed.), Constructivism and Practice: Towards a Social and Historical Epistemology. Rowman& Littlefield. pp. 109-135.
    Newton's use of mathematics in mechanics was justified by him from his neo-platonician conception of the physical world that was going along with his «absolute, true and mathematical concepts» such as space, time, motion, force, etc. But physics, afterwards, although it was based on newtonian dynamics, meant differently the legitimacy of being mathematized, and this difference can be seen already in the works of eighteenth century «Geometers» such as Euler, Clairaut and d'Alembert (and later on Lagrange, Laplace and others). Despite (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  55
    On Metric and Matter in Unconnected, Connected, and Metrically Connected Manifolds.Horst-Heino von Borzeszkowski & Hans-Jürgen Treder - 2004 - Foundations of Physics 34 (10):1541-1572.
    From Einstein's point of view, his General Relativity Theory had strengths as well as failings. For him, its shortcoming mainly was that it did not unify gravitation and electromagnetism and did not provide solutions to field equations which can be interpreted as particle models with discrete mass and charge spectra, As a consequence, General Relativity did not solve the quantum problem, either. Einstein tried to get rid of the shortcomings without losing the achievements of General Relativity Theory. Stimulated by papers (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47. Logic, mathematics, physics: from a loose thread to the close link: Or what gravity is for both logic and mathematics rather than only for physics.Vasil Penchev - 2023 - Astrophysics, Cosmology and Gravitation Ejournal 2 (52):1-82.
    Gravitation is interpreted to be an “ontomathematical” force or interaction rather than an only physical one. That approach restores Newton’s original design of universal gravitation in the framework of “The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy”, which allows for Einstein’s special and general relativity to be also reinterpreted ontomathematically. The entanglement theory of quantum gravitation is inherently involved also ontomathematically by virtue of the consideration of the qubit Hilbert space after entanglement as the Fourier counterpart of pseudo-Riemannian space. Gravitation can be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Space, Time and Falsifiability Critical Exposition and Reply to "A Panel Discussion of Grünbaum's Philosophy of Science".Adolf Grünbaum - 1970 - Philosophy of Science 37 (4):469 - 588.
    Prompted by the "Panel Discussion of Grünbaum's Philosophy of Science" (Philosophy of Science 36, December, 1969) and other recent literature, this essay ranges over major issues in the philosophy of space, time and space-time as well as over problems in the logic of ascertaining the falsity of a scientific hypothesis. The author's philosophy of geometry has recently been challenged along three main distinct lines as follows: (i) The Panel article by G. J. Massey calls for a more precise and (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  49.  17
    Towards a history of the geometric foundations of mathematics.Rossana Tazzioli - 2003 - Revue de Synthèse 124 (1):11-41.
    Beaucoup de « géomètres » du XIXe siècle - Bernhard Riemann, Hermann von Helmholtz, Felix Klein, Riccardo De Paolis, Mario Pieri, Henri Poincaré, Federigo Enriques, et autres - ont joué un rôle important dans la discussion sur les fondements des mathématiques. Mais, contrairement aux idées d'Euclide, ils n'ont pas identifié «l'espace physique» avec« l'espace de nos sens». Partant de notre expérience dans l'espace, ils ont cherché à identifier les propriétés les plus importantes de l'espace et les ont posées à (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50.  72
    Domains for computation in mathematics, physics and exact real arithmetic.Abbas Edalat - 1997 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 3 (4):401-452.
    We present a survey of the recent applications of continuous domains for providing simple computational models for classical spaces in mathematics including the real line, countably based locally compact spaces, complete separable metric spaces, separable Banach spaces and spaces of probability distributions. It is shown how these models have a logical and effective presentation and how they are used to give a computational framework in several areas in mathematics and physics. These include fractal geometry, where new results on existence (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
1 — 50 / 951