Results for 'Aristotle, Physics, Change'

952 found
Order:
  1.  49
    Reading Aristotle: Physics VII.3. “What is Alteration?” Proceedings of the International ESAP-HYELE Conference Reading Aristotle: Physics VII.3. “What is Alteration?” Proceedings of the International ESAP-HYELE Conference ed. by Stephano Maso, Carlo Natali, and Gerhard Seel (review). [REVIEW]Mariska Leunissen - 2013 - American Journal of Philology 134 (1):155-159.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Reading Aristotle: Physics VII.3. “What is Alteration?” Proceedings of the International ESAP-HYELE Conference Reading Aristotle: Physics VII.3. “What is Alteration?” Proceedings of the International ESAP-HYELE Conference ed. by Stephano Maso, Carlo Natali, and Gerhard SeelMariska LeunissenStephano Maso, Carlo Natali, and Gerhard Seel, eds. Reading Aristotle: Physics VII.3. “What is Alteration?” Proceedings of the International ESAP-HYELE Conference. Las Vegas, Nev.: Parmenides Publishing, 2012. xvii + 152 pp. Paper, $65.As (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Time for Aristotle: Physics IV.10-14.Ursula Coope - 2005 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    What is the relation between time and change? Does time depend on the mind? Is the present always the same or is it always different? Aristotle tackles these questions in the Physics. In the first book in English exclusively devoted to this discussion, Ursula Coope argues that Aristotle sees time as a universal order within which all changes are related to each other. This interpretation enables her to explain two striking Aristotelian claims: that the now is like a moving (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  3.  50
    Time for Aristotle: Physics IV.10-14, by Ursula Coope. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005.Tony Roark - unknown
    Aristotle’s views on time have received sporadic at tention over the years, but Ursula Coope’s elegantl y- written book is the first monograph available in En glish dedicated exclusively to the account that Ari stotle develops in the final five chapters of Physics IV. Three topics form the thematic core of the boo k: time’s relation to change, time’s status as a kind of numb er, and the unity and diversity of times. I shall t ouch on each of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  82
    Nature, Change, and Agency in Aristotle's Physics: A Philosophical Study.Sarah Waterlow - 1982 - New York: Clarendon Press.
    An investigation into Aristotle's metaphysics of nature as expounded in the Physics. It focuses in particular his conception of change, a concept which is shown to possess a unique metaphysical structure, with implications that should engage the attention of contemporary analysis. First published in hardback in 1982, the book is now available for the first time in paperback. 'A powerful and appealing explanatory scheme which succeeds on the whole in drawing together a great many seemingly disparate elements in the (...)
  5.  88
    Time Matter and Form: Essays on Aristotles Physics.David Bostock - 2006 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Space, Time, Matter, and Form collects ten of David Bostock's essays on themes from Aristotle's Physics, four of them published here for the first time. The first five papers look at issues raised in the first two books of the Physics, centred on notions of matter and form, and the idea of substance as what persists through change. They also range over other of Aristotle's scientific works, such as his biology and psychology and the account of change in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  14
    The Chain of Change: A Study of Aristotle's Physics VII.Robert Wardy - 1990 - Cambridge University Press.
    The Chain of Change is the first full-scale philosophical commentary devoted to Aristotle's Physics VII, in which Aristotle argues for the existence of a first, unmoved cosmic mover. This study systematically considers the major issues of the book, and argues for the fundamental importance of Physics VII in our understanding of Aristotelian cosmology and natural science. Physics VII is extant in two versions, and therefore poses special editorial problems. For this reason one of the features of Dr. Wardy's study (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  7. (1 other version)Nature, Change and Agency in Aristotle's `Physics', A Philosophical Study.Sarah Waterlow - 1984 - Mind 93 (370):297-300.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  8. Why Continuous Motions Cannot Be Composed of Sub-motions: Aristotle on Change, Rest, and Actual and Potential Middles.Caleb Cohoe - 2018 - Apeiron 51 (1):37-71.
