Results for ' Sympathy for Others’ Feeling'

968 found
Order:
  1. Feeling for Others: Empathy, Sympathy, and Morality.Heidi L. Maibom - 2009 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 52 (5):483-499.
    An increasingly popular suggestion is that empathy and/or sympathy plays a foundational role in understanding harm norms and being motivated by them. In this paper, I argue these emotions play a rather more moderate role in harms norms than we are often led to believe. Evidence from people with frontal lobe damage suggests that neither empathy, nor sympathy is necessary for the understanding of such norms. Furthermore, people's understanding of why it is wrong to harm varies and is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  2. Feeling for others: Empathy and sympathy as sources of moral motivation.Heidi Maibom - manuscript
    According to the Humean theory of motivation, we only have a reason to act if we have both a belief and a pro-attitude. When it comes to moral reasons, it matters a great deal what that pro-attitude is; pure self-interest cannot combine with a belief to form a moral reason. A long tradition regards empathy and sympathy as moral motivators, and recent psychological evidence supports this view. I examine what I take to be the most plausible version of this (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  65
    Who Feels Sympathy for Roosters Used in Cockfighting? Examining the Influence of Feelings, Belief in Animal Mind, Personality, and Empathy-Related Traits.Sherman A. Lee & Linsey Quarles - 2012 - Society and Animals 20 (4):327-341.
    Since the 2007 Vick dog-fighting case, much attention has been focused on cruelty against dogs. Cockfighting roosters, on the other hand, have been virtually ignored by scientists and laypeople alike. Accordingly, very little is known about our emotional reactions to roosters used for cockfighting. The present study attempts to fill this void in the scientific literature by examining the relationship between individual differences variables and sympathetic reactions to roosters used for cockfighting depicted in a video newscast. The results were robust, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  34
    Do Emotional Laborers Help the Needy More or Less? The Mediating Role of Sympathy in the Effect of Emotional Dissonance on Prosocial Behavior.Yun-na Park, Hyowon Hyun & JiHoon Jhang - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10:431444.
    Despite the growing body of research on emotional labor, little has been known about the social consequences of emotional labor. Drawing on emotional dissonance theory, the authors investigate the relationship between the felt emotional dissonance and prosocial behavior (e.g., donation to a charity). Findings from multiple studies suggest that higher emotional dissonance serially influences perceived lack of control, emotional exhaustion, lowered sympathy for others’ feeling, and subsequently lower willingness to help others. when individuals are asked to recall their (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  5.  27
    Forms of Fellow Feeling: Empathy, Sympathy, Concern and Moral Agency.Neil Roughley & Thomas Schramme (eds.) - 2017 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    What is the basis of our capacity to act morally? This is a question that has been discussed for millennia, with philosophical debate typically distinguishing two sources of morality: reason and sentiment. This collection aims to shed light on whether the human capacity to feel for others really is central for morality and, if so, in what way. To tackle these questions, the authors discuss how fellow feeling is to be understood: its structure, content and empirical conditions. Also discussed (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  41
    Animating Sympathetic Feelings. An Analysis of the Nature of Sympathy in the Accounts of David Hume’s Treatise.Natalia Borza - 2019 - Conatus 4 (1):31.
    Sympathy is a powerful principle in human nature, which can change our passions, sentiments and ways of thinking. For the 18th century Scottish philosopher David Hume, sympathy is a working mechanism accountable for a wide range of communication: the ways of interacting with the others’ affections, emotions, sentiments, inclinations, ways of thinking and even opinions. The present paper intends to find a systematic reading of Hume’s Treatise of Human Nature from the point of view of what the mechanism (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  29
    What is Sympathy? Understanding the Structure of Other-Oriented Emotions.Elodie Malbois - 2023 - Emotion Review 15 (1):85-95.
