Causal Necessity in Aristotle

British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (5):855-879 (2012)
  Copy   BIBTEX

Abstract

Like many realists about causation and causal powers, Aristotle uses the language of necessity when discussing causation, and he appears to think that by invoking necessity, he is clarifying the manner in which causes bring about or determine their effects. In so doing, he would appear to run afoul of Humean criticisms of the notion of a necessary connection between cause and effect. The claim that causes necessitate their effects may be understood—or attacked—in several ways, however, and so whether the view or its criticism is tenable depends on how we understand the necessitation claim. In fact, Aristotelian efficient causation may be said to involve two distinct necessary connections: one is a relation between causes considered as potential, while the other relates them considered as active. That is, the claims that (1) what has the power to heat necessarily heats what has the power to be heated, and that (2) a particular flame which is actually under a pot necessarily heats it, both of which appear to be true for Aristotle, involve distinct notions of necessity. The latter kind of necessity is based on the facts, as Aristotle sees them, about change, whereas the former is based in the nature of properties. Though different, both kinds of necessity are instances of what contemporary philosophers would call metaphysical necessity, and together they also amount to a theory of causal determination

Other Versions

No versions found

Links

PhilArchive



    Upload a copy of this work     Papers currently archived: 100,665

External links

Setup an account with your affiliations in order to access resources via your University's proxy server

Through your library

Similar books and articles

Causes and Coincidences.David Owens - 1992 - New York, NY, USA: Cambridge University Press.
Necessity in Hume's Causal Theory.Leonard Greenberg - 1955 - Review of Metaphysics 8 (4):612 - 623.
The Powerlessness of Necessity.Markus Schrenk - 2010 - Noûs 44 (4):725-739.
The Nature of Necessity. [REVIEW]F. K. C. - 1975 - Review of Metaphysics 28 (4):762-763.
Natural Necessity, Objective Chances and Causal Powers.C. Behan McCullagh - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 10:78-83.
Hume's Account of Causation.Sun Demirli - 1999 - Dissertation, Syracuse University

Analytics

Added to PP
2012-09-25

Downloads
148 (#151,873)

6 months
16 (#177,983)

Historical graph of downloads
How can I increase my downloads?

Author's Profile

Nathanael Stein
Florida State University

Citations of this work

Aristotle's Four Causes of Action.Bryan C. Reece - 2018 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 97 (2):213-227.
Aristotle on causality.Andrea Falcon - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Αριστοτέλης και Χριστιανική Φιλοσοφία.Michael Mantzanas - 2017 - In V. Nikolaidis Apostolos (ed.), Proceedings of the International Conference "Aristotle and Christianity". School of Theology of the National and Kapodistrian University of Athens. pp. 219-232.

View all 6 citations / Add more citations

References found in this work

The Nature of Necessity.Alvin Plantinga - 1974 - Oxford, England: Clarendon Press.
Scientific Essentialism.Brian Ellis - 2001 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
Causation.David Lewis - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (17):556-567.
Humean Supervenience Debugged.David Lewis - 1994 - Mind 103 (412):473--490.
Causation as influence.David Lewis - 2000 - Journal of Philosophy 97 (4):182-197.

View all 34 references / Add more references