Results for 'mental predicates'

961 found
Order:
  1.  55
    Cartesians, Strawsonians and the univocal meaning of mental predicates.Yakir Levin - 2004 - Acta Analytica 19 (32):91-106.
    The paper examines the Cartesian and the Strawsonian answers to the question of why self-applied and other-applied mental predicates mean the same. While these answers relate to different, complementary aspects of this question, they seem and are usually considered as incompatible. Indeed, their apparent incompatibility constitutes a major objection to the Cartesian answer. A primary aim of the paper is to show that the Strawsonian answer does not pose a real problem to the Cartesian answer. Unlike other attempts (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  56
    The ascription of mental predicates.Robert Rosthal - 1961 - Philosophical Studies 12 (1-2):20-27.
  3.  16
    Conditionals and Egocentric Mental Predicates.A. Boguslawski - 1998 - Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 62:29-38.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. The Logic of Criteria with Special Application to Mental Predicates.Martin Deitsch - 1969 - Dissertation, University of Michigan
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Some Empirical Justification of the Mental-Predicate-Logic Model.Yinguri Yang, Martin D. S. Braine & David P. O'Brien - 1998 - In Yinguri Yang, Martin D. S. Braine & David P. O'Brien, [no title]. Lawerence Erlbaum. pp. 333-365.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  6.  15
    Mental states via possessive predication: the grammar of possessive experiencer complex predicates in Persian.Ryan Walter Smith - 2024 - Natural Language Semantics 32 (3):359-402.
    Persian possesses a number of stative complex predicates with _dâshtan_ ‘to have’ that express certain kinds of mental state. I propose that these _possessive experiencer complex predicates_ be given a formal semantic treatment involving possession of a portion of an abstract quality by an individual, as in the analysis of property concept lexemes due to Francez and Koontz-Garboden (Language 91(3):533–563, 2015 ; Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 34:93–106, 2016 ; Semantics and morphosyntactic variation: Qualities and the grammar of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  27
    Review: A Predicate Operator Theory of Mental Predicates[REVIEW]Richard E. Aquila - 1991 - Behavior and Philosophy 19 (1):101 - 108.
  8. (1 other version)Predication and Two Concepts of Judgment.Indrek Reiland - 2019 - In Brian Andrew Ball & Christoph Schuringa, The Act and Object of Judgment: Historical and Philosophical Perspectives. New York: Routledge. pp. 217-234.
    Recently, there’s been a lot of interest in a research program that tries to understand propositional representation in terms of the subject’s performance of sub-propositional mental acts like reference and predication (e. g. Burge 2010, Hanks 2015, Soames 2010, 2015). For example, on one version of the view, for a subject to predicate the property of being a composer of Arvo just is what it is to perform the to the basic propositional act of judging that Arvo is a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  9. Predication in Conceptual Realism.Nino B. Cocchiarella - 2013 - Axiomathes 23 (2):301-321.
    Conceptual realism begins with a conceptualist theory of the nexus of predication in our speech and mental acts, a theory that explains the unity of those acts in terms of their referential and predicable aspects. This theory also contains as an integral part an intensional realism based on predicate nominalization and a reflexive abstraction in which the intensional contents of our concepts are “object”-ified, and by which an analysis of predication with intensional verbs can be given. Through a second (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10. The neural basis of predicate-argument structure.James R. Hurford - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (3):261-283.
    Neural correlates exist for a basic component of logical formulae, PREDICATE(x). Vision and audition research in primates and humans shows two independent neural pathways; one locates objects in body-centered space, the other attributes properties, such as colour, to objects. In vision these are the dorsal and ventral pathways. In audition, similarly separable “where” and “what” pathways exist. PREDICATE(x) is a schematic representation of the brain's integration of the two processes of delivery by the senses of the location of an arbitrary (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  11. William Crathorn on Predication and Mental Language.Aurélien Robert - unknown
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  50
    Attributing Psychological Predicates to Non-human Animals: Literalism and its Limits.Andrés Crelier - 2023 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 14 (4):1309-1328.
