Results for 'Rigor, Proof, Diagrams, Formalization'

975 found
Order:
  1. What is Mathematical Rigor?John Burgess & Silvia De Toffoli - 2022 - Aphex 25:1-17.
    Rigorous proof is supposed to guarantee that the premises invoked imply the conclusion reached, and the problem of rigor may be described as that of bringing together the perspectives of formal logic and mathematical practice on how this is to be achieved. This problem has recently raised a lot of discussion among philosophers of mathematics. We survey some possible solutions and argue that failure to understand its terms properly has led to misunderstandings in the literature.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2. Proof: Its Nature and Significance.Michael Detlefsen - 2008 - In Bonnie Gold & Roger A. Simons (eds.), Proof and Other Dilemmas: Mathematics and Philosophy. Mathematical Association of America. pp. 3-32.
    I focus on three preoccupations of recent writings on proof. -/- I. The role and possible effects of empirical reasoning in mathematics. Do recent developments (specifically, the computer-assisted proof of the 4CT) point to something essentially new as regards the need for and/or effects of using broadly empirical and inductive reasoning in mathematics? In particular, should we see such things as the computer-assisted proof of the 4CT as pointing to the existence of mathematical truths of which we cannot have a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  3. Proof: Its nature and significance.Michael Detlefsen - 2008 - In Bonnie Gold & Roger A. Simons (eds.), Proof and Other Dilemmas: Mathematics and Philosophy. Mathematical Association of America. pp. 1.
    I focus on three preoccupations of recent writings on proof. -/- I. The role and possible effects of empirical reasoning in mathematics. Do recent developments (specifically, the computer-assisted proof of the 4CT) point to something essentially new as regards the need for and/or effects of using broadly empirical and inductive reasoning in mathematics? In particular, should we see such things as the computer-assisted proof of the 4CT as pointing to the existence of mathematical truths of which we cannot have a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  4. Proofs, pictures, and Euclid.John Mumma - 2010 - Synthese 175 (2):255 - 287.
    Though pictures are often used to present mathematical arguments, they are not typically thought to be an acceptable means for presenting mathematical arguments rigorously. With respect to the proofs in the Elements in particular, the received view is that Euclid's reliance on geometric diagrams undermines his efforts to develop a gap-free deductive theory. The central difficulty concerns the generality of the theory. How can inferences made from a particular diagrams license general mathematical results? After surveying the history behind the received (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  5. Nathaniel Miller. Euclid and his twentieth century rivals: Diagrams in the logic of euclidean geometry. Csli studies in the theory and applications of diagrams.John Mumma - 2008 - Philosophia Mathematica 16 (2):256-264.
    It is commonplace to view the rigor of the mathematics in Euclid's Elements in the way an experienced teacher views the work of an earnest beginner: respectable relative to an early stage of development, but ultimately flawed. Given the close connection in content between Euclid's Elements and high-school geometry classes, this is understandable. Euclid, it seems, never realized what everyone who moves beyond elementary geometry into more advanced mathematics is now customarily taught: a fully rigorous proof cannot rely on geometric (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  6.  11
    99 Variations on a Proof.Philip Ording - 2018 - Princeton: Princeton University Press.
    An exploration of mathematical style through 99 different proofs of the same theorem This book offers a multifaceted perspective on mathematics by demonstrating 99 different proofs of the same theorem. Each chapter solves an otherwise unremarkable equation in distinct historical, formal, and imaginative styles that range from Medieval, Topological, and Doggerel to Chromatic, Electrostatic, and Psychedelic. With a rare blend of humor and scholarly aplomb, Philip Ording weaves these variations into an accessible and wide-ranging narrative on the nature and practice (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  33
    Counter-Example Construction with Euler Diagrams.Ryo Takemura - 2015 - Studia Logica 103 (4):669-696.
    One of the traditional applications of Euler diagrams is as a representation or counterpart of the usual set-theoretical models of given sentences. However, Euler diagrams have recently been investigated as the counterparts of logical formulas, which constitute formal proofs. Euler diagrams are rigorously defined as syntactic objects, and their inference systems, which are equivalent to some symbolic logical systems, are formalized. Based on this observation, we investigate both counter-model construction and proof-construction in the framework of Euler diagrams. We introduce the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  91
    Mathematical rigor, proof gap and the validity of mathematical inference.Yacin Hamami - 2014 - Philosophia Scientiae 18 (1):7-26.
