Results for ' Geometrical Sciences'

971 found
Order:
  1.  57
    The Geometric Universe: Science, Geometry, and the Work of Roger Penrose.Antony Valentini - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 33 (1):131-135.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  8
    Physical Science, its Structure and Development: From Geometric Astronomy to the Mechanical Theory of Heat.Edwin C. Kemble - 1966 - MIT Press.
    This introduction to physical science combines a rigorous discussion of scientific principles with sufficient historical background and philosophic interpretation to add a new dimension of interest to the accounts given in more conventional textbooks. It brings out the twofold character of physical science as an expanding body of verifiable knowledge and as an organized human activity whose goals and values are major factors in the revolutionary changes sweeping over the world today.Professor Kemble insists that to understand science one must understand (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  22
    Physical Science, Its Structure and Development. Vol. I: From Geometric Astronomy to the Mechanical Theory of HeatEdwin C. Kemble. [REVIEW]Clifford Maier - 1967 - Isis 58 (3):420-422.
  4.  82
    Solving Geometric Analogy Problems Through Two‐Stage Analogical Mapping.Andrew Lovett, Emmett Tomai, Kenneth Forbus & Jeffrey Usher - 2009 - Cognitive Science 33 (7):1192-1231.
    Evans’ 1968 ANALOGY system was the first computer model of analogy. This paper demonstrates that the structure mapping model of analogy, when combined with high‐level visual processing and qualitative representations, can solve the same kinds of geometric analogy problems as were solved by ANALOGY. Importantly, the bulk of the computations are not particular to the model of this task but are general purpose: We use our existing sketch understanding system, CogSketch, to compute visual structure that is used by our existing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  5.  55
    Deux notes sur l' «imparfaite science» du geometre athee.Georges J. D. Moyal - 2005 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 43 (3):277-300.
    Georges J. D. Moyal - Deux notes sur l' «imparfaite science» du geometre athee - Journal of the History of Philosophy 43:3 Journal of the History of Philosophy 43.3 277-300 Deux notes sur l'« imparfaite science » du géomètre athée Georges J. D. Moyal Deux questions. La Ve Méditation de Descartes vise à démontrer que l'existence d'un Dieu vérace est la condition nécessaire de toute science. En effet, Descartes y écrit ceci : « . . . je remarque que la (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Geometrical Method.Ursula Goldenbaum - 2015
    The Geometrical Method The Geometrical Method is the style of proof that was used in Euclid’s proofs in geometry, and that was used in philosophy in Spinoza’s proofs in his Ethics. The term appeared first in 16th century Europe when mathematics was on an upswing due to the new science of mechanics. … Continue reading Geometrical Method →.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  44
    Foundations of geometric cognition.Mateusz Hohol - 2019 - London-New York: Routledge.
    The cognitive foundations of geometry have puzzled academics for a long time, and even today are mostly unknown to many scholars, including mathematical cognition researchers. -/- Foundations of Geometric Cognition shows that basic geometric skills are deeply hardwired in the visuospatial cognitive capacities of our brains, namely spatial navigation and object recognition. These capacities, shared with non-human animals and appearing in early stages of the human ontogeny, cannot, however, fully explain a uniquely human form of geometric cognition. In the book, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8. historians of science have ignored Descartes' solution to the geometrization problem...[because of] an orthodoxy of misplaced emphasis on Descartes' more “philosophical” texts':'Cartesian Optics and the Geometrization of Nature'.Nancy L. Maull Complains That‘Philosophers - 1980 - In Stephen Gaukroger (ed.), Descartes: philosophy, mathematics and physics. Totowa, N.J.: Barnes & Noble.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Platonic approaches to individual sciences: Aristotelian objections and post-Aristotelian responses to Plato's elemental theory / Ian Mueller. In defence of geometric atomism : explaining elemental properties / Jan Opsomer. Plato's geography : Damascius' interpretation of the Phaedo myth / Carlos Steel. Neoplatonists on 'spontaneous' generation / James Wilberding. Aspects of biology in Plotinus. [REVIEW]Christoph Horn - 2012 - In James Wilberding & Christoph Horn (eds.), Neoplatonism and the Philosophy of Nature. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
  10.  29
    AMIR R. ALEXANDER, Geometrical Landscapes: The Voyages of Discovery and the Transformation of Mathematical Practice. Writing Science. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002. Pp. xvii+293. ISBN 0-80473-260-4. £46.95. [REVIEW]Jackie Stedall - 2005 - British Journal for the History of Science 38 (1):108-109.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  68
    Hobbes’s Geometrical Optics.José Médina - 2016 - Hobbes Studies 29 (1):39-65.
