Results for 'hyperbolic geometry'

952 found
Order:
  1.  96
    Axiomatizations of hyperbolic geometry: A comparison based on language and quantifier type complexity.Victor Pambuccian - 2002 - Synthese 133 (3):331 - 341.
    Hyperbolic geometry can be axiomatized using the notions of order andcongruence (as in Euclidean geometry) or using the notion of incidencealone (as in projective geometry). Although the incidence-based axiomatizationmay be considered simpler because it uses the single binary point-linerelation of incidence as a primitive notion, we show that it issyntactically more complex. The incidence-based formulation requires some axioms of the quantifier-type forallexistsforall, while the axiom system based on congruence and order can beformulated using only forallexists-axioms.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  2.  31
    Constructive Axiomatization of Plane Hyperbolic Geometry.Victor Pambuccian - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (4):475-488.
    We provide a universal axiom system for plane hyperbolic geometry in a firstorder language with two sorts of individual variables, ‘points’ and ‘lines’ , containing three individual constants, A0, A1, A2, standing for three non-collinear points, two binary operation symbols, φ and ι, with φ = l to be interpreted as ‘[MATHEMATICAL SCRIPT SMALL L] is the line joining A and B’ , and ι = P to be interpreted as [MATHEMATICAL SCRIPT SMALL L]P is the point of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  26
    Constructive Axiomatizations of Plane Absolute, Euclidean and Hyperbolic Geometry.Victor Pambuccian - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (1):129-136.
    In this paper we provide quantifier-free, constructive axiomatizations for 2-dimensional absolute, Euclidean, and hyperbolic geometry. The main novelty consists in the first-order languages in which the axiom systems are formulated.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  4.  44
    The Simplest Axiom System for Hyperbolic Geometry Revisited, Again.Jesse Alama - 2014 - Studia Logica 102 (3):609-615.
    Dependencies are identified in two recently proposed first-order axiom systems for plane hyperbolic geometry. Since the dependencies do not specifically concern hyperbolic geometry, our results yield two simpler axiom systems for absolute geometry.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  41
    The Simplest Axiom System for Plane Hyperbolic Geometry Revisited.Victor Pambuccian - 2011 - Studia Logica 97 (3):347 - 349.
    Using the axiom system provided by Carsten Augat in [1], it is shown that the only 6-variable statement among the axioms of the axiom system for plane hyperbolic geometry (in Tarski's language L B =), we had provided in [3], is superfluous. The resulting axiom system is the simplest possible one, in the sense that each axiom is a statement in prenex form about at most 5 points, and there is no axiom system consisting entirely of at most (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  58
    Correction to “Axiomatizations of Hyperbolic Geometry”.Victor Pambuccian - 2005 - Synthese 145 (3):497-497.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  90
    The Bifurcation Approach to Hyperbolic Geometry.Abraham A. Ungar - 2000 - Foundations of Physics 30 (8):1257-1282.
    The Thomas precession of relativity physics gives rise to important isometries in hyperbolic geometry that expose analogies with Euclidean geometry. These, in turn, suggest our bifurcation approach to hyperbolic geometry, according to which Euclidean geometry bifurcates into two mutually dual branches of hyperbolic geometry in its transition to non-Euclidean geometry. One of the two resulting branches turns out to be the standard hyperbolic geometry of Bolyai and Lobachevsky. The corresponding (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  52
    The simplest axiom system for plane hyperbolic geometry.Victor Pambuccian - 2004 - Studia Logica 77 (3):385 - 411.
    We provide a quantifier-free axiom system for plane hyperbolic geometry in a language containing only absolute geometrically meaningful ternary operations (in the sense that they have the same interpretation in Euclidean geometry as well). Each axiom contains at most 4 variables. It is known that there is no axiom system for plane hyperbolic consisting of only prenex 3-variable axioms. Changing one of the axioms, one obtains an axiom system for plane Euclidean geometry, expressed in the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  9.  70
    Thomas precession: Its underlying gyrogroup axioms and their use in hyperbolic geometry and relativistic physics.Abraham A. Ungar - 1997 - Foundations of Physics 27 (6):881-951.