    Mathematical rigor is commonly formulated by mathematicians and philosophers using the notion of proof gap: a mathematical proof is rig­orous when there is no gaps in the mathematical reasoning of the proof. Any philosophical approach to mathematical rigor along this line requires then an account of what a proof gap is. However, the notion of proof gap makes sense only relatively to a given conception of valid mathematical reasoning, i.e., to a given conception of the validity of mathematical inference. A (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  18
    Euclid and His Twentieth Century Rivals: Diagrams in the Logic of Euclidean Geometry.Nathaniel Miller - 2007 - Center for the Study of Language and Inf.
    Twentieth-century developments in logic and mathematics have led many people to view Euclid’s proofs as inherently informal, especially due to the use of diagrams in proofs. In _Euclid and His Twentieth-Century Rivals_, Nathaniel Miller discusses the history of diagrams in Euclidean Geometry, develops a formal system for working with them, and concludes that they can indeed be used rigorously. Miller also introduces a diagrammatic computer proof system, based on this formal system. This volume will be of interest to mathematicians, computer (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  10.  86
    The end of argument: Knowledge and the internet.Simon Barker - 2000 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 33 (2):154-181.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The End of Argument: Knowledge and the InternetSimon Barker1. Fermat's last videoModern mathematics is nearly characterized by the use of rigorous proofs. This practice, the result of literally thousands of years of refinement, has brought to mathematics a clarity and reliability unmatched by any other science.(Jaffe and Quinn 1993, 1)The above passage illustrates how mathematicians have come to esteem rigorous argument as the most important feature of their subject. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  88
    Mathematical rigor and proof.Yacin Hamami - 2022 - Review of Symbolic Logic 15 (2):409-449.
    Mathematical proof is the primary form of justification for mathematical knowledge, but in order to count as a proper justification for a piece of mathematical knowl- edge, a mathematical proof must be rigorous. What does it mean then for a mathematical proof to be rigorous? According to what I shall call the standard view, a mathematical proof is rigorous if and only if it can be routinely translated into a formal proof. The standard view is almost an orthodoxy among contemporary (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  12.  78
    Proof Theory for Reasoning with Euler Diagrams: A Logic Translation and Normalization.Ryo Takemura - 2013 - Studia Logica 101 (1):157-191.
    Proof-theoretical notions and techniques, developed on the basis of sentential/symbolic representations of formal proofs, are applied to Euler diagrams. A translation of an Euler diagrammatic system into a natural deduction system is given, and the soundness and faithfulness of the translation are proved. Some consequences of the translation are discussed in view of the notion of free ride, which is mainly discussed in the literature of cognitive science as an account of inferential efficacy of diagrams. The translation enables us to (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  13.  14
    Proofs 101: an introduction to formal mathematics.Joseph Kirtland - 2020 - Boca Raton: CRC Press, Taylor & Francis Group.
    Proofs 101: An Introduction to Formal Mathematics serves as an introduction to proofs for mathematics majors who have completed the calculus sequence (at least Calculus I and II) and Linear Algebra. It prepares students for the proofs they will need to analyse and write, the axiomatic nature of mathematics, and the rigors of upper-level mathematics courses. Basic number theory, relations, functions, cardinality, and set theory will provide the material for the proofs and lay the foundation for a deeper understanding of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. A formal proof of the born rule from decision-theoretic assumptions [aka: How to Prove the Born Rule].David Wallace - 2010 - In Simon Saunders, Jonathan Barrett, Adrian Kent & David Wallace (eds.), Many Worlds?: Everett, Quantum Theory, & Reality. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    I develop the decision-theoretic approach to quantum probability, originally proposed by David Deutsch, into a mathematically rigorous proof of the Born rule in (Everett-interpreted) quantum mechanics. I sketch the argument informally, then prove it formally, and lastly consider a number of proposed ``counter-examples'' to show exactly which premises of the argument they violate. (This is a preliminary version of a chapter to appear --- under the title ``How to prove the Born Rule'' --- in Saunders, Barrett, Kent and Wallace, "Many (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  15.  39
    A Correctness Proof for Al-Barakāt’s Logical Diagrams.Wilfrid Hodges - 2023 - Review of Symbolic Logic 16 (2):369-384.