    _ Source: _Volume 29, Issue 1, pp 39 - 65 Since Euclid, optics has been considered a geometrical science, which Aristotle defines as a “mixed” mathematical science. Hobbes follows this tradition and clearly places optics among physical sciences. However, modern scholars point to a confusion between geometry and physics and do not seem to agree about the way Hobbes mixes both sciences. In this paper, I return to this alleged confusion and intend to emphasize the peculiarity of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  77
    Geometrical Constructivism and Modal Relationalism: Further Aspects of the Dynamical/Geometrical Debate.James Read - 2020 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 33 (1):23-41.
    I draw together some recent literature on the debate between dynamical versus geometrical approaches to spacetime theories, in order to argue that there exist defensible versions of the geometr...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  13.  18
    Geometrical Touch: Drawing an Occasioned Map on the Hand.Marc Relieu - 2023 - Human Studies 46 (4):757-781.
    In this paper, based on video recordings of Orientation and Mobility (O&M) lessons for visually-disabled students, I will examine how occasioned maps (Psathas, 1979 ; Garfinkel, 2002 ), drawn in the student’s palm are interactionally traced, felt, and noticed in order to represent the shape of a crossing for all practical purposes. Touching will be examined from the perspective of the live production of "trails" on a specific region of the body, the palm of the hand. We will begin to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  26
    Mechanistic Images in Geometric Form: Heinrich Hertz's 'Principles of Mechanics'.Jesper Lützen - 2005 - Oxford University Press UK.
    This book gives an analysis of Hertz's posthumously published Principles of Mechanics in its philosophical, physical and mathematical context. In a period of heated debates about the true foundation of physical sciences, Hertz's book was conceived and highly regarded as an original and rigorous foundation for a mechanistic research program. Insisting that a law-like account of nature would require hypothetical unobservables, Hertz viewed physical theories as images of the world rather than the true design behind the phenomena. This paved (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  15.  23
    The Geometrical Background to the “Merton School”: An Exploration into the Application of Mathematics to Natural Philosophy in the Fourteenth Century.A. G. Molland - 1968 - British Journal for the History of Science 4 (2):108-125.
    At the end of the last century Paul Tannery published an article on geometry in eleventh-century Europe, which he began with the following statement:“This is not a chapter in the history of science; it is a study of ignorance, in a period immediately before the introduction into the West of Arab mathematics.”.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  16.  85
    The Geometrization of Motion: Galileo’s Triangle of Speed and its Various Transformations.Carla Rita Palmerino - 2010 - Early Science and Medicine 15 (4-5):410-447.
    This article analyzes Galileo's mathematization of motion, focusing in particular on his use of geometrical diagrams. It argues that Galileo regarded his diagrams of acceleration not just as a complement to his mathematical demonstrations, but as a powerful heuristic tool. Galileo probably abandoned the wrong assumption of the proportionality between the degree of velocity and the space traversed in accelerated motion when he realized that it was impossible, on the basis of that hypothesis, to build a diagram of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  17.  46
    In defence of geometrical algebra.Viktor Blåsjö - 2016 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 70 (3):325-359.
    The geometrical algebra hypothesis was once the received interpretation of Greek mathematics. In recent decades, however, it has become anathema to many. I give a critical review of all arguments against it and offer a consistent rebuttal case against the modern consensus. Consequently, I find that the geometrical algebra interpretation should be reinstated as a viable historical hypothesis.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18. Geometric foundations of classical yang–mills theory.Gabriel Catren - 2008 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39 (3):511-531.