    Sympathy (empathic concern) is mainly understood as a feeling for another and is often contrasted with empathy—a feeling with another. However, it is not clear what feeling for another means and what emotions sympathy involves. Since empirical data suggests that sympathy plays an important role in our social lives and is more closely connected to helping behavior than empathy, we need a more detailed account. In this paper, I argue that sympathy is not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  43
    Sympathy in Mind (1876–1900).Susan Lanzoni - 2009 - Journal of the History of Ideas 70 (2):265-287.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Sympathy in Mind (1876–1900)Susan LanzoniIn the April 1884 issue of Mind, William James published his influential account of emotion, which stressed the bodily and physiological constitution of various feeling-states.1 The article reflected new trends in physiological psychology, but came under attack by numerous respondents in the journal who argued that there was more to the emotions than physiology.2 As the evolutionary psychologist Hiram Stanley intoned, "emotions in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  32
    (1 other version)Sympathy.Nancy E. Snow - 2013 - In Hugh LaFollette, The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell.
    The term “sympathy” has two meanings in philosophical literature. According to one conception, “sympathy” commonly means having care and concern for another whose well-being is under threat or is encountering some obstacle (Darwall 1998: 261). When I feel sympathy, I feel for the other (Darwall 1998: 261). The Confucian philosopher Mengzi (also known as Mencius), for example, writes that a person seeing a small child on the verge of falling into a well would be moved by alarm (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Adam Smith’s concept of sympathy and its contemporary interpretations.Bence Nanay - 2010 - Adam Smith Review 5:85-105.
    Adam Smith’s account of sympathy or ‘fellow feeling’ has recently become exceedingly popular. It has been used as an antecedent of the concept of simulation: understanding, or attributing mental states to, other people by means of simulating them. It has also been singled out as the first correct account of empathy. Finally, to make things even more complicated, some of Smith’s examples for sympathy or ‘fellow feeling’ have been used as the earliest expression of emotional contagion. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  11.  74
    The Ethical Importance of Sympathy.H. B. Acton - 1955 - Philosophy 30 (112):62 - 66.
    It seems natural enough to suppose that there must be some very close connection between our feelings of sympathy and our moral principles. A large part, at any rate, of the badness of bad men seems to consist in their lack of real concern for other people, and a large part of the goodness of good men consists in the regard they have for their fellows. Could a man who never felt with of for another be regarded as good, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12.  60
    The relationship between empathy and sympathy in good health care.Fredrik Svenaeus - 2015 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 18 (2):267-277.
    Whereas empathy is most often looked upon as a virtue and essential skill in contemporary health care, the relationship to sympathy is more complicated. Empathic approaches that lead to emotional arousal on the part of the health care professional and strong feelings for the individual patient run the risk of becoming unprofessional in nature and having the effect of so-called compassion fatigue or burnout. In this paper I want to show that approaches to empathy in health care that attempt (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  13.  95
    Hume, Sympathy, and the Theater.Brian Kirby - 2003 - Hume Studies 29 (2):305-325.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Studies Volume 29, Number 2, November 2003, pp. 305-325 Hume, Sympathy, and the Theater BRIAN KIRBY Every movement of the theater, by a skillful poet, is communicated, as it were by magic, to the spectators; who weep, tremble, resent, rejoice, and are inflamed with all the variety of passions, which actuate the several personages of the drama. (EPM 5.2.26; SBN 221-2) Much has been written recently about (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  58
    Barriers to Feeling and Actualizing Compassion.Lani Roberts - 2001 - Philosophy in the Contemporary World 8 (1):13-19.
    Hume and Rousseau argue that “feeling with and/or for others” is natural and basic to us as human persons. but Royce claims that merely feeling the fleeting impulse of sympathy is not the moral insight itself. Compassion must be both felt and acted upon for it to play the role in morality ascribed by Hume and Rousseau. Why is it so often the case that we fail to feel compassion for others and, even when we do, why (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  21
    Sympathy, Scruple, and Piety: The Moral and Religious Valuation of Nonhumans.Steven G. Smith - 1993 - Journal of Religious Ethics 21 (2):319 - 342.