    Gyrogroup theory and its applications is introduced and explored, exposing the fascinating interplay between Thomas precession of special relativity theory and hyperbolic geometry. The abstract Thomas precession, called Thomas gyration, gives rise to grouplike objects called gyrogroups [A, A. Ungar, Am. J. Phys.59, 824 (1991)] the underlying axions of which are presented. The prefix gyro extensively used in terms like gyrogroups, gyroassociative and gyrocommutative laws, gyroautomorphisms, and gyrosemidirect products, stems from their underlying abstract Thomas gyration. Thomas gyration is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10.  87
    From the Group SL(2, C) to Gyrogroups and Gyrovector Spaces and Hyperbolic Geometry.Jingling Chen & Abraham A. Ungar - 2001 - Foundations of Physics 31 (11):1611-1639.
    We show that the algebra of the group SL(2, C) naturally leads to the notion of gyrogroups and gyrovector spaces for dealing with the Lorentz group and its underlying hyperbolic geometry. The superiority of the use of the gyrogroup formalism over the use of the SL(2, C) formalism for dealing with the Lorentz group in some cases is indicated by (i) the validity of gyrogroups and gyrovector spaces in higher dimensions, by (ii) the analogies that they share with (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  27
    The complexity of plane hyperbolic incidence geometry is∀∃∀∃.Victor Pambuccian - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (3):277-281.
    We show that plane hyperbolic geometry, expressed in terms of points and the ternary relation of collinearity alone, cannot be expressed by means of axioms of complexity at most ∀∃∀, but that there is an axiom system, all of whose axioms are ∀∃∀∃ sentences. This remains true for Klingenberg's generalized hyperbolic planes, with arbitrary ordered fields as coordinate fields.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  12.  89
    Szmielew Wanda. Some metamathematical problems concerning elementary hyperbolic geometry. The axiomatic method with special reference to geometry and physics, Proceedings of an International Symposium held at the University of California, Berkeley, December 26, 1957-January 4, 1958. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam 1959, pp. 30–52. [REVIEW]Thomas Frayne - 1962 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 27 (2):237-238.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  32
    Corrigendum to “The complexity of plane hyperbolic incidence geometry is ∀∃∀∃”.Victor Pambuccian - 2008 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 54 (6):668-668.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  93
    The Hyperbolic Geometric Structure of the Density Matrix for Mixed State Qubits.Abraham A. Ungar - 2002 - Foundations of Physics 32 (11):1671-1699.
    Density matrices for mixed state qubits, parametrized by the Bloch vector in the open unit ball of the Euclidean 3-space, are well known in quantum computation theory. We bring the seemingly structureless set of all these density matrices under the umbrella of gyrovector spaces, where the Bloch vector is treated as a hyperbolic vector, called a gyrovector. As such, this article catalizes and supports interdisciplinary research spreading from mathematical physics to algebra and geometry. Gyrovector spaces are mathematical objects (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  51
    Extension of trigonometric and hyperbolic functions to vectorial arguments and its application to the representation of rotations and Lorentz transformations.H. Yamasaki - 1983 - Foundations of Physics 13 (11):1139-1154.
    The use of the axial vector representing a three-dimensional rotation makes the rotation representation much more compact by extending the trigonometric functions to vectorial arguments. Similarly, the pure Lorentz transformations are compactly treated by generalizing a scalar rapidity to a vector quantity in spatial three-dimensional cases and extending hyperbolic functions to vectorial arguments. A calculation of the Wigner rotation simplified by using the extended functions illustrates the fact that the rapidity vector space obeys hyperbolic geometry. New representations (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  41
    Distance geometry and geometric algebra.Andreas W. M. Dress & Timothy F. Havel - 1993 - Foundations of Physics 23 (10):1357-1374.