    We analyze the geometric foundations of classical Yang-Mills theory by studying the relationships between internal relativity, locality, global/local invariance, and background independence. We argue that internal relativity and background independence are the two independent defining principles of Yang-Mills theory. We show that local gauge invariance -heuristically implemented by means of the gauge argument- is a direct consequence of internal relativity. Finally, we analyze the conceptual meaning of BRST symmetry in terms of the invariance of the gauge fixed theory under general (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  19.  22
    Gravitational Quantum Dynamics: A Geometrical Perspective.Ivano Tavernelli - 2021 - Foundations of Physics 51 (2):1-24.
    We present a gravitational quantum dynamics theory that combines quantum field theory for particle dynamics in space-time with classical Einstein’s general relativity in a non-Riemannian Finsler space. This approach is based on the geometrization of quantum mechanics proposed in Tavernelli and combines quantum and gravitational effects into a global curvature of the Finsler space induced by the quantum potential associated to the matter quantum fields. In order to make this theory compatible with general relativity, the quantum effects are described in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  35
    A Quantum Geometric Framework for Modeling Color Similarity Judgments.Gunnar P. Epping, Elizabeth L. Fisher, Ariel M. Zeleznikow-Johnston, Emmanuel M. Pothos & Naotsugu Tsuchiya - 2023 - Cognitive Science 47 (1):e13231.
    Since Tversky argued that similarity judgments violate the three metric axioms, asymmetrical similarity judgments have been particularly challenging for standard, geometric models of similarity, such as multidimensional scaling. According to Tversky, asymmetrical similarity judgments are driven by differences in salience or extent of knowledge. However, the notion of salience has been difficult to operationalize, especially for perceptual stimuli for which there are no apparent differences in extent of knowledge. To investigate similarity judgments between perceptual stimuli, across three experiments, we collected (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  63
    Cognitive Artifacts for Geometric Reasoning.Mateusz Hohol & Marcin Miłkowski - 2019 - Foundations of Science 24 (4):657-680.
    In this paper, we focus on the development of geometric cognition. We argue that to understand how geometric cognition has been constituted, one must appreciate not only individual cognitive factors, such as phylogenetically ancient and ontogenetically early core cognitive systems, but also the social history of the spread and use of cognitive artifacts. In particular, we show that the development of Greek mathematics, enshrined in Euclid’s Elements, was driven by the use of two tightly intertwined cognitive artifacts: the use of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  22.  58
    On the Continuity of Geometrized Newtonian Gravitation and General Relativity.Saeed Masoumi - 2021 - Foundations of Physics 51 (2):1-33.
    Pessimistic meta-induction is a powerful argument against scientific realism, so one of the major roles for advocates of scientific realism will be trying their best to give a sustained response to this argument. On the other hand, it is also alleged that structural realism is the most plausible form of scientific realism; therefore, the plausibility of scientific realism is threatened unless one is given the explicit form of a structural continuity and minimal structural preservation for all our current theories. This (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23. On geometric objects, the non-existence of a gravitational stress-energy tensor, and the uniqueness of the Einstein field equation.Erik Curiel - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 66:90-102.
    The question of the existence of gravitational stress-energy in general relativity has exercised investigators in the field since the inception of the theory. Folklore has it that no adequate definition of a localized gravitational stress-energetic quantity can be given. Most arguments to that effect invoke one version or another of the Principle of Equivalence. I argue that not only are such arguments of necessity vague and hand-waving but, worse, are beside the point and do not address the heart of the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  24. Geometric Pooling: A User's Guide.Richard Pettigrew & Jonathan Weisberg - forthcoming - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
    Much of our information comes to us indirectly, in the form of conclusions others have drawn from evidence they gathered. When we hear these conclusions, how can we modify our own opinions so as to gain the benefit of their evidence? In this paper we study the method known as geometric pooling. We consider two arguments in its favour, raising several objections to one, and proposing an amendment to the other.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  48
    (1 other version)Geometrical and physical conventionalism of Henri poincar'e in epistemological formulation.Jerzy Giedymin - 1991 - Studies in the History and Philsophy of Science 22 (1):1-22.
