When to defer to majority testimony - and when not

Analysis 66 (3):179-187 (2006)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

How sensitive should you be to the testimony of others? You saw the car that caused an accident going through traffic lights on the red; or so you thought. Should you revise your belief on discovering that the majority of bystanders, equally well-equipped, equally well-positioned and equally impartial, reported that it went through on the green? Or take another case. You believe that intelligent design is the best explanation for the order of the living universe. Should you revise that belief on finding that most other people, or at least most who by your own lights are as intelligent, informed and impartial as yourself, believe that evolutionary theory offers the better account? Should you do this, in particular, if your own personal sense of where the evidence points – like your own vivid memory of the car going through on the red – remains firmly on the side of intelligent design? Assume, to take a third case, that there is a matter of fact about whether abortion is right or wrong. You believe that it is wrong, having a firm picture of it as an act on a par with murder. Should you revise that belief on discovering that among those whom you regard as equally intelligent, informed and impartial, most believe that abortion is not wrong, or at least not wrong in the way that murder is wrong? Should you do this, in particular, if your own personal sense of abortion remains unchanged; it still seems to you to be a grievous wrong? Should you put aside your own sense of things as mistaken, in the way you might put aside your imagined memory of the car going through on the red, and decide to go along with the majority view?

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 103,401

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Reflection and disagreement.Adam Elga - 2007 - Noûs 41 (3):478–502.
Belief and Difficult Action.Berislav Marušić - 2012 - Philosophers' Imprint 12:1-30.
The Enkratic Requirement.Allen Coates - 2011 - European Journal of Philosophy 21 (2):320-333.
How Do You Know?: A Dialogue.Gordon Barnes - 2021 - Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett Publishing Company.
On Having a Good.Christine M. Korsgaard - 2014 - Philosophy 89 (3):405-429.
The toss-up between a profiting, innocent threat and his victim.Susanne Burri - 2015 - Journal of Political Philosophy 23 (2):146-165.
Justified by Thought Alone.Andrei Mărășoiu - 2020 - Logos and Episteme 11 (2):195-208.
Moral Worth and Moral Belief.James Grant - 2022 - Ethics 133 (2):216-230.

Analytics

Added to PP
2009-01-28

Downloads
304 (#94,481)

6 months
13 (#197,488)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Philip Pettit
Australian National University

Citations of this work

Epistemology of disagreement: The good news.David Christensen - 2007 - Philosophical Review 116 (2):187-217.
Disagreement.Richard Feldman & Ted A. Warfield (eds.) - 2010 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
Self-deception.Ian Deweese-Boyd - 2023 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

View all 50 citations / Add more citations