    Our moral valuation of nonhuman and human beings alike may arise in sympathy, the realization in feeling of a significant commonality between self and others; in scrupulous observance of policy, the affirmation in practical consistency of a system of relations with others; and in piety, the attitude of boundless appreciation and absolute scruple with respect to objects as sacred - that is, as valued for the sake of adequate valuation of the holy. Differences between the moral status of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. On Susan Moller Okin’s “Reason and Feeling in Thinking about Justice”.Alison M. Jaggar - 2015 - Ethics 125 (4):1127-1131.
    An essay on the article "Reason and Feeling in Thinking about Justice," by Susan Moller Okin is presented. It offers a history of the original position in philosophical reasoning for explaining a sense of justice and examines feminist criticisms against such thinking for failure to appreciate differences and otherness while focused on universality and impartiality. The author relates the choice feminist theories on ethic of sympathy or care for others in place of an ethic of justice in general.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Empathy and sympathy as tactile encounter.Edith Wyschogrod - 1981 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 6 (1):25-44.
    Empathy and sympathy are feeling-acts which bring the self into direct encounter with other persons. In empathy a self grasps the affective act of another self; in sympathy x n persons apprehend a common object while immersed in similar feeling acts. Since touch is the paradigmatic sense for bringing what is felt into proximity with feeling, structural affinities between touch and these feeling acts can be shown. This relationship has been obscured by classical theories (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  18. I Feel You: Toward a Schelerian Conception of Empathy.Jean Moritz Müller - 2023 - In Christiana Werner, Empathy's Role in Understanding Persons, Literature, and Art. New York, NY: Routledge. pp. 272-295.
    In his The Nature of Sympathy, Max Scheler (2007 [1923]) offers an intriguing, if puzzling, account of empathy. According to this account, empathy is a specific kind of feeling through which we are immediately aware of others’ emotions but which is not itself an emotion and doesn’t require us to have those emotions ourselves. Moreover, qua immediate awareness of others’ emotions empathy is supposed to afford understanding why they feel those emotions. Although having echoes with ordinary discourse and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  12
    Doing empathy and sympathy: caring responses to troubles tellings on a peer support line.Christopher Pudlinski - 2005 - Discourse Studies 7 (3):267-288.
    Conversation analysis of 53 emotive responses to troubles tellings on a peer support line discovered eight different methods for expressing empathy and/or sympathy. Emotive reactions, assessments, and formulating the gist of the trouble typically occur early on in a troubles telling. Reporting one’s own reaction was found in the midst of troubles telling, as a second reaction to ‘bad’ news or after callers’ reports of their own feelings. Naming another’s feelings and using an idiom occur towards the end of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  20.  32
    Kant on Rational Sympathy.Benjamin Vilhauer - 2024 - Cambridge University Press.
    This Element explains Kant's distinction between rational sympathy and natural sympathy. Rational sympathy is regulated by practical reason and is necessary for adopting as our own those ends of others which are contingent from the perspective of practical rationality. Natural sympathy is passive and can prompt affect and dispose us to act wrongly. Sympathy is a function of a posteriori productive imagination. In rational sympathy, we freely use the imagination to step into others' first-person (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  57
    Feeling, Impulse and Changeability: The Role of Emotion in Hume's Theory of the Passions.Katharina A. Paxman - unknown
    Hume’s “impressions of reflection” is a category made up of all our non-sensory feelings, including “the passions and other emotions.” These two terms for affective mental states, ‘passion’ and ‘emotion’, are both used frequently in Hume’s work, and often treated by scholars as synonymous. I argue that Hume’s use of both ‘passion’ and ‘emotion’ in his discussions of affectivity reflects a conceptual distinction implicit in his work between what I label ‘attending emotions’ and ‘fully established passions.’ The former are the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  36
    Aristotle on Thought and Feeling by Paula Gottlieb (review).Corinne Gartner - 2023 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 61 (4):703-705.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Aristotle on Thought and Feeling by Paula GottliebCorinne GartnerPaula Gottlieb. Aristotle on Thought and Feeling. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2021. Pp. 173. Hardback, $99.99.Paula Gottlieb's recent book is an illuminating, synoptic study of Aristotle's theory of human motivation, according to which his innovative notion of prohairesis (choice)—specifically, the virtuous agent's prohairesis—is the cornerstone. She argues against both Kantian-flavored readings, which prioritize reason's role in motivating ethical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. The Worm at the Root of the Passions: Poetry and Sympathy in Mill's Utilitarianism: L. A. Paul.L. A. Paul - 1998 - Utilitas 10 (1):83-104.