    I examine the reasons Aristotle presents in Physics VIII 8 for denying a crucial assumption of Zeno’s dichotomy paradox: that every motion is composed of sub-motions. Aristotle claims that a unified motion is divisible into motions only in potentiality (δυνάμει). If it were actually divided at some point, the mobile would need to have arrived at and then have departed from this point, and that would require some interval of rest. Commentators have generally found Aristotle’s reasoning unconvincing. Against David Bostock (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  9.  15
    Nature, Change and Agency in Aristotle's Physics.W. Charlton - 1983 - Philosophical Books 24 (1):11-14.
  10. Nature, Change and Agency in Aristotle’s Physics.Sarah Broadie - 1982 - In . Oxford University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  11. (1 other version)Change in Aristotle's Physics 3.Andreas Anagnostopoulos - 2010 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 39:33-79.
  12.  21
    Aristotle's Physics Alpha: Symposium Aristotelicum.Katerina Ierodiakonou, Paul Kalligas & Vassilis Karasmanis (eds.) - 2019 - Oxford University Press.
    Eleven scholars present a collaborative commentary on the first book of Aristotle's Physics. This text is central to Aristotle's studies of the natural world and the principles of physical change. He formulates his theory on the basis of critical examination of hispredecessors' views, so the book is also a key source for early Greek philosophy.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  56
    Nature, Change, and Agency in Aristotle’s Physics. [REVIEW]David Furley - 1984 - Ancient Philosophy 4 (1):108-110.
  14.  88
    Aristotle on Self-Change in Plants.Daniel Coren - 2019 - Rhizomata 7 (1):33-62.
    A lot of scholarly attention has been given to Aristotle’s account of how and why animals are capable of moving themselves. But no one has focused on the question, whether self-change is possible in plants on Aristotle’s account. I first give some context and explain why this topic is worth exploring. I then turn to Aristotle’s conditions for self-change given in Physics VIII.4, where he argues that the natural motion of the elements does not count as self-motion. I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  15.  20
    Aristotle's Physics: a critical guide.Mariska Leunissen (ed.) - 2015 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    Aristotle's study of the natural world plays a tremendously important part in his philosophical thought. He was very interested in the phenomena of motion, causation, place and time, and teleology, and his theoretical materials in this area are collected in his Physics, a treatise of eight books which has been very influential on later thinkers. This volume of new essays provides cutting-edge research on Aristotle's Physics, taking into account recent changes in the field of Aristotle in terms of its understanding (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  16. Motion and Change in Aristotle’s Physics 5. 1.Jacob Rosen - 2012 - Phronesis 57 (1):63-99.
    Abstract This paper illustrates how Aristotle's topological theses about change in Physics 5-6 can help address metaphysical issues. Two distinctions from Physics 5. 1 are discussed: changing per se versus changing per aliud ; motion versus change. Change from white to black is motion and alteration, whereas change from white to not white is neither. But is not every change from white to black identical with a change from white to not white? Theses from (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  35
    Aristotle on Time and Change.Andrea Falcon - 2013 - In Adrian Bardon & Heather Dyke (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Time. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 47–58.
    Aristotle's discussion of time is part of his Physics, which was an important part of the philosophical curriculum of late antiquity. Aristotle says that it is because nature is a principle of change that people must establish what change is. This chapter focuses on his scientific treatment of time. Aristotle begins his discussion of time by engaging in the examination of a set of puzzles (aporiai). He clearly indicates that this examination is embedded in the two‐stage inquiry. Aristotle (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18.  6
    Nature, change, and agency in Aristotle's Physics: a philosophical study.Sarah Broadie - 1982 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    A powerful and appealing explanatory scheme which succeeds on the whole in drawing together a great many seemingly disparate elements in the Physics' into a neat unitary structure.' Canadian Philosophical Reviews.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19.  18
    Change and contrariety in Aristotle, James Bogen Aristotle says that in all coming to be and passing away things arise from or perish into contraries or into intermediates which lie in between and are derived from contraries (physics 188b21-26, and elsewhere). This paper takes up two questions about this:(1) does Aristotle say enough. [REVIEW]Craven Nussbaum & Rene Lefebvre - 1992 - Phronesis 37 (1).