    In Baghdad in the mid twelfth century Abū al-Barakāt proposes a radical new procedure for finding the conclusions of premise-pairs in syllogistic logic, and for identifying those premise-pairs that have no conclusions. The procedure makes no use of features of the standard Aristotelian apparatus, such as conversions or syllogistic figures. In place of these al-Barakāt writes out pages of diagrams consisting of labelled horizontal lines. He gives no instructions and no proof that the procedure will yield correct results. So the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16. Proofs for a price: Tomorrow’s ultra-rigorous mathematical culture.Silvia De Toffoli - 2024 - Bulletin (New Series) of the American Mathematical Society 61 (3):395–410.
    Computational tools might tempt us to renounce complete cer- tainty. By forgoing of rigorous proof, we could get (very) probable results for a fraction of the cost. But is it really true that proofs (as we know and love them) can lead us to certainty? Maybe not. Proofs do not wear their correct- ness on their sleeve, and we are not infallible in checking them. This suggests that we need help to check our results. When our fellow mathematicians will be (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  65
    Logic Works: A Rigorous Introduction to Formal Logic.Lorne Falkenstein, Scott Stapleford & Molly Kao - 2021 - New York: Routledge. Edited by Scott Stapleford & Molly Kao.
    Logic Works is a critical and extensive introduction to logic. It asks questions about why systems of logic are as they are, how they relate to ordinary language and ordinary reasoning, and what alternatives there might be to classical logical doctrines. It considers how logical analysis can be applied to carefully represent the reasoning employed in academic and scientific work, better understand that reasoning, and identify its hidden premises. Aiming to be as much a reference work and handbook for further, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  10
    Words, Proofs, and Diagrams.David Barker-Plummer, David I. Beaver, Johan van Benthem & Patrick Scotto di Luzio (eds.) - 2002 - Center for the Study of Language and Inf.
    The past twenty years have witnessed extensive collaborative research between computer scientists, logicians, linguists, philosophers, and psychologists. These interdisciplinary studies stem from the realization that researchers drawn from all fields are studying the same problem. Specifically, a common concern amongst researchers today is how logic sheds light on the nature of information. Ancient questions concerning how humans communicate, reason and decide, and modern questions about how computers should communicate, reason and decide are of prime interest to researchers in various disciplines. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  33
    Proof theory for heterogeneous logic combining formulas and diagrams: proof normalization.Ryo Takemura - 2021 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 60 (7):783-813.
    We extend natural deduction for first-order logic (FOL) by introducing diagrams as components of formal proofs. From the viewpoint of FOL, we regard a diagram as a deductively closed conjunction of certain FOL formulas. On the basis of this observation, we first investigate basic heterogeneous logic (HL) wherein heterogeneous inference rules are defined in the styles of conjunction introduction and elimination rules of FOL. By examining what is a detour in our heterogeneous proofs, we discuss that an elimination-introduction pair of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  49
    Rigor and Structure.John P. Burgess - 2015 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press UK.
    While we are commonly told that the distinctive method of mathematics is rigorous proof, and that the special topic of mathematics is abstract structure, there has been no agreement among mathematicians, logicians, or philosophers as to just what either of these assertions means. John P. Burgess clarifies the nature of mathematical rigor and of mathematical structure, and above all of the relation between the two, taking into account some of the latest developments in mathematics, including the rise of experimental mathematics (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  21.  54
    Formal Ontology and Mathematics. A Case Study on the Identity of Proofs.Matteo Bianchetti & Giorgio Venturi - 2023 - Topoi 42 (1):307-321.