    I claim that Mill has a theory of poetry which he uses to reconcile nineteenth century associationist psychology, the tendency of the intellect to dissolve associations, and the need for educated members of society to desire utilitarian ends. The heart of the argument is that Mill thinks reading poetry encourages us to feel the feelings of others, and thus to develop pleasurable associations with the pleasurable feelings of others and painful associations with the painful feelings of others. Once the associations (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24. Zhu Xi on Self-Focused vs. Other-Focused Empathy.Justin Tiwald - 2020 - In Kai-Chiu Ng & Yong Huang, Dao Companion to Zhu Xi’s Philosophy. Springer. pp. 963-980.
    This chapter is about issues in ethics and moral psychology that have been little explored by contemporary philosophers, ones that concern the advantages and disadvantages of two different kinds of empathy. Roughly, first type is what is sometimes called “other-focused” empathy, in which one reconstructs the thoughts and feelings that someone else has or would have. The second type, “self-focused” empathy, is the sort of emotional attitude someone adopts when she imagines how she would think or feel were she in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25. “Reason's sympathy” and others' ends in Kant.Benjamin Vilhauer - 2021 - European Journal of Philosophy 30 (1):96-112.
    Kant’s notion of (what I will call) rational sympathy solves a problem about how we can voluntarily fulfill our imperfect duty to adopt those ends of others which have value only because they have been set by rational agents, ends which I will refer to as merely permissible ends (MPEs). Others’ MPEs are individuated in terms of their own concepts of their MPEs, and we can only adopt their MPEs in terms of their concepts, since to adopt them in (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26.  45
    “Feminist” Sympathy and Other Serious Crimes.Patricia Jagentowicz Mills - 1992 - The Owl of Minerva 24 (1):55-62.
    The first two-thirds of Stuart Swindle’s article, “Why Feminists Should Take the Phenomenology of Spirit Seriously,” amounts to little more than rhetorical misogyny: “Those poor feminists, trapped in ‘the little stories’ of the Hegelian system, unable to see for themselves that what is really important is Hegel’s ‘big story.’ Why those poor creatures, those feminists just cannot see the forest for the trees! How could they be so small-minded: trying to turn such monumental philosophy into “an activists’ handbook”! On top (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  50
    Commentary on "Psychopathy, Other-Regarding Moral Beliefs, and Responsibility".Gwen Adshead - 1996 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 3 (4):279-281.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Commentary on“Psychopathy, Other-Regarding Moral Beliefs, and Responsibility”Gwen Adshead (bio)AbstractIn this commentary, I address two points raised by Fields: the origin of other-regarding beliefs, and the management of psychopaths, if they are not criminally responsible (as Fields suggests). I argue that the capacity to form affective bonds is necessary in order to hold other-regarding beliefs, and that a psychological developmental perspective may be helpful in understanding the moral understanding of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  40
    Sympathy for the Other: Female Solidarity and Postcolonial Subjectivity in Francophone Cinema.Kathleen Scott & Stefanie Van de Peer - 2016 - Film-Philosophy 20 (1):168-194.
    In this article we explore how female sympathy and solidarity can be forged between transnational subjects and spectators. In particular, we place cinematic depictions of minority female suffering in the contexts of current feminist and postcolonial praxes. The aim is to demonstrate the ways in which world cinema can produce a transnational feminist solidarity through forms and narratives that reflect the experiences of women as gendered postcolonial subjects. Amongst the female and feminist theorists drawn upon, central to our understanding (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  25
    Sympathy for the underdog: people are inclined to adopt the emotional perspective of powerless (versus powerful) others.François Quesque, Alexandre Foncelle, Elodie Barat, Eric Chabanat, Yves Rossetti & Jean-Baptiste Van der Henst - forthcoming - Cognition and Emotion:1-16.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  54
    On sympathy: With other creatures.Ian Hacking - 2001 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 63 (4):685 - 717.