  20.  17
    Aristotle’s Methodology for Natural Science in Physics 1-2: a New Interpretation.Evan Dutmer - 2020 - Journal of Ancient Philosophy 14 (2):130-146.
    In this essay I will argue for an interpretation of the remarks of Physics 1.1 that both resolves some of the confusion surrounding the precise nature of methodology described there and shows how those remarks at 184a15-25 serve as important programmatic remarks besides, as they help in the structuring of books 1 and 2 of the Physics. I will argue that “what is clearer and more knowable to us” is what Aristotle goes on to describe in 1.2—namely, that nature exists (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Aristotle's Ontology of Change.Mark Sentesy - 2020 - Chicago, IL, USA: Northwestern University Press.
    This book investigates what change is, according to Aristotle, and how it affects his conception of being. Mark Sentesy argues that change leads Aristotle to develop first-order metaphysical concepts such as matter, potency, actuality, sources of being, and the teleology of emerging things. He shows that Aristotle’s distinctive ontological claim—that being is inescapably diverse in kind—is anchored in his argument for the existence of change. -/- Aristotle may be the only thinker to have given a noncircular definition (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  40
    The Chain of Change: A Study of Aristotle's Physics VIIRobert Wardy.David Hahm - 1993 - Isis 84 (3):556-557.
  23.  10
    Reading Aristotle's Physics Vii.3: "What is Alteration?": Proceedings of the European Society for Ancient Philosophy Conference: Organized by the Hyele Institute for Comparative Studies, Vitznau, Switzerland, 12/15 April 2007.Stefano Maso, Carlo Natali & Gerhard Seel (eds.) - 2011 - Las Vegas, Zurich, Athens: Parmenides.
    Aristotle has a rather extreme concept of change: Alteration is the change of a sensible quality in a thing. This is produced when a thing comes into immediate contact with another thing and is affected by the opposite sensible quality of the latter. Book VII, chapter 3 of the Aristotelian Physics is the crucial text to explore this topic. The present volume sets out to analyze and clarify the reason of this approach.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. Changing Aristotle's mind and world : critical notes on McDowell's Aristotle.Matthew Sharpe - 2012 - Philosophy Study 2 (11):804-821.
    Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics is central to John McDowell’s classic Mind and World. In Lectures IV and V of that work, McDowell makes three claims concerning Aristotle’s ethics: first, that Aristotle did not base his ethics on an externalist, naturalistic basis (including a theory of human nature); second, that attempts to read him as an ethical naturalist are a modern anachronism, generated by the supposed need to ground all viable philosophical claims on claims analogous to the natural sciences; and third, that (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Aristotle’s Physics: The Metaphysics of Change, Matter, Motion and Time.Philipp Blum - manuscript
  26. Heraclitus, Change and Objective Contradictions in Aristotle’s Metaphysics Γ.Celso Vieira - 2022 - Rhizomata 10 (2):183-214.
    In Metaphysics Γ, Aristotle argues against those who seem to accept contradictions. He distinguishes between the Sophists, who deny the principle of non-contradiction through arguments, and the Natural Philosophers, whose physical investigations lead to the acceptance of objective contradictions. Heraclitus’ name appears throughout the discussion. Usually, he is associated with the discussion against the Sophists. In this paper, I explore how the discussion with the Natural Philosophers may illuminate both the interpretation of Heraclitus by Aristotle and Heraclitus’ own worldview. To (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. A Fault Line in Aristotle’s Physics.Arnold Brooks - 2019 - Ancient Philosophy 39 (2):335-361.