    We propose a novel, ontological approach to studying mathematical propositions and proofs. By “ontological approach” we refer to the study of the categories of beings or concepts that, in their practice, mathematicians isolate as fruitful for the advancement of their scientific activity (like discovering and proving theorems, formulating conjectures, and providing explanations). We do so by developing what we call a “formal ontology” of proofs using semantic modeling tools (like RDF and OWL) developed by the computer science community. In this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  64
    The Independence of the Parallel Postulate and Development of Rigorous Consistency Proofs.David J. Stump - 2007 - History and Philosophy of Logic 28 (1):19-30.
    I trace the development of arguments for the consistency of non-Euclidean geometries and for the independence of the parallel postulate, showing how the arguments become more rigorous as a formal conception of geometry is introduced. I analyze the kinds of arguments offered by Jules Hoüel in 1860-1870 for the unprovability of the parallel postulate and for the existence of non-Euclidean geometries, especially his reaction to the publication of Beltrami’s seminal papers, showing that Beltrami was much more concerned with the existence (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  14
    Formal Proofs in Mathematical Practice.Danielle Macbeth - 2024 - In Bharath Sriraman (ed.), Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Cham: Springer. pp. 2113-2135.
    Over the past half-century, formal, machine-executable proofs have been developed for an impressive range of mathematical theorems. Formalists argue that such proofs should be seen as providing the fully worked out proofs of which mathematicians’ proofs are sketches. Nonformalists argue that this conception of the relationship of formal to informal proofs cannot explain the fact that formal proofs lack essential virtues enjoyed by mathematicians’ proofs, the fact, for example, that formal proofs are not convincing and lack the explanatory power of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  93
    A Brief Proof of the Full Completeness of Shin’s Venn Diagram Proof System.Nathaniel Miller - 2006 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 35 (3):289-291.
    In an article in the Journal of Philosophical Logic in 1996, "Towards a Model Theory of Venn Diagrams,", Hammer and Danner proved the full completeness of Shin's formal system for reasoning with Venn Diagrams. Their proof is eight pages long. This note gives a brief five line proof of this same result, using connections between diagrammatic and sentential representations.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  75
    (1 other version)From Euclidean geometry to knots and nets.Brendan Larvor - 2017 - Synthese:1-22.
    This paper assumes the success of arguments against the view that informal mathematical proofs secure rational conviction in virtue of their relations with corresponding formal derivations. This assumption entails a need for an alternative account of the logic of informal mathematical proofs. Following examination of case studies by Manders, De Toffoli and Giardino, Leitgeb, Feferman and others, this paper proposes a framework for analysing those informal proofs that appeal to the perception or modification of diagrams or to the inspection or (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  26. The Relationship of Derivations in Artificial Languages to Ordinary Rigorous Mathematical Proof.J. Azzouni - 2013 - Philosophia Mathematica 21 (2):247-254.
    The relationship is explored between formal derivations, which occur in artificial languages, and mathematical proof, which occurs in natural languages. The suggestion that ordinary mathematical proofs are abbreviations or sketches of formal derivations is presumed false. The alternative suggestion that the existence of appropriate derivations in formal logical languages is a norm for ordinary rigorous mathematical proof is explored and rejected.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  27. Diagrams as sketches.Brice Halimi - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):387-409.
    This article puts forward the notion of “evolving diagram” as an important case of mathematical diagram. An evolving diagram combines, through a dynamic graphical enrichment, the representation of an object and the representation of a piece of reasoning based on the representation of that object. Evolving diagrams can be illustrated in particular with category-theoretic diagrams (hereafter “diagrams*”) in the context of “sketch theory,” a branch of modern category theory. It is argued that sketch theory provides a diagrammatic* theory of diagrams*, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  28.  56
    Reasoning with Sentences and Diagrams.Eric Hammer - 1994 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 35 (1):73-87.
    A formal system is studied having both sentences and diagrams as well-formed representations. Proofs in the system allow inference back and forth between sentences and diagrams, as well as between diagrams and diagrams, and between sentences and sentences. This sort of heterogeneous system is of interest because external representations other than linguistic ones occur commonly in actual reasoning in conjunction with language. Syntax, semantics, and rules of inference for the system are given and it is shown to be sound and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  29.  15
    The Philosophical Status of Diagrams.Mark Greaves - 2001 - Center for the Study of Language and Inf.