    In this essay, I deal with the problem of the attribution of psychological predicates to non-human animals. The first section illustrates three research topics where it has become scientifically legitimate to explain the conduct of non-human animals by means of the attribution of psychological predicates. The second section discusses several philosophical objections to the legitimacy of such attributions provided by central thinkers from the last decades. I try to show that these objections —which are related among other questions (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13. A truth predicate in the object language.William G. Lycan - 2012 - In Gerhard Preyer, Donald Davidson on truth, meaning, and the mental. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    The semantic paradoxes arise when the range of the quantifiers in the object language is too generous in certain ways. But it is not really clear how unfair to Urdu or to Hindi it would be to view the range of their quantifiers as insufficient to yield an explicit definition of ‗true-in-Urdu‘ or ‗true-in- Hindi‘. Or, to put the matter in another, if not more serious, way, there may in the nature of the case always be something we grasp in (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  27
    The suppression task and first‐order predicate calculus.Miguel López-Astorga - 2023 - Theoria 89 (6):800-810.
    The suppression task challenges classical logic. Classical logic is monotonic. However, in the suppression task, an inference with the form of modus ponendo ponens is inhibited by adding a new premise. Several explanations have been given to account for this fact. The present paper indicates three of them as examples: that of the theory of mental models, that based on logic programming and closed world assumption, and that referring to Carnap's concept of state‐descriptions. Besides, the paper offers one more (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  52
    The material basis of predication and other concepts.Andrew Newman - 1988 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66 (3):331 – 347.
    Immanent realism is a justly popular theory of universals which is incomplete. It is not good enough to say that all universals are equally real and all equally inhere in objects. Concepts come in hierarchies, For example: "colored," "red" and "claret," where "claret" is a shade of red. Only those at the very bottom of the hierarchy exist in objects, And are rightly called properties. Only properties have causality as a criterion of identity. Frege's functional account of concepts can be (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16. A truth predicate in the object language.William G. Lycan - 2012 - In Gerhard Preyer, Donald Davidson on truth, meaning, and the mental. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Representational limitations of the one-place predicate.Peter F. Dominey - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (3):291-292.
    In the context of Hurford's claim that “some feature of language structure maps onto a feature of primitive mental representations,” I will argue that Hurford's focus on 1-place predicates as the basis of the “mental representations of situations in the world” is problematic, particularly with respect to spatiotemporal events. A solution is proposed.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Mental Imagery and Polysemy Processing.Michelle Liu - 2022 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 29 (5-6):176-189.
    Recent research in psycholinguistics suggests that language processing frequently involves mental imagery. This paper focuses on visual imagery and discusses two issues regarding the processing of polysemous words (i.e. words with multiple related meanings or senses) – co-predication and sense-relatedness. It aims to show how mental imagery can illuminate these two issues.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  19.  66
    Review of Radu J. Bogdan’s Predicative Minds: The Social Ontogeny of Propositional Thinking[REVIEW]Itay Shani - 2011 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 41 (4):596-605.
    In this book, Bogdan offers an empirically informed theory of the emergence and nature of predication with unmistakable pragmatic and developmental overtones. While the emphasis on psycho-pragmatic and developmental factors is most welcome, and while the discussion is informed and informative, Bogdan’s thesis suffers from some major weaknesses, in particular philosophical ones. Chief among these is an insufficient clarity with regard to the problem domain being addressed: Bogdan professes to offer a theory of predication as a general mental faculty (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  73
    The neural representation of spatial predicate-argument structures in sign language.Bencie Woll - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (3):300-301.
    Evidence from studies of the processing of topographic and classifier constructions in sign language sentences provides a model of how a mental scene description can be represented linguistically, but it also raises questions about how this can be related to spatial linguistic descriptions in spoken languages and their processing. This in turn provides insights into models of the evolution of language.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Mental properties.John Heil & David Robb - 2003 - American Philosophical Quarterly 40 (3):175-196.