  26.  13
    The Role of Geometrical Construction in Theodosius’s Spherics.Ken Saito & Nathan Sidoli - 2009 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 63 (6):581-609.
    This paper is a contribution to our understanding of the constructive nature of Greek geometry. By studying the role of constructive processes in Theodoius’s Spherics, we uncover a difference in the function of constructions and problems in the deductive framework of Greek mathematics. In particular, we show that geometric problems originated in the practical issues involved in actually making diagrams, whereas constructions are abstractions of these processes that are used to introduce objects not given at the outset, so that their (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27.  46
    Geometric Magic Squares and Cubes.Harry A. Sayles - 1913 - The Monist 23 (4):631-640.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  19
    A Geometric Milieu Inside the Brain.Arturo Tozzi, Alexander Yurkin & James F. Peters - 2022 - Foundations of Science 27 (4):1477-1488.
    The brain, rather than being homogeneous, displays an almost infinite topological genus, since it is punctured with a high number of “cavities”. We might think to the brain as a sponge equipped with countless, uniformly placed, holes. Here we show how these holes, termed topological vortexes, stand for nesting, non-concentric brain signal cycles resulting from the activity of inhibitory neurons. Such inhibitory spike activity is inversely correlated with its counterpart, i.e., the excitatory spike activity propagating throughout the whole brain tissue. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  70
    Hume's Geometric.E. W. Van Steenburgh - 1980 - Hume Studies 6 (1):61-68.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:61. HUME'S GEOMETRIC "OBJECTS" Arithmetic and algebra allow of precision and certainty. The science of geometry is not likewise a perfect and infallible science. At any rate, this is Hume's teaching in the Treatise. When two numbers are so combin ' d, as that the one has always an unite answering to every unite of the other, we pronounce them equal; and 'tis for want of such a standard (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  40
    Geometric ordering of concepts, logical disjunction, and learning by induction.Dominic Widdows & Michael Higgins - 2004 - In Simon D. Levy & Ross Gayler (eds.), Compositional Connectionism in Cognitive Science. AAAI Press. pp. 22--24.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Geometric model of gravity, counterfactual solar mass, and the Pioneer anomalies.Andrew Holster - manuscript
    This study analyses the predictions of the General Theory of Relativity (GTR) against a slightly modified version of the standard central mass solution (Schwarzschild solution). It is applied to central gravity in the solar system, the Pioneer spacecraft anomalies (which GTR fails to predict correctly), and planetary orbit distances and times, etc (where GTR is thought consistent.) -/- The modified gravity equation was motivated by a theory originally called ‘TFP’ (Time Flow Physics, 2004). This is now replaced by the ‘Geometric (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  12
    Graphical Choices and Geometrical Thought in the Transmission of Theodosius’ Spherics from Antiquity to the Renaissance.Michela Malpangotto - 2009 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 64 (1):75-112.
    Spherical geometry studies the sphere not simply as a solid object in itself, but chiefly as the spatial context of the elements which interact on it in a complex three-dimensional arrangement. This compels to establish graphical conventions appropriate for rendering on the same plane—the plane of the diagram itself—the spatial arrangement of the objects under consideration. We will investigate such “graphical choices” made in the Theodosius’ Spherics from antiquity to the Renaissance. Rather than undertaking a minute analysis of every particular (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  18
    The Definitions of Fundamental Geometric Entities Contained in Book I of Euclids Elements.Lucio Russo - 1998 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 52 (3):195-219.
    OElig;he thesis is sustained that the definitions of fundamental geometric entities which open Euclids Elements actually are excerpts from the Definitions by Heron of Alexandria, interpolated in late antiquity into Euclids treatise. As a consequence, one of the main bases of the traditional Platonist interpretation of Euclid is refuted. Arguments about the constructivist nature of Euclids mathematical philosophy are given.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34. Geometric conventionalism and carnap's principle of tolerance.David De Vidi & Graham Solomon - 1993 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (5):773-783.