    This dissertation explores the reasons why structured graphics have been largely ignored in the representation and reasoning components of contemporary theories of axiomatic systems. In particular, it demonstrates that for the case of modern logic and geometry, there are systematic forces in the intellectual history of these disciplines which have driven the adoption of sentential representational styles over diagrammatic ones. These forces include: the changing views of the role of intuition in the procedures and formalisms of formal proof; the historical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  30.  17
    Proof and Consequence: An Introduction to Classical Logic with Simon and Simon Says.Ray Jennings & Nicole A. Friedrich - 2006 - Peterborough, CA: Broadview Press.
    Proof and Consequence is a rigorous, elegant introduction to classical first-order natural deductive logic; it provides an accurate and accessible first course in the study of formal systems. The text covers all the topics necessary for learning logic at the beginner and intermediate levels: this includes propositional and quantificational logic (using Suppes-style proofs) and extensive metatheory, as well as over 800 exercises. Proof and Consequence provides exclusive access to the software application Simon, an easily downloadable program designed to facilitate an (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  88
    Proof, rigour and informality : a virtue account of mathematical knowledge.Fenner Stanley Tanswell - 2016 - St Andrews Research Repository Philosophy Dissertations.
    This thesis is about the nature of proofs in mathematics as it is practiced, contrasting the informal proofs found in practice with formal proofs in formal systems. In the first chapter I present a new argument against the Formalist-Reductionist view that informal proofs are justified as rigorous and correct by corresponding to formal counterparts. The second chapter builds on this to reject arguments from Gödel's paradox and incompleteness theorems to the claim that mathematics is inherently inconsistent, basing my objections on (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  32. Diagrams and Natural Deduction: Theory and Pedagogy of Hyperproof.Ruth Eberle - 1995 - Dissertation, Indiana University
    The logical system Hyperproof and the computer implementation of it--both created by Jon Barwise and John Etchemendy--present a radical new approach to modeling and teaching about reasoning. Hyperproof is a heterogeneous proof system that uses both sentences and diagrams as steps in proofs. This dissertation addresses important logical, philosophical, and pedagogical issues that Hyperproof raises. We formalize the syntax and semantics of Hyperproof, show that the major inference rules are valid, and give completeness results for four subsystems of Hyperproof. We (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Reconciling Rigor and Intuition.Silvia De Toffoli - 2020 - Erkenntnis 86 (6):1783-1802.
    Criteria of acceptability for mathematical proofs are field-dependent. In topology, though not in most other domains, it is sometimes acceptable to appeal to visual intuition to support inferential steps. In previous work :829–842, 2014; Lolli, Panza, Venturi From logic to practice, Springer, Berlin, 2015; Larvor Mathematical cultures, Springer, Berlin, 2016) my co-author and I aimed at spelling out how topological proofs work on their own terms, without appealing to formal proofs which might be associated with them. In this article, I (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  34.  63
    Mathematical Explanations: An Analysis Via Formal Proofs and Conceptual Complexity.Francesca Poggiolesi - 2024 - Philosophia Mathematica 32 (2):145-176.
    This paper studies internal (or intra-)mathematical explanations, namely those proofs of mathematical theorems that seem to explain the theorem they prove. The goal of the paper is a rigorous analysis of these explanations. This will be done in two steps. First, we will show how to move from informal proofs of mathematical theorems to a formal presentation that involves proof trees, together with a decomposition of their elements; secondly we will show that those mathematical proofs that are regarded as having (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  38
    Internal Diagrams and Archetypal Reasoning in Category Theory.Eduardo Ochs - 2013 - Logica Universalis 7 (3):291-321.
    We can regard operations that discard information, like specializing to a particular case or dropping the intermediate steps of a proof, as projections, and operations that reconstruct information as liftings. By working with several projections in parallel we can make sense of statements like “Set is the archetypal Cartesian Closed Category”, which means that proofs about CCCs can be done in the “archetypal language” and then lifted to proofs in the general setting. The method works even when our archetypal language (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  84
    Review of J. Norman, After Euclid: Visual Reasoning and the Epistemology of Diagrams[REVIEW]F. Janet - 2007 - Philosophia Mathematica 15 (1):116-121.