    It is becoming increasingly clear that the deepest problems currently exercising philosophers of mind arise from an ill-begotten ontology, in particular, a mistaken ontology of properties. After going through some preliminaries, we identify three doctrines at the heart of this mistaken ontology: (P) For each distinct predicate, “F”, there exists one, and only one, property, F, such that, if “F” is applicable to an object a, then “F” is applicable in virtue of a’s being F. (U) Properties are universals, not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  22. Mental simulation and language comprehension: The case of copredication.Michelle Liu - 2024 - Mind and Language 39 (1):2-21.
    Empirical evidence suggests that perceptual‐motor simulations are often constitutively involved in language comprehension. Call this “the simulation view of language comprehension”. This article applies the simulation view to illuminate the much‐discussed phenomenon of copredication, where a noun permits multiple predications which seem to select different senses of the noun simultaneously. On the proposed account, the (in)felicitousness of a copredicational sentence is closely associated with the perceptual simulations that the language user deploys in comprehending the sentence.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  23. Are mental representations underdeterminacy-free?Claudia Picazo Jaque - 2019 - Synthese 196 (2):633-654.
    According to some views, natural language suffers from underdeterminacy, but thought doesn’t. According to the underdeterminacy claim, sentence types underdetermine the truth-conditions of sentence tokens. In particular, the semantics of a predicate type seems to underdetermine the satisfaction conditions of its tokens. By contrast, mental representation-types are supposed to determine the truth-conditions of its tokens. In this paper I critically examine these mixed views. First, I argue that the arguments supporting the indispensability of including in one’s theory mental (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24. Mental health and mental illness: Some problems of definition and concept formation.Ruth Macklin - 1972 - Philosophy of Science 39 (3):341-365.
    In recent years there has been considerable discussion and controversy concerning the concepts of mental health and mental illness. The controversy has centered around the problem of providing criteria for an adequate conception of mental health and illness, as well as difficulties in specifying a clear and workable system for the classification, understanding, and treatment of psychological and emotional disorders. In this paper I shall examine a cluster of these complex and important issues, focusing on attempts to (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  25. Hylomorphism and Mental Causation.William Jaworski - 2005 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 79:201-216.
    Mind-body problems are predicated on two things: a distinction between the mental and the physical, and premises that make it difficult to see how the two are related. Before Descartes there were no mind-body problems of the sort now forming the stock in trade of philosophy of mind. One possible explanation for this is that pre-Cartesian philosophers working in the Aristotelian tradition had a different way of understanding the mental-physical distinction, the nature of causation, and the character of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26. Mental Substances.Tim Crane - 2003 - In Anthony O'Hear, Minds and Persons. Cambridge University Press. pp. 229-250.
    Philosophers of mind typically conduct their discussions in terms of mental events, mental processes, mental properties, mental states – but rarely in terms of minds themselves. Sometimes this neglect is explicitly acknowledged. Donald Davidson, for example, writes that ‘there are no such things as minds, but people have mental properties, which is to say that certain psychological predicates are true of them. These properties are constantly changing, and such changes are mental events’.2 Hilary (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  27. Mental causation from the top-down.William Jaworski - 2006 - Erkenntnis 65 (2):277-299.
    Dual-attribute theories are alleged to face a problem with mental causation which commits them to either epiphenomenalism or overdetermination – neither of which is attractive. The problem, however, is predicated on assumptions about psychophysical relations that dual-attribute theorists are not obliged to accept. I explore one way they can solve the problem by rejecting those assumptions.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  28.  61
    The mental representation of universal quantifiers.Tyler Knowlton, Paul Pietroski, Justin Halberda & Jeffrey Lidz - 2022 - Linguistics and Philosophy 45 (4):911-941.
    A sentence like every circle is blue might be understood in terms of individuals and their properties or in terms of a relation between groups. Relatedly, theorists can specify the contents of universally quantified sentences in first-order or second-order terms. We offer new evidence that this logical first-order vs. second-order distinction corresponds to a psychologically robust individual vs. group distinction that has behavioral repercussions. Participants were shown displays of dots and asked to evaluate sentences with each, every, or all combined (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  29.  33
    Acerca da taxonomia do mental para contextos que requerem neutralidade.Filipe Lazzeri - 2013 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 16 (3):365-392.