    As part of his program to unify linear algebra and geometry using the language of Clifford algebra, David Hestenes has constructed a (well-known) isomorphism between the conformal group and the orthogonal group of a space two dimensions higher, thus obtaining homogeneous coordinates for conformal geometry.(1) In this paper we show that this construction is the Clifford algebra analogue of a hyperbolic model of Euclidean geometry that has actually been known since Bolyai, Lobachevsky, and Gauss, and we (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  96
    From Pythagoras To Einstein: The Hyperbolic Pythagorean Theorem. [REVIEW]Abraham A. Ungar - 1998 - Foundations of Physics 28 (8):1283-1321.
    A new form of the Hyperbolic Pythagorean Theorem, which has a striking intuitive appeal and offers a strong contrast to its standard form, is presented. It expresses the square of the hyperbolic length of the hypotenuse of a hyperbolic right-angled triangle as the “Einstein sum” of the squares of the hyperbolic lengths of the other two sides, Fig. 1, thus completing the long path from Pythagoras to Einstein. Following the pioneering work of Varičak it is well (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18.  9
    Quadrature arithmétique du cercle, de l'ellipse et de l'hyperbole et la trigonométrie sans tables trigonométriques qui en est le corollaire.Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz - 2004 - Vrin.
    En 1676, alors qu'il sejourne encore a Paris, Leibniz entreprend de composer un volumineux traite qui restera sans doute l'un de ses ecrits mathematiques les plus fortement charpentes: La quadrature arithmetique du cercle, de l'ellipse et de l'hyperbole et la trigonometrie sans tables qui en est le corollaire. Ce traite se presente comme un abrege exhaustif de la geometrie infinitesimale, dont Leibniz avait pu esperer qu'elle lui ouvrirait les portes de l'Academie des Sciences. Cependant, contraint de quitter la capitale avant (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  11
    Cognitive and Applicative Universality of Synthetic Geometry Knowledge.Sergio Aramburu - 2024 - Global Philosophy 34 (1):1-15.
    Geometric statements are expressions of natural language with descriptive meaning, since they refer to things such as triangles, and to their characteristics. It is shown, following statements by authors such as Carnap (Philosophical foundations of physics) that geometric meanings are not factual, but mathematical, so that it is not geometric theories that apply, but geometrically interpreted factual theories. Under the Euclidean paradigm, the object of study of geometry was space, but the theoretical pluralism that replaced it resulted in the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  49
    The Relativistic Geometry and Dynamics of Electrons.M. F. Atiyah & J. Malkoun - 2018 - Foundations of Physics 48 (2):199-208.
    Atiyah and Sutcliffe made a number of conjectures about configurations of N distinct points in hyperbolic 3-space, arising from ideas of Berry and Robbins. In this paper we prove all these conjectures, purely geometrically, but we also provide a physical interpretation in terms of Electrons.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  55
    The Bloch Gyrovector.Jing-Ling Chen & Abraham A. Ungar - 2002 - Foundations of Physics 32 (4):531-565.
    Hyperbolic vectors are called gyrovectors. We show that the Bloch vector of quantum mechanics is a gyrovector. The Bures fidelity between two states of a qubit is generated by two Bloch vectors. Treating these as gyrovectors rather than vectors results in our novel expression for the Bures fidelity, expressed in terms of its two generating Bloch gyrovectors. Taming the Thomas precession of Einstein's special theory of relativity led to the advent of the theory of gyrogroups and gyrovector spaces. Gyrovector (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. On the geometry of quantum correlations.Itamar Pitowsky - unknown
    Consider the set Q of quantum correlation vectors for two observers, each with two possible binary measurements. Quadric (hyperbolic) inequalities which are satis…ed by every q 2 Q are proved, and equality holds on a two dimensional manifold consisting of the local boxes, and all..
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  9
    The Insufficiency of Traditional Platonism from the Viewpoint of Incompatible Mathematical Theories.János Tanács - 2018 - Proceedings of the XXIII World Congress of Philosophy 56:47-51.