    Animal liberationists have increased our moral concern for animals, to the extent that many now think that animals have rights. I am very cautious about the arguments of these philosophers, although I agree with many of their precepts. In this respect, I am aligned with the powerful essays of Cora Diamond. I argue that something like what Hume calls sympathy is essential for expanding circles of moral concern, and develop some Humeian ideas. Sympathy with, and not simply (...) for. Suffering is too narrow a range of concern. It is not as if the pain and pleasure of the utilitarians were the only ways in which we could be concerned with others. As Hume argued, animals share most human emotions, and it is through sympathy with the entire range that our worlds join. It is increasingly difficult for most of us to realize this, because human relationships with animals have changed since Hume's day. The multi-species barnyard has all but disappeared. We now live in a world of televised wilderness. To exaggerate, our species lives alone for the first time. Animal liberationists have the effect of enlarging our moral world, but should do so not just by attending to suffering or to rights of an animal, but to the whole creature, a being with which we can resonate. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  14
    Se transporter dans l'autre" : une théorie weilienne de l’empathie?Blandine Delanoy - 2024 - Labyrinth: An International Journal for Philosophy, Value Theory and Sociocultural Hermeneutics 25 (2):74-92.
    Defined as the ability to understand and share others' feelings and suffering, empathy seems to come naturally to mind when we consider Simone Weil's life and works. If this concept doesn't explicitly appear in her writings, "pity", "sympathy" and "compassion" are pervasive: the purpose of this paper is to demonstrate how these notions converge on the contemporary understanding of "empathy". Since the turn of the century, this concept has known such a development that it has become difficult to clearly (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  36
    Differences in the Social Motivations and Emotions of Humans and Other Great Apes.Michael Tomasello - 2023 - Human Nature 34 (4):588-604.
    Humans share with other mammals and primates many social motivations and emotions, but they are also much more cooperative than even their closest primate relatives. Here I review recent comparative experiments and analyses that illustrate humans’ species-typical social motivations and emotions for cooperation in comparison with those of other great apes. These may be classified most generally as (i) ‘you > me’ (e.g., prosocial sympathy, informative and pedagogical motives in communication); (ii) ‘you = me’ (e.g., feelings of mutual respect, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  16
    A Note on Being Ability–different, Atypically–bodied... Criptastic?Emily Hutcheon - 2013 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 3 (3):196-199.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:A Note on Being Ability–different, Atypically–bodied... Criptastic?Emily HutcheonIn being prompted to write about my experiences with disability [alternatively written: (dis)ability, dis/ability, “disability,” disAbility], I am confronted with more questions than I have answers. Am I to reflect on that small window of time, one so small that I don’t actually remember it, when I did not know that I was different? My mom [End Page 196] has recounted vivid (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. 'In Examining Others We Know Ourselves': Joanna Baillie on Sympathetic Curiosity, Moral Education, and Drama.Lauren Kopajtic - 2024 - Journal of Modern Philosophy 6.
    This paper argues that Joanna Baillie’s ‘Introductory Discourse’ to her Plays on Passions offers a theory of moral education based on an epistemology of passion—an account of how we come to know and understand the passions—both of which deserve further philosophical attention. Like her fellow Scots, David Hume and Adam Smith, Baillie offers a sentimentalist approach to human psychology, focusing on affective states as the primary constituents of character and determinants of action. She also shares a spectatorial approach to moral (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  87
    When Bad Things Happen to Other People.John Portmann - 1999 - New York: Routledge.