    This monograph treats the important topic of the epistemology of diagrams in Euclidean geometry. Norman argues that diagrams play a genuine justificatory role in traditional Euclidean arguments, and he aims to account for these roles from a modified Kantian perspective. Norman considers himself a semi-Kantian in the following broad sense: he believes that Kant was right that ostensive constructions are necessary in order to follow traditional Euclidean proofs, but he wants to avoid appealing to Kantian a priori intuition as the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  38
    A Structured Argumentation Framework for Modeling Debates in the Formal Sciences.Marcos Cramer & Jérémie Dauphin - 2020 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 51 (2):219-241.
    Scientific research in the formal sciences comes in multiple degrees of formality: fully formal work; rigorous proofs that practitioners know to be formalizable in principle; and informal work like rough proof sketches and considerations about the advantages and disadvantages of various formal systems. This informal work includes informal and semi-formal debates between formal scientists, e.g. about the acceptability of foundational principles and proposed axiomatizations. In this paper, we propose to use the methodology of structured argumentation theory to produce a formal (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  92
    Local axioms in disguise: Hilbert on Minkowski diagrams.Ivahn Smadja - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):315-370.
    While claiming that diagrams can only be admitted as a method of strict proof if the underlying axioms are precisely known and explicitly spelled out, Hilbert praised Minkowski’s Geometry of Numbers and his diagram-based reasoning as a specimen of an arithmetical theory operating “rigorously” with geometrical concepts and signs. In this connection, in the first phase of his foundational views on the axiomatic method, Hilbert also held that diagrams are to be thought of as “drawn formulas”, and formulas as “written (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  39.  55
    The Eu Approach to Formalizing Euclid: A Response to “On the Inconsistency of Mumma’s Eu”.John Mumma - 2019 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 60 (3):457-480.
    In line with Ken Manders’s seminal account of Euclid’s diagrammatic method in the “The Euclidean Diagram,” two proof systems with a diagrammatic syntax have been advanced as formalizations of the method FG and Eu. In a paper examining Eu, Nathaniel Miller, the creator of FG, has identified a variety of technical problems with the formal details of Eu. This response shows how the problems are remedied.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  42
    Jesse Norman. After Euclid: Visual Reasoning and the Epistemology of Diagrams. Stanford: CSLI Publications, 2006. ISBN 1-57586-509-2 ; 1-57586-510-6 . Pp. vii +176. [REVIEW]Jesse Norman - 2007 - Philosophia Mathematica 15 (1):116-121.
    This monograph treats the important topic of the epistemology of diagrams in Euclidean geometry. Norman argues that diagrams play a genuine justificatory role in traditional Euclidean arguments, and he aims to account for these roles from a modified Kantian perspective. Norman considers himself a semi-Kantian in the following broad sense: he believes that Kant was right that ostensive constructions are necessary in order to follow traditional Euclidean proofs, but he wants to avoid appealing to Kantian a priori intuition as the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  18
    Temporal display of gestures in diagrammatic proof.Leclercq Bruno - 2021 - Metodo. International Studies in Phenomenology and Philosophy 9 (1):119-142.
    According to the deductivist view of mathematics which became the rule during the nineteenth century, formal proofs working with symbolic formulas replaced the intuitive knowledge that used to be gained by the step-by-step construction of geometric fgures and diagrams. Twentieth century epistemological refection on symbolic formulas and formal proofs, however, took them to be diagrams respectively exhibiting formal relations and transformations. The claim was also made that, for such diagrams to be proofs, temporal displays of transformations—and of other speech acts—were (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. All science as rigorous science: the principle of constructive mathematizability of any theory.Vasil Penchev - 2020 - Logic and Philosophy of Mathematics eJournal 12 (12):1-15.
    A principle, according to which any scientific theory can be mathematized, is investigated. Social science, liberal arts, history, and philosophy are meant first of all. That kind of theory is presupposed to be a consistent text, which can be exhaustedly represented by a certain mathematical structure constructively. In thus used, the term “theory” includes all hypotheses as yet unconfirmed as already rejected. The investigation of the sketch of a possible proof of the principle demonstrates that it should be accepted rather (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  9
    Proof in the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice: An Introduction.Joachim Frans & Bart Van Kerkhove - 2024 - In Bharath Sriraman (ed.), Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Cham: Springer. pp. 2037-2043.