    The paper distinguishes two types of Platonist approach, namely the Traditional one and the Robust one. In relation to this distinction I am going to argue that if the ontology of mathematics is intended to be defended plausibly in a Platonist way then this cannot be done according to the Traditional version. This will draw our attention to the plausibility of the Robust version. The plausibility of the two versions of Platonism will be examined in relation to one of the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  67
    Quantum logic and the classical propositional calculus.Othman Qasim Malhas - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (3):834-841.
    In much the same way that it is possible to construct a model of hyperbolic geometry in the Euclidean plane, it is possible to model quantum logic within the classical propositional calculus.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  14
    Styles of Discourse.Ioannis Vandoulakis & Tatiana Denisova (eds.) - 2021 - Kraków: Instytut Filozofii, Uniwersytet Jagielloński w Krakowie.
    The volume starts with the paper of Lynn Maurice Ferguson Arnold, former Premier of South Australia and former Minister of Education of Australia, concerning the Exposition Internationale des Arts et Techniques dans la Vie Moderne (International Exposition of Art and Technology in Modern Life) that was held from 25 May to 25 November 1937 in Paris, France. The organization of the world exhibition had placed the Nazi German and the Soviet pavilions directly across from each other. Many papers are devoted (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  1
    So Called Newton’s Inertia Law.Hikmat Vazirov & Fikrat Vazirov-Kangarli - 2024 - Metafizika 7 (4):49-60.
    The article is devoted to the justification of the law of inertia. It is often called Newton's first law. It was established that this is not a law, but a postulate. Modern definitions of this law are given. It turned out that well -known definitions of this law are similar to each other. It is shown that this law before Newton was formulated by Descartes, Balillians, Ballo and Galileo. The ontology and philosophical significance of the category "cause" are considered. It (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  15
    Historical development of Teichmüller theory.Athanase Papadopoulos & Lizhen Ji - 2013 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 67 (2):119-147.
    Originally, the expression “Teichmüller theory” referred to the theory that Oswald Teichmüller developed on deformations and on moduli spaces of marked Riemann surfaces. This theory is not an isolated field in mathematics. At different stages of its development, it received strong impetuses from analysis, geometry, and algebraic topology, and it had a major impact on other fields, including low-dimensional topology, algebraic topology, hyperbolic geometry, geometric group theory, representations of discrete groups in Lie groups, symplectic geometry, topological (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28. Firstness, evolution and the absolute in Peirce's Spinoza.Shannon Dea - 2008 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 44 (4):pp. 603-628.
    Inspired by Peirce’s repeated claim in the final decade of his life that Spinoza was a pragmati(ci)st, this article examines whether or not Peirce also believed that Spinoza’s metaphysics leaves room for Firstness. He engaged this issue explicitly in his third “Lecture on Pragmatism” (1903), listing Spinoza’s among the metaphysics that include Firstness, Secondness and Thirdness. Moreover, over a decade earlier, in the context of his exploration of hyperbolic geometry and the evolutionary cosmology that he regarded as corresponding (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  66
    Midpoints in gyrogroups.Abraham A. Ungar - 1996 - Foundations of Physics 26 (10):1277-1328.
    The obscured Thomas precessionof the special theory of relativity (STR) has been soared into prominence by exposing the mathematical structure, called a gyrogroup,to which it gives rise [A. A. Ungar, Amer. J. Phys.59,824 (1991)], and the role that it plays in the study of Lorentz groups [A. A. Ungar, Amer. J. Phys.60,815 (1992); A. A. Ungar, J. Math. Phys.35,1408 (1994); A. A. Ungar, J. Math. Phys.35,1881 (1994)]. Thomas gyrationresults from the abstraction of Thomas precession.As such, its study sheds light on (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30. Real Examples of NeutroGeometry & AntiGeometry.Florentin Smarandache - 2023 - Neutrosophic Sets and Systems 55.
