Methodology and metaphysics in the development of Dedekind's theory of ideals

In José Ferreirós Domínguez & Jeremy Gray (eds.), The Architecture of Modern Mathematics: Essays in History and Philosophy. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press (2006)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Philosophical concerns rarely force their way into the average mathematician’s workday. But, in extreme circumstances, fundamental questions can arise as to the legitimacy of a certain manner of proceeding, say, as to whether a particular object should be granted ontological status, or whether a certain conclusion is epistemologically warranted. There are then two distinct views as to the role that philosophy should play in such a situation. On the first view, the mathematician is called upon to turn to the counsel of philosophers, in much the same way as a nation considering an action of dubious international legality is called upon to turn to the United Nations for guidance. After due consideration of appropriate regulations and guidelines (and, possibly, debate between representatives of different philosophical factions), the philosophers render a decision, by which the dutiful mathematician abides. Quine was famously critical of such dreams of a ‘first philosophy.’ At the opposite extreme, our hypothetical mathematician answers only to the subject’s internal concerns, blithely or brashly indifferent to philosophical approval. What is at stake to our mathematician friend is whether the questionable practice provides a proper mathematical solution to the problem at hand, or an appropriate mathematical understanding; or, in pragmatic terms, whether it will make it past a journal referee. In short, mathematics is as mathematics does, and the philosopher’s task is simply to make sense of the subject as it evolves and certify practices that are already in place. In his textbook on the philosophy of mathematics (Shapiro, 2000), Stewart Shapiro characterizes this attitude as ‘philosophy last, if at all.’.

Other Versions

manuscript Avigad, Jeremy (manuscript) "Methodology and metaphysics in the development of dedekind's theory of ideals".

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 101,174

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Explanation in Mathematics.Paolo Mancosu - 2012 - In Ed Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Whether philosophers need contemporary mathematics?V. A. Erovenko - 2013 - Liberal Arts in Russia 2 (6):523--530.
Mathematics and Aesthetics in Kantian Perspectives.Wenzel Christian Helmut - 2016 - In Cassaza Peter, Krantz Steven G. & Ruden Randi R. (eds.), I, Mathematician II. Further Introspections on the Mathematical Life. The Consortium of Mathematics and its Applications. pp. 93-106.
The Problems of Understanding Mathematics.Jarosław Mrozek - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 34:17-23.
NEOPLATONIC STRUCTURALISM IN PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS.Inna Savynska - 2019 - The Days of Science of the Faculty of Philosophy – 2019 1:52-53.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-03-12

Downloads
72 (#292,509)

6 months
11 (#352,895)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Jeremy Avigad
Carnegie Mellon University

References found in this work

Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology.Stewart Shapiro - 2000 - Philosophical Quarterly 50 (198):120-123.
Three Forms of Naturalism.Penelope Maddy - 2005 - In Stewart Shapiro (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
The genesis of ideal theory.Harold M. Edwards - 1980 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 23 (4):321-378.

View all 7 references / Add more references