    Although many of us deny it, it is not uncommon to feel pleasure over the suffering of others, particularly when we feel that suffering has been deserved. The German word for this concept-_Schadenfreude_-has become universal in its expression of this feeling. Drawing on the teachings of history's most prominent philosophers, John Portmann explores the concept of _Schadenfreude_ in this rigorous, comprehensive, and absorbing study.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  36.  26
    Feeling Responsible: On Regret for Others’ Harms.Magnus Ferguson - 2024 - Philosophy 99 (2):247-271.
    This paper investigates the moral emotion of being socially, but non-agentially connected to a harm. I propose understanding the emotion of an affiliated onlooker as a species of regret called ‘social-regret’. Breaking from existing guilt- and shame-based accounts, I argue that social-regret can be a fitting, expressive, and revelatory reactive attitude that opens the way for deliberation over accountability for others’ harms. When we feel social-regret, our attention is directed towards the moral salience of our social relations and the expectations (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  18
    Reading Russian Philosophy and Max Scheler Together: The Problem of the Other I.A. A. Tchikine - 2019 - Russian Journal of Philosophical Sciences 62 (2):127-141.
    The article explores the parallels between the theory of sympathy developed by Max Scheler and the understanding of the foreign I in Russian philosophy. Russian philosophy has been developing the topic of foreign psychic life since the 1880s, and it regards Scheler’s theory as unable to raise above the level of emotional contagion. True sympathy is possible, when the Other is already present to the I, or, according to Nikolay Lossky, there is an original gnoseological difference between “the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  33
    To feel what others feel: two episodes from 18th century medicine.Stewart Justman - 2011 - Medical Humanities 37 (1):34-37.
    In the late 18th century two medical fashions—Mesmerism in France and the Perkins ‘tractor’ in the USA and England—appealed to the principle that a single universal force acts on all of us and is responsible for health and illness. This principle served both fashions well, as it made it all the easier for those who came within their force fields to experience the sort of sensations that other subscribers to the fashion also seemed to feel. The first research on what (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  49
    Morality From Compassion.Ingmar Persson - 2021 - Oxford University Press.
    According to Arthur Schopenhauer, compassion is the basis of morality. He sees concern for justice as a negative form of compassion, directed at not harming anyone, as opposed to the more far-reaching, positive form of benefiting. He thinks a higher degree of compassion involves realizing that the spatio-temporal separation of individuals is illusory and that in reality they are all identical. Such compassion is impartial and all-encompassing. Compassion is suited to be the centre of morality because its object are negative (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  17
    Emotion, reason, and action in Kant.Maria Borges - 2019 - New York: Bloomsbury Academic.
    Action, reason, and causes in Kant -- Can we act without feelings? Respect, sympathy and other forms of love -- A place for affects and passion in the Kantian system -- What can Kant teach us about emotions? -- Physiology and the controlling of affects in Kant's philosophy -- Virtue as a cure for affects and passions -- The beautiful and the good: refinement as an introduction to morality -- Women and emotion -- Evil and passion -- An emotional (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41. Leporello's question.Garry Hagberg - 2005 - Philosophy and Literature 29 (1):180-199.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Leporello's QuestionGarry L. HagbergOne finds in the later philosophical writings of Ludwig Wittgenstein an articulation of the distinctive attitude we bring to the perception of human beings. This attitude, called by Wittgenstein "Eine Einstellung zur Seele," an attitude towards a soul, is irreducible—it cannot be analyzed into any more basic constituent parts—and it is the precondition for our sympathetic and imaginative understanding of others. It serves at the same (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Food as art: The problem of function.Marienne L. Quinet - 1981 - British Journal of Aesthetics 21 (2):159-171.
    Works of culinary expertise are not typically regarded as works of "fine" art, in the way that, say, paintings, etchings, symphonies and sculptures are. I argue, however, that any form of creativity embodied in a perceptible work reflecting it is a subject about which we might exercise "aesthetic judgments" that do not differ fundamentally from the sorts typical with regard to the usual "fine" arts. To reserve a special notion for marking off the latter simply disguises the fact that it (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  43.  47
    Hume, Hermeneutics, and History: A "Sympathetic" Account.James Farr - 1978 - History and Theory 17 (3):285-310.