    For the classical Geometry, in a geometrical space, all items (concepts, axioms, theorems, etc.) are totally (100%) true. But, in the real world, many items are not totally true. The NeutroGeometry is a geometrical space that has some items that are only partially true (and partially indeterminate, and partially false), and no item that is totally false. The AntiGeometry is a geometrical space that has some item that are totally (100%) false. While the Non-Euclidean Geometries [hyperbolic and elliptic (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. REVIEW OF 1988. Saccheri, G. Euclides Vindicatus (1733), edited and translated by G. B. Halsted, 2nd ed. (1986), in Mathematical Reviews MR0862448. 88j:01013.John Corcoran - 1988 - MATHEMATICAL REVIEWS 88 (J):88j:01013.
    Girolamo Saccheri (1667--1733) was an Italian Jesuit priest, scholastic philosopher, and mathematician. He earned a permanent place in the history of mathematics by discovering and rigorously deducing an elaborate chain of consequences of an axiom-set for what is now known as hyperbolic (or Lobachevskian) plane geometry. Reviewer's remarks: (1) On two pages of this book Saccheri refers to his previous and equally original book Logica demonstrativa (Turin, 1697) to which 14 of the 16 pages of the editor's "Introduction" (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Mathematics, Method and Metaphysics: Essays Towards a Genealogy of Modern Thought.David R. Lachterman - 1984 - Dissertation, The Pennsylvania State University
    The generative and governing "idea" of radical modernity is spawned by the technique of mathematical construction deployed and interpreted by the major early-modern thinkers and their legatees. ;Chapter I is a survey of this legacy as it appears in Vico, Kant, Fichte, Marx and Nietzsche and in the post-Nietzschean inheritance of contemporary philosophy, hyperbolic in the case of Derrida et al., elliptical, in the case of Carnap and Goodman. ;In Chapter II I try to show how the pre-modern mathematical (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  7
    The Years of Consolidation 1634–1640.Stephen Gaukroger - 1995 - In Descartes: An Intellectual Biography. Oxford, GB: Clarendon Press.
    Discusses various works of Descartes's and their reception, including objections to them and his response to those objections. Météors deals with meteorology, which includes a corpuscular model of light, an account of refraction, and vision, and its links with optical instruments; the Dioptrique is a practical treatise on the construction of these optical instruments; and Géométrie compares arithmetic with geometry and extends Descartes's treatment of the Pappus problem and the classification of curves. The organization of material in the Discours (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34. Harald Schwaetzer.Bunte Geometrie - 2009 - In Klaus Reinhardt, Harald Schwaetzer & Franz-Bernhard Stammkötter (eds.), Heymericus de Campo: Philosophie Und Theologie Im 15. Jahrhundert. Roderer. pp. 28--183.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Vigier III.Spin Foam Spinors & Fundamental Space-Time Geometry - 2000 - Foundations of Physics 30 (1).
  36.  10
    D'Erehwon à l'Antre du Cyclope.Géométrie de L'Incommunicable & La Folie - 1988 - In Barry Smart (ed.), Michel Foucault: critical assessments. New York: Routledge.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Instruction to Authors 279–283 Index to Volume 20 285–286.Christian Lotz, Corinne Painter, Sebastian Luft, Harry P. Reeder, Semantic Texture, Luciano Boi, Questions Regarding Husserlian Geometry, James R. Mensch & Postfoundational Phenomenology Husserlian - 2004 - Husserl Studies 20:285-286.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Time and physical geometry.Hilary Putnam - 1967 - Journal of Philosophy 64 (8):240-247.
  39. On the relationship between plane and solid geometry.Andrew Arana & Paolo Mancosu - 2012 - Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (2):294-353.
    Traditional geometry concerns itself with planimetric and stereometric considerations, which are at the root of the division between plane and solid geometry. To raise the issue of the relation between these two areas brings with it a host of different problems that pertain to mathematical practice, epistemology, semantics, ontology, methodology, and logic. In addition, issues of psychology and pedagogy are also important here. To our knowledge there is no single contribution that studies in detail even one of the (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  40. Edmund Husserl’s ‘Origin of Geometry’: An Introduction.Jacques Derrida - 1978 - University of Nebraska.