    In Physics 4.11, Aristotle says that changes are continuous because magnitude is continuous. I suggest that this is not Aristotle’s considered view, and that in Generation and Corruption 2.10 Aristotle argues that this leads to the unacceptable consequence that alterations can occur discontinuously. Physics 6.4 was written to amend this theory, and to argue that changes are continuous because changing bodies are so. I also discuss the question of Aristotle’s consistency on the possibility of discontinuous alterations, such as freezing.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Aristotle’s Physics 5.1, 225a1-b5.John Bowin - 2019 - Philosophical Inquiry 43:147-164.
    This contribution offers an interpretation of the last half of chapter 1 of book 5 of Aristotle’s Physics in the form of a commentary. Among other things, it attempts an explanation of why Aristotle calls the termini of changes ‘something underlying’ (ὑποκείμενον) and ‘something not underlying’ (μὴ ὑποκείμενον). It also provides an analysis of Aristotle’s argument for the claim that what is not simpliciter does not change in the light of this interpretation.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Alteration and Aristotle's Theory of Change in Physics 6.Damian Murphy - 2008 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 34:185-218.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  42
    Geometrical Changes: Change and Motion in Aristotle’s Philosophy of Geometry.Chiara Martini - 2023 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (3):385-394.
    Graduate Papers from the 2022 Joint Session. It is often said that Aristotle takes geometrical objects to be absolutely unmovable and unchangeable. However, Greek geometrical practice does appeal to motion and change, and geometers seem to consider their objects apt to be manipulated. In this paper, I examine if and how Aristotle’s philosophy of geometry can account for the geometers’ practices and way of talking. First, I illustrate three different ways in which Greek geometry appeals to change. Second, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  62
    The Eleatic Challenge in Aristotle’s Physics I.8.Scott O’Connor - 2017 - Rhizomata 5 (1):25-50.
    In Physics I.8, Aristotle outlines and responds to an Eleatic argument against the reality of change. I defend a new reading according to which the argu- ment assumes Predicational Monism, the claim that each being can possess only one property. In Phys. I.2, Aristotle responds to Predicational Monism, which he attributes to the Eleatics; I argue that he uses this response to distinguish coin- cidental from non-coincidental becoming, a distinction he employs in Phys I.8 to resolve the argument against (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. Physics V–VI vs. VIII: : Unity of Change and Disunity in the Physics.Jacob Rosen - 2015 - In Mariska Leunissen (ed.), Aristotle's Physics: a critical guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 206–224.
    Aristotle offers several arguments in Physics viii.8 for his thesis that, when something moves back and forth, it does not undergo a single motion. These arguments occur against the background of a sophisticated theory, expounded in Physics v—vi, of the basic structure of motions and of other continuous entities such as times and magnitudes. The arguments in Physics viii.8 stand in a complex relation to that theory. On the one hand, Aristotle evidently relies on the theory in a number of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  33.  22
    Aristotle's Physics and Cosmology.István Bodnár & Pierre Pellegrin - 2018 - In Sean D. Kirkland & Eric Sanday (eds.), A Companion to Ancient Philosophy. Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press. pp. 270–291.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The Principles of Physics The Science of Natural Beings Motion, Causal Interaction, and Causational Synonymy Aristotelian Kinematics Aristotle's Theory of the Continuum The Causes of Elemental Motions Unmoved Movers Bibliography.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  12
    On Aristotle's Physics 4.1-5, 10-14.J. O. Simplicius & Urmson - 1992 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. Edited by J. O. Urmson.
    "This volume offers a new translation of the Neoplatonist philosopher Simplicius' commentary on the chapters concerning place and time in Aristotle's Physics, Book Four. Written after the closing of the Athenian Neoplatonist school in A.D. 529, the commentary clarifies the structure and meaning of Aristotle's arguments and provides a rich account of 800 years of interpretation." "Surprisingly, in the first five chapters of Book Four Aristotle shows place as two-dimensional: one's place is the two-dimensional inner surface of one's surroundings. He (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  37
    Nature, Change and Agency in Aristotle's "Physics": A Philosophical Study by Sarah Waterlow. [REVIEW]Robert Wardy - 1984 - Isis 75 (4):752-753.