    Though Hume is often considered the hero of analytic philosophy in its positivistic phase, his concept of sympathy can be understood as an eighteenth- century prototype of Verstehen. Sympathy is central to Hume's moral philosophy, as he considered it the source of human motivation, social interaction, evaluation, and understanding. It has been acknowledged that sympathy, for Hume, was the human ability to associate with the sensations and passions of others. However, he also stated that this association was (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  44.  72
    Hume Contra Spinoza?Wim Klever - 1990 - Hume Studies 16 (2):89-105.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Contra Spinoza? Wim Klever In Book 1 ofthe TreatiseofHumanNature1 Spinoza enjoys thehonour ofbeing the only figure from the history of philosophy and science to be explicitly and extensively discussed by Hume. This honour is, however, a dubious one as the treatment he gets is not so friendly. The passage (T 232-51) is full of insults and denunciations: Spinoza is referred to as "that famous atheist" (T 241), and (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  45.  86
    Utility and Morality: Adam Smith's Critique of Hume.Marie A. Martin - 1990 - Hume Studies 16 (2):107-120.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Utility and Morality: Adam Smith's Critique of Hume Marie A. Martin Reading Smith's Theory ofMoral Sentiments one cannot help but note that, in spite ofthe obvious similarities between Smith and Hume and the equally obvious borrowings and adaptions Smith makesofportions of Hume's theory, the two differ substantially on the role of utility in morality. The difference is, in fact, practically diametrical opposition. Hume believed that utility was the "foundation (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46.  27
    The Moral Value of Social Shame in Adam Smith's The Theory of Moral Sentiments.Şule Ozler - 2024 - Journal of Scottish Philosophy 22 (1):37-55.
    Central to the debate on the moral relevance of shame is whether we take others’ assessments of our moral shortcomings seriously. Some argue that viewing shame as a social emotion undermines the moral standing of shame; for a moral agent, what is authoritative are his own moral values, not the mere disapproval of others. Adam Smith's framework sheds some light on the contemporary debates in philosophy on the moral value of shame. Shame is mostly a social emotion but has moral (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  34
    Historical and critical dictionary.John B. Wolf - 1968 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 6 (1):85-86.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:BOOK REVIEWS 85 scientious search for principles of method (and of peace) may have been one of the reasons why he was suspect in England, as were the Ramist "methodists." In any case, it is quite clear now that Hobbes was not a materialist, not even when he was writing De Corpore. HERBERT W. SCHNEIDER Claremont, CallJornia Pierre Bayle, Historical and Critical Dictionary selections. Translated with an Introduction and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  31
    Politeness.Henri Bergson - 2016 - Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy 24 (2):3-9.
    This is the English translation of a speech Bergson made at Lycée Henri-IV on July 30, 1892. This is an interesting text because it anticipates Bergson’s last book, his The Two Sources of Morality and Religion. Like the distinction in The Two Sources between the open and the closed, “Politeness” defines its subject matter in two ways. There is what Bergson calls “manners” and there is true politeness. For Bergson, both kinds of politeness concern equality. Manners or material politeness amount (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49.  20
    Introduction.Taras Zakydalsky - 1997 - Russian Studies in Philosophy 36 (3):4-6.
    The first four selections in this issue are devoted to the question of the future of science in Russia. A. V. Iurevich and I. P. Tsapenko outline the depressed state of Russian science today and the tendencies that, unless checked, will bring about its complete collapse. The precipitous decline in government financing of research has not been offset by support from international foundations or private business in Russia. The salaries of scientists are among the lowest in the economy—below the official (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. The Task of Peace Journalism.Johan Galtung - 2000 - Ethical Perspectives 7 (2):162-167.
    During the last 42 years I have been a mediator in 48 countries, in some of them with success. One of the reasons for that success is that I have a certain skill: I've avoided any contact with journalists. For that reason it's with some trepidation that I enter this room and listen to the discussion today which was at such a high academic level and never touched reality.Let me start by posing some questions for you to consider. Are you (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 968