    Ordinary psychological predicates, and the phenomena we report to by means of them, can be grouped together into different categories. For instance, it is usual to group together phenomena such as belief and expectancy in a category of ‘propositional attitudes’, whereas sensations, like pain and itch, in a distinct one. Which taxonomy of the mental would be plausible to be adopted in contexts such as those of introductory books to the philosophy of mind, i.e., when we need to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  36
    Representing, Running, and Revising Mental Models: A Computational Model.Scott Friedman, Kenneth Forbus & Bruce Sherin - 2018 - Cognitive Science 42 (4):1110-1145.
    People use commonsense science knowledge to flexibly explain, predict, and manipulate the world around them, yet we lack computational models of how this commonsense science knowledge is represented, acquired, utilized, and revised. This is an important challenge for cognitive science: Building higher order computational models in this area will help characterize one of the hallmarks of human reasoning, and it will allow us to build more robust reasoning systems. This paper presents a novel assembled coherence theory of human conceptual change, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31. Propositional Attitudes and Mental Acts.Indrek Reiland - 2012 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 1 (3):239-245.
    Peter Hanks and Scott Soames have recently developed similar views of propositional attitudes on which they consist at least partly of being disposed to perform mental acts. Both think that to believe a proposition is at least partly to be disposed to perform the primitive propositional act: one the performance of which is part of the performance of any other propositional act. However, they differ over whether the primitive act is the forceless entertaining or the forceful judging. In this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  32. Analogy and Mental Representation: A Solution to the Mind-Body Problem Based on the Philosophy of Wilfrid Sellars.William W. Davis - 1981 - Dissertation, University of Kansas
    In this dissertation, I provide the logical foundation for a solution to the mind-body problem, a solution which is directly based upon Wilfrid Sellars' analogical theory of thought and sensation. Chapters I-IV are devoted to an interpretation, analysis, and constructive criticism of Sellars' notions of the inner thought episode and the sensing state. My analysis is offered in support of three general contentions: I argue that the postulation of inner thought episodes and sensing states is necessary for adequate explanations of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  49
    Jerónimo Pardo on the Unity of Mental Propositions.Paloma Pérez-Ilzarbe - 2009 - In Joël Biard, Le langage mental du Moyen Âge à l'Âge Classique. Peeters Publishers.
    Originally motivated by a sophism, Pardo's discussion about the unity of mental propositions allows him to elaborate on his ideas about the nature of propositions. His option for a non-composite character of mental propositions is grounded in an original view about syncategorems: propositions have a syncategorematic signification, which allows them to signify aliquid aliqualiter, just by virtue of the mental copula, without the need of any added categorematic element. Pardo's general claim about the simplicity of mental (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  34.  18
    Existence does not Have any Extension: Sohrawardi\'s Theory about Existence not Having any Real Extension and its Usage in the Realm of the Necessary Being through Itself.R. Akbari - 2012 - Metaphysics (University of Isfahan) 3 (11):33-48.
    Theories about the dawn of "principality of existence" or "principality of quiddity" stand in the realm of "confusion of term and concept fallacy". It is true that asalat as a term appeared for the first time in Mirdamad's works such as Taqwim al-Iman to mention the problem of principality of existence, but we should notice that its meaning as a concept can be tracked in Suhrawadi's works. If by the term asalat we mean having real extension, as it is used (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. On What is Effable.Delia Belleri - 2013 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 2 (4):341-349.
    The Effability thesis has it that all propositions can be encoded by a sentence. By contrast, the Ineffability thesis has it that no proposition can be encoded by a sentence. In this article, I undermine an important motivation for the Ineffability thesis and advance a proposal concerning what is effable and what is not. My strategy will be as follows: First, I'll note that the Ineffability thesis assumes that propositions/thoughts are determinate. I'll point out that propositions/thoughts qua the things we (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36. Supposition and truth in ockham's mental language.Mikko Yrjönsuuri - 1997 - Topoi 16 (1):15-25.