    We discuss in this paper the question of the scope of the principle of tolerance about languages promoted in Carnap's The Logical Syntax of Language and the nature of the analogy between it and the rudimentary conventionalism purportedly exhibited in the work of Poincaré and Hilbert. We take it more or less for granted that Poincaré and Hilbert do argue for conventionalism. We begin by sketching Coffa's historical account, which suggests that tolerance be interpreted as a conventionalism that allows us (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  66
    Geometrical First Principles in Proclus’ Commentary on the First Book of Euclid’s Elements.D. Gregory MacIsaac - 2014 - Phronesis 59 (1):44-98.
    In his commentary on Euclid, Proclus says both that the first principle of geometry are self-evident and that they are hypotheses received from the single, highest, unhypothetical science, which is probably dialectic. The implication of this seems to be that a geometer both does and does not know geometrical truths. This dilemma only exists if we assume that Proclus follows Aristotle in his understanding of these terms. This paper shows that this is not the case, and explains what Proclus (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  60
    Geometric possibility- an argument from dimension.Carolyn Brighouse - 2014 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 4 (1):31-54.
    One cannot expect an exact answer to the question “What are the possible structures of space?”, but rough answers to it impact central debates within philosophy of space and time. Recently Gordon Belot has suggested that a rough answer takes the class of metric spaces to represent the possible structures of space. This answer has intuitive appeal, but I argue, focusing on topological characterizations of dimension, examples of prima facie space-like mathematical spaces that have pathological dimension properties, and endorsing a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  73
    Building the Stemma Codicum of Geometrical Diagrams. A Treatise on Optics by Ibn al-Haytham as a Test Case.Dominique Raynaud - 2014 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 68 (2):207-239.
    In view of the progress made in recent decades in the fields of stemmatology and the analysis of geometric diagrams, the present article explores the possibility of establishing the stemma codicum of a handwritten tradition from geometric diagrams alone. This exploratory method is tested on Ibn al-Haytham’s Epistle on the Shape of the Eclipse, because this work has not yet been issued in a critical edition. Separate stemmata were constructed on the basis of the diagrams and the text, and a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  38.  7
    Huggett, S. A. / Mason, Lionel J. / Tod, K. Paul / Tsou, Sheung Tsun / Woodhouse, Nick M. (eds): The Geometric Universe. Science, Geometry and the Work of Roger Penrose, Oxford University, Oxford, 1998, XVIII, 431 págs. [REVIEW]Carlos Ortiz de Landázuri - 2001 - Anuario Filosófico:226-227.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  30
    Geometrical Figures and Generality in Ancient China and Beyond: Liu Hui and Zhao Shuang, Plato and Thabit ibn Qurra.Karine Chemla - 2005 - Science in Context 18 (1):123-166.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  8
    Extrafoveal Processing in Categorical Search for Geometric Shapes: General Tendencies and Individual Variations.Anna Dreneva, Anna Shvarts, Dmitry Chumachenko & Anatoly Krichevets - 2021 - Cognitive Science 45 (8):e13025.
    The paper addresses the capabilities and limitations of extrafoveal processing during a categorical visual search. Previous research has established that a target could be identified from the very first or without any saccade, suggesting that extrafoveal perception is necessarily involved. However, the limits in complexity defining the processed information are still not clear. We performed four experiments with a gradual increase of stimuli complexity to determine the role of extrafoveal processing in searching for the categorically defined geometric shape. The series (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  56
    Geometric significance of the spinor Lie derivative. I.V. Jhangiani - 1978 - Foundations of Physics 8 (5-6):445-462.
    In a previous article, the writer explored the geometric foundation of the generally covariant spinor calculus. This geometric reasoning can be extended quite naturally to include the Lie covariant differentiation of spinors. The formulas for the Lie covariant derivatives of spinors, adjoint spinors, and operators in spin space are deduced, and it is observed that the Lie covariant derivative of an operator in spin space must vanish when taken with respect to a Killing vector. The commutator of two Lie covariant (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  42
    (1 other version)The geometrical basis of arithmetical knowledge: Frege & Dehaene.Sorin Costreie - 2018 - Theoria : An International Journal for Theory, History and Fundations of Science 33 (2):361-370.