    This introductory chapter sets the stage for an engaging exploration of the multifaceted concept of proof in the philosophy of mathematical practice. As a fundamental pillar of mathematics, proof has long been a subject of intense scrutiny for mathematicians and philosophers alike. Traditionally, proofs have been perceived as rigorous and deductive arguments, and this analysis was directed towards the notion of formal proof. However, recent developments have challenged this traditional view, highlighting the dynamic and evolving nature of mathematical proofs. In (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  36
    Gapless Lines and Gapless Proofs: Intersections and Continuity in Euclid’s Elements.Vincenzo De Risi - 2021 - Apeiron 54 (2):233-259.
    In this paper, I attempt a reconstruction of the theory of intersections in the geometry of Euclid. It has been well known, at least since the time of Pasch onward, that in the Elements there are no explicit principles governing the existence of the points of intersections between lines, so that in several propositions of Euclid the simple crossing of two lines (two circles, for instance) is regarded as the actual meeting of such lines, it being simply assumed that the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45.  34
    Proof, Semiotics, and the Computer: On the Relevance and Limitation of Thought Experiment in Mathematics.Johannes Lenhard - 2022 - Axiomathes 32 (1):29-42.
    This contribution defends two claims. The first is about why thought experiments are so relevant and powerful in mathematics. Heuristics and proof are not strictly and, therefore, the relevance of thought experiments is not contained to heuristics. The main argument is based on a semiotic analysis of how mathematics works with signs. Seen in this way, formal symbols do not eliminate thought experiments (replacing them by something rigorous), but rather provide a new stage for them. The formal world resembles the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. Constructive geometrical reasoning and diagrams.John Mumma - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):103-119.
    Modern formal accounts of the constructive nature of elementary geometry do not aim to capture the intuitive or concrete character of geometrical construction. In line with the general abstract approach of modern axiomatics, nothing is presumed of the objects that a geometric construction produces. This study explores the possibility of a formal account of geometric construction where the basic geometric objects are understood from the outset to possess certain spatial properties. The discussion is centered around Eu , a recently developed (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  47.  36
    The three dimensions of proofs.Yves Guiraud - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 141 (1):266-295.
    In this document, we study a 3-polygraphic translation for the proofs of SKS, a formal system for classical propositional logic. We prove that the free 3-category generated by this 3-polygraph describes the proofs of classical propositional logic modulo structural bureaucracy. We give a 3-dimensional generalization of Penrose diagrams and use it to provide several pictures of a proof. We sketch how local transformations of proofs yield a non contrived example of 4-dimensional rewriting.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. And so on... : reasoning with infinite diagrams.Solomon Feferman - 2012 - Synthese 186 (1):371-386.
    This paper presents examples of infinite diagrams whose use is more or less essential for understanding and accepting various proofs in higher mathematics. The significance of these is discussed with respect to the thesis that every proof can be formalized, and a “pre” form of this thesis that every proof can be presented in everyday statements-only form.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  49.  32
    On Euclidean diagrams and geometrical knowledge.Tamires Dal Magro & Manuel J. García-Pérez - 2019 - Theoria. An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science 34 (2):255.
    We argue against the claim that the employment of diagrams in Euclidean geometry gives rise to gaps in the proofs. First, we argue that it is a mistake to evaluate its merits through the lenses of Hilbert’s formal reconstruction. Second, we elucidate the abilities employed in diagram-based inferences in the Elements and show that diagrams are mathematically reputable tools. Finally, we complement our analysis with a review of recent experimental results purporting to show that, not only is the Euclidean diagram-based (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  8
    Granularity analysis for tutoring mathematical proofs.Marvin Schiller - 2011 - [Heidelberg]: AKA Verlag.
    Rigorous formal proof is one of the key techniques in the natural sciences, engineering, and of course also in the formal sciences. Progress in automated reasoning increasingly enables computer systems to support, and even teach, users to conduct formal a.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 975