    In this paper, Ockham's theory of an ideal language of thought is used to illuminate problems of interpretation of his theory of truth. The twentieth century idea of logical form is used for finding out what kinds of atomic sentences there are in OckhamÕs mental language. It turns out that not only the theory of modes of supposition, but also the theory of supposition in general is insufficient as a full theory of truth. Rather, the theory of supposition is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  12
    (1 other version)Is Menkiti’s Normative Personhood Inclusive? The Case of Mentally Disabled Persons.Evaristus Matthias Eyo - 2023 - Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions 12 (2):55-72.
    In this essay, I argue that Menkiti’s normative personhood is exclusionary, and logically inadequate, especially regarding mentally disabled persons. My argument is that Menkiti’s account of personhood as a moral-political theory does not possess the resources to accommodate and account for mentally disabled persons because of its rigid process of transformation, which requires moral excellence. An inclusive moral theory, I argue, should be able to accommodate all members of the moral community irrespective of their ability, but rather, their capacity for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  36
    Time and interpretation: understanding concepts and conceptual change.John G. Gunnell - 1998 - History of Political Thought 19 (4):641-658.
    The issue of the nature of concepts and the problem of understanding conceptual change have become increasingly important in methodological discussions of the study of the history of political thought as well as in substantive research. The treatment of these matters, however, remains inadequate. This is in part a consequence of metatheoretical agendas that have diverted attention away from a theoretical analysis of concepts and apposite issues such as the relationship between mental predicates, words and concepts. But the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  90
    Must the other be derived from the I? Towards the reformulation of Husserl's 5th cartesian meditation.Robert M. Harlan - 1984 - Husserl Studies 1 (1):79-104.
    With the possible exception of the first volume of the Ideas, no single work published by Husserl has caused as much controversy among philosophers otherwise sympathetic to his philosophical endeavor as the 5th Cartesian Meditation. The controversy centers around the constitutive analysis of the sense "another subject," an analysis the elaborate detail of which seems out of place in the otherwise programmatic Cartesian Meditations. This analysis, which marks the first step in Husserl's account of consciousness of the other as another (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Reduction, explanation, and individualism.Harold Kincaid - 1986 - Philosophy of Science 53 (4):492-513.
    This paper contributes to the recently renewed debate over methodological individualism (MI) by carefully sorting out various individualist claims and by making use of recent work on reduction and explanation outside the social sciences. My major focus is on individualist claims about reduction and explanation. I argue that reductionist versions of MI fail for much the same reasons that mental predicates cannot be reduced to physical predicates and that attempts to establish reducibility by weakening the requirements for (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  41. When we think about thinking: The acquisition of belief verbs.Anna Papafragou - 2007 - Cognition 105 (1):125.
    Mental-content verbs such as think, believe, imagine and hope seem to pose special problems for the young language learner. One possible explanation for these diYculties is that the concepts that these verbs express are hard to grasp and therefore their acquisition must await relevant conceptual development. According to a diVerent, perhaps complementary, proposal, a major contributor to the diYculty of these items lies with the informational requirements for identifying them from the contexts in which they appear. The experiments reported (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  42. Which immunity to error?Joel Smith - 2006 - Philosophical Studies 130 (2):273-83.
    A self-ascription is a thought or sentence in which a predicate is self-consciously ascribed to oneself. Self-ascriptions are best expressed using the first-person pronoun. Mental self-ascriptions are ascriptions to oneself of mental predicates (predicates that designate mental properties), non-mental self-ascriptions are ascriptions to oneself of non-mental predicates (predicates that designate non-mental properties). It is often claimed that there is a range of self-ascriptions that are immune to error through misidentification relative (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  43.  45
    (2 other versions)Self-knowledge, Normativity, and Construction.Julia Tanney - 2002 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 51:37-55.