    Derrida's introduction to his French translation of Husserl's essay "The Origin of Geometry," arguing that although Husserl privileges speech over writing in an account of meaning and the development of scientific knowledge, this privilege is in fact unstable.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  41. Relativity and Geometry.R. Torretti - 1985 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (1):100-104.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  42. Conceptual Spaces: The Geometry of Thought.Peter Gärdenfors - 2000 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 64 (1):180-181.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   340 citations  
  43.  13
    The Completeness of Scientific Theories: On the Derivation of Empirical Indicators within a Theoretical Framework: The Case of Physical Geometry.Martin Carrier - 2012 - Springer.
    Earlier in this century, many philosophers of science (for example, Rudolf Carnap) drew a fairly sharp distinction between theory and observation, between theoretical terms like 'mass' and 'electron', and observation terms like 'measures three meters in length' and 'is _2° Celsius'. By simply looking at our instruments we can ascertain what numbers our measurements yield. Creatures like mass are different: we determine mass by calculation; we never directly observe a mass. Nor an electron: this term is introduced in order to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  44.  70
    Algebraic Fields and the Dynamical Approach to Physical Geometry.Tushar Menon - 2019 - Philosophy of Science 86 (5):1273-1283.
    Brown and Pooley’s ‘dynamical approach’ to physical theories asserts, in opposition to the orthodox position on physical geometry, that facts about physical geometry are grounded in, or explained by, facts about dynamical fields, not the other way round. John Norton has claimed that the proponent of the dynamical approach is illicitly committed to spatiotemporal presumptions in ‘constructing’ space-time from facts about dynamical symmetries. In this article, I present an abstract, algebraic formulation of field theories and demonstrate that the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  45.  97
    Axiomatizability of geometry without points.Andrzej Grzegorczyk - 1960 - Synthese 12 (2-3):228 - 235.
  46.  27
    (1 other version)The Foundations of Geometry.David Hilbert - 1899 - Open Court Company (This Edition Published 1921).
    §30. Significance of Desargues's theorem . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 64 CHAPTER VI. PASCAL'S THEOREM. §31. ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  47. Kant on real definitions in geometry.Jeremy Heis - 2014 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 44 (5-6):605-630.
    This paper gives a contextualized reading of Kant's theory of real definitions in geometry. Though Leibniz, Wolff, Lambert and Kant all believe that definitions in geometry must be ‘real’, they disagree about what a real definition is. These disagreements are made vivid by looking at two of Euclid's definitions. I argue that Kant accepted Euclid's definition of circle and rejected his definition of parallel lines because his conception of mathematics placed uniquely stringent requirements on real definitions in (...). Leibniz, Wolff and Lambert thus accept definitions that Kant rejects because they assign weaker roles to real definitions. (shrink)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  48. Space, points and mereology. On foundations of point-free Euclidean geometry.Rafał Gruszczyński & Andrzej Pietruszczak - 2009 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 18 (2):145-188.
    This article is devoted to the problem of ontological foundations of three-dimensional Euclidean geometry. Starting from Bertrand Russell’s intuitions concerning the sensual world we try to show that it is possible to build a foundation for pure geometry by means of the so called regions of space. It is not our intention to present mathematically developed theory, but rather demonstrate basic assumptions, tools and techniques that are used in construction of systems of point-free geometry and topology by (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  49. Natural number and natural geometry.Elizabeth S. Spelke - 2011 - In Stanislas Dehaene & Elizabeth Brannon (eds.), Space, Time and Number in the Brain: Searching for the Foundations of Mathematical Thought. Oxford University Press. pp. 287--317.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  50.  66
    The Relation of Space and Geometry to Experience.Norbert Weiner - 1922 - The Monist 32 (2):200-247.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 952