    Frege writes in Numbers and Arithmetic about kindergarten-numbers and “an a priori mode of cognition” that they may have “a geometrical source.” This resembles recent findings on arithmetical cognition. In my paper, I explore this resemblance between Gottlob Frege’s later position concerning the geometrical source of arithmetical knowledge, and some current positions in the literature dedicated to arithmetical cognition, especially that of Stanislas Dehaene. In my analysis, I shall try to mainly see to what extent logicism is compatible (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  14
    Geometric division problems, quadratic equations, and recursive geometric algorithms in Mesopotamian mathematics.Jöran Friberg - 2014 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 68 (1):1-34.
    Most of what is told in this paper has been told before by the same author, in a number of publications of various kinds, but this is the first time that all this material has been brought together and treated in a uniform way. Smaller errors in the earlier publications are corrected here without comment. It has been known since the 1920s that quadratic equations played a prominent role in Babylonian mathematics. See, most recently, Høyrup (Hist Sci 34:1–32, 1996, and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  19
    Alfred Clebsch’s “Geometrical Clothing” of the theory of the quintic equation.François Lê - 2017 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 71 (1):39-70.
    This paper describes Alfred Clebsch’s 1871 article that gave a geometrical interpretation of elements of the theory of the general algebraic equation of degree 5. Clebsch’s approach is used here to illuminate the relations between geometry, intuition, figures, and visualization at the time. In this paper, we try to delineate clearly what he perceived as geometric in his approach, and to show that Clebsch’s use of geometrical objects and techniques is not intended to aid visualization matters, but rather (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  44
    Geometrical Figures in Spinoza's Book of Nature.Matthew Homan - 2018 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 56 (3):455-476.
    the view of spinoza as a scion of the mathematico-mechanistic tradition of Galileo and Descartes, albeit perhaps an idiosyncratic one, has been held by many commentators and might be considered standard.1 Although the standard view has a prima facie solid basis in Spinoza's conception of the physical world as extended, law-bound, and deterministic, it has come under sustained criticism of late. Arguing that, for Spinoza, numbers and figures are mere beings of reason and mathematical conceptions of nature belong to the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  65
    From a Geometrical point of View: A Study of the History and Philosophy of Category Theory jean-pierre marquis Springer series, Logic, Epistemology and the Unity of Science 14, 2009, 310 pp., $219.00 cloth. [REVIEW]Clayton Peterson - 2012 - Dialogue 51 (2):333-335.
    Book Reviews Clayton peterson, Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review/Revue canadienne de philosophie, FirstView Article.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  54
    The Perceptual Roots of Geometric Idealizations.John J. Drummond - 1984 - Review of Metaphysics 37 (4):785 - 810.