    He tried to look into her face, to find out what she thought, but she was smelling the lilac and the lilies of the valley and did not know herself what she was thinking—what she ought to say or do.OblomovMuch of modern and contemporary philosophy of mind in the ‘analytic’ tradition has presupposed, since Descartes, what might be called a realist view about the mind and the mental. According to this view there are independently existing, determinate items that are (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44.  92
    Supervenience and Anomalism are Compatible.Oron Shagrir - 2011 - Dialectica 65 (2):241-266.
    I explore a Davidsonian proposal for the reconciliation of two theses. One is the supervenience of the mental on the physical, the other is the anomalism of the mental. The gist of the proposal is that supervenience and anomalism are theses about interpretation. Starting with supervenience, the claim is that it should not be understood in terms of deeper metaphysical relations, but as a constraint on the relations between the applications of physical and mental predicates. Regarding (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45.  48
    Anti-reductionist materialism.Kathleen Lennon - 1984 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 27 (December):363-380.
    This paper characterizes a form of materialism which is strongly anti?reductionist with regard to mental predicates. It argues against the functionalist views of writers such as Brian Loar on the basis that the counterfactual interdependencies of intentional states are governed by constraints of rationality embodied in semantic links which cannot be captured in non?intentional, functionalist terms. However, contrary to what is commonly supposed, such anti?reductionism requires neither instrumentalism about the mental nor opposition to a causal explanatory view (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  52
    Two kinds of representational functionalism: Defusing the combinatorial explosion.Joel Pust - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):392-393.
    Alvin Goldman (1993) presents three arguments against the psychological plausibility of representational functionalism (RF) as a theory of how subjects self-ascribe mental predicates. Goldman appears to construe RF as an account of attitude type self-ascription. His “combinatorial explosion” argument, however, proves devastating only to an implausible construal of RF as an account of attitude content self-ascription.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Persons and their properties.Jason Stanley - 1998 - Philosophical Quarterly 48 (191):159-175.
    According to what I call ‘the asymmetry thesis’, persons, though they are the direct bearers of the properties expressed by mental predicates, are not the direct bearers of properties such as those expressed by ‘weighs 135 pounds’ or ‘has crossed legs’. A number of different views about persons entail the asymmetry thesis. I first argue that the asymmetry thesis entails an error theory about our discourse involving person‐referring terms. I then argue that it is further threatened by consideration (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  48.  26
    Menschliche Existenz und moderne Welt (review).Harold A. Durfee - 1968 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 6 (4):408-412.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:408 HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY The Fellowship of Being. By John B. O'Malley. (The Hague: Martinus Niihoff, 1966. Pp. xii + 140. $5.60) This book is a study of the concept of person in the philosophy of Gabriel Marcel. It is the revision of a doctoral thesis, completed at the University of London, under the direction of A. J. Ayer. This fact, in addition to the intrinsic interest of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. A note on Descartes and Spinoza.Jonathan Bennett - 1965 - Philosophical Review 74 (3):379-380.
    DESCARTES was a dualist and Spinoza a monist. If this marks a contrast between them, there ought to be a question to which Descartes’s answer was “two” and Spinoza’s “one”. (a) How many substances are there? Spinoza: “One.” Descartes: “Strictly speaking, one; but if we relax the criteria for substantiality a little, millions.” On no interpretation of the question did Descartes answer, “Two.” (b) How many basic kinds of substance are there? Descartes: “Two.” Spinoza: “Two; though there is only one (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50. An Analysis of Searle's Theory of the Intentionality of Speech Acts.Shashi Motilal - 1986 - Dissertation, State University of New York at Buffalo
    It is an indubitable fact that our thoughts are always about something or some state of affairs in the world. Again, it is true that we use language to express some of our thoughts, and that in such a use of language which philosophers call a speech act, language also comes to be about something or some state of affairs in the world. E.g., when someone asserts that Peter is married to Mary, the sentence, 'Peter is married to Mary', comes (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 961