    EDMUND HUSSERL in his early writings on space distinguishes three kinds of problems surrounding the presentation of space: psychological, logical, and metaphysical. By the term "psychology" Husserl means a descriptive and genetic psychology which seeks to characterize the contents and structure of particular experiences and to investigate the genetic relations between different experiences. Included among the genetic questions concerning space is the problem of the origin of the science of space.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  53
    Isaac Barrow on the Mathematization of Nature: Theological Voluntarism and the Rise of Geometrical Optics.Antoni Malet - 1997 - Journal of the History of Ideas 58 (2):265-287.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Isaac Barrow on the Mathematization of Nature: Theological Voluntarism and the Rise of Geometrical OpticsAntoni MaletIntroductionIsaac Newton’s Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy embodies a strong program of mathematization that departs both from the mechanical philosophy of Cartesian inspiration and from Boyle’s experimental philosophy. The roots of Newton’s mathematization of nature, this paper aims to demonstrate, are to be found in Isaac Barrow’s (1630–77) philosophy of the mathematical (...).Barrow’s attitude towards natural philosophy evolved from his earnest interest in medicine of around 1650, when a young Cambridge graduate, to natural philosophy (apparently under Henry More’s influence); from his thesis on the insufficiency of the Cartesian hypothesis to geometrical optics and the strong program of mathematization of natural philosophy of the middle 1660s; from Lucasian professor of Mathematics to Chaplain of his Majesty and eminent Restoration divine. Contemporary accounts of Barrow’s life suggest that he grew ever more skeptical about the worth of natural philosophy and mathematics. 1 In his last years he became a prolific [End Page 265] author of sermons and theological works. Published shortly after his death by John Tillotson (1630–94), later archbishop of Canterbury, they occupy over two thousand folio pages. Overloaded with involved philosophical arguments, Barrow’s sermons were apparently not very popular, but they were highly regarded by scholars and the Anglican hierarchy. 2 It is on certain of his sermons, as well as on the philosophical discussions contained in the Mathematical Lectures that our account of Barrow’s philosophy of the mathematical sciences will rest. 3 Barrow’s understanding of the mathematical sciences will allow us to discuss together three issues often analyzed independently: the theological background to English natural philosophy, the changing notion of mixed mathematical sciences during the seventeenth century, and finally the philosophical foundations of modern geometrical optics.It has long been recognized that significant relationships exist between theological voluntarism or intellectualism and views on natural philosophy. In particular Robert Boyle’s theological voluntarism is seen as grounding his experimentalist approach to natural philosophy. It is not quite so clear, however, how well theological voluntarism may relate to a strong program of mathematization such as the one embodied in Newton’s Principia Mathematica. In fact it has been suggested that the relationship is a negative one. This is derived from the necessary character of mathematical laws, which would put unwanted restrictions on God’s absolute dominion over nature, and also from the notion that theological intellectualism is conducive to a deductive, a priori science—the paradigm of which is of course geometry. However, Barrow’s theological voluntarism lead him to heighten the role of mathematics within natural philosophy.During the seventeenth century the so-called mixed or subalternate mathematical sciences changed profoundly. In the Enlightenment mixed mathematics—meaning above all rational mechanics—became one of the most prestigious and influential disciplines. The mixed mathematics of the Enlightenment, however, was markedly different from the Aristotelian [End Page 266] mixed mathematical sciences. The differences are noticeable both in the subject matter and in the substitution of mathematical infinitesimal analysis for geometrical synthesis, but also in the way of grounding mathematical theory on empirical evidence. Barrow’s Mathematical Lectures (delivered at Cambridge from 1664 to 1666) offer a fresh insight into the metamorphosis of these sciences just when Newton’s “mathematical principles” were in the making. Not the least interesting feature of Barrow’s discussion is that God’s omnipotence allows an evaluation of the truth of mathematical theories that do not apply to this world. Therefore, Barrow is led to introduce the distinction between the internal consistency, or mathematical truth, of a mathematical theory and its physical truth. This, in turn, leads him to the notion that theories need testing.Barrow on Matter and GodRecent literature has established significant correlations between theological voluntarism and empiricism, as well as between theological intellectualism and rationalism. As E. B. Davis writes, “the Christian doctrine of creation is a dialogue between God’s unconstrained will, which utterly transcends the bounds of human comprehension, and God’s orderly intellect, which serves as the model for the human mind.” Intellectualist theology considers God’s omniscience His... (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  49. What is the Value of Geometric Models to Understand Matter?Francoise Monnoyeur (ed.) - 2015 - palermo italy: review of Ontology.
    This article analyzes the value of geometric models to understand matter with the examples of the Platonic model for the primary four elements (fire, air, water, and earth) and the models of carbon atomic structures in the new science of crystallography. How the geometry of these models is built in order to discover the properties of matter is explained: movement and stability for the primary elements, and hardness, softness and elasticity for the carbon atoms. These geometric models appear to have (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  46
    Keplerian Illusions: Geometrical Pictures "vs" Optical Images in Kepler's Visual Theory.Antoni Malet - 1990 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 21 (1):1.
1 — 50 / 971