  36. Aristotle on Non-substantial Particulars, Fundamentality, and Change.Keren Wilson Shatalov - 2024 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 106 (4):723-753.
    There is a debate about whether particular properties are for Aristotle non-recurrent and trope-like individuals or recurrent universals. I argue that Physics I.7 provides evidence that he took non-substantial particulars to be neither; they are instead non-recurrent modes. Physics I.7 also helps show why this matters. Particular properties must be individual modes in order for Aristotle to preserve three key philosophical commitments: that objects of ordinary experience are primary substances, that primary substances undergo genuine change, and that primary substances (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Aristotle on the Unity of Change.John Bowin - 2010 - Ancient Philosophy 30 (2):319-345.
  38.  19
    On Aristotle’s Physics 5. [REVIEW]Leo J. Elders - 1997 - Review of Metaphysics 51 (2):444-445.
    Book 5 stands between the first four books of the Physics and Books 6, 7, and 8, which are traditionally called the treatise On motion. Simplicius, however, attaches it to the first four books on the principles of physical reality, describing it as a supplement to Book 3. David Ross, in his monumental Aristotle’s Physics prefers to consider Books 5, 6, and 8 a coherent group of pragmateiai on motion, while 7 is a comparatively isolated book, a view shared by (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  83
    Why Aristotle Says There Is No Time Without Change.Tony Roark - 2004 - Apeiron 37 (3):227-246.
    The title of this paper is intended as a provocative reference to Ursula Coope 's recent article 'Why Does Aristotle Say That There Is No Time Without Change?', which provides much of the impetus for the present paper.1 For although Coope 's strategy in answering this question is admirable, and although I think that her criticisms of the standard interpretation of the argument that opens Physics IV 11 hit their mark, I believe that her own interpretation fails and that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40.  42
    Sarah Waterlow "Nature, Change and Agency in Aristotle's Physics".J. D. G. Evans - 1984 - Philosophical Quarterly 34 (134):78.
  41.  50
    The Chain of Change: a Study of Aristotle's Physics VII. [REVIEW]Lindsay Judson - 1992 - The Classical Review 42 (2):334-337.
  42.  41
    Aristotle's Physics II 1 and Cultivated Plants.Errol G. Katayama - 2018 - Science in Context 31 (4):405-419.
    ArgumentThe aim of this paper is two-fold: to offer an interpretation that preserves the natural reading ofPhysicsII 1 – that Aristotle is drawing a stark distinction between what is natural and what is artificial; and to show how there is logical room for atertium quid– a category for things that are products of both nature and art. This aim is attained by highlighting two important qualifications Aristotle makes about the products of art in relation to an innate internal principle of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43. Aristotle’s Resolution of the Aporia about Coming-To-Be in Physics I 8.Gabriela Rossi - 2017 - Eirene 53 (1):247-271.
    In Physica I,8 Aristotle endeavors to show that a long-term Eleatic puzzle about coming-to-be can be resolved by appealing to his own ontological principles of change (substratum, privation, and form). In this paper, I posit that the key to Aristotle’s resolution lies in the introduction of aspectual distinctions within numerical unities. These distinctions within the terminus a quo and the terminus as quem of coming-to-be made it possible for Aristotle to maintain, while answering the puzzle, that there is no (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. S. Waterlow, Nature, Change And Agency In Aristotle's Physics. [REVIEW]Michael Ferejohn - 1984 - Philosophy in Review 4:226-230.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  46
    Time of Change in Plato and Aristotle.Ondřej Krása - 2024 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 26 (2):232-252.
    When do things change? When do things have some characteristics? I try to answer these questions by looking at different solutions Plato and Aristotle presented in their works. The famous analysis of change from the second half of Plato’s Parmenides claims that change happens outside of time, at an “instant”. On the contrary, Aristotle in the Physics explicitly argues that all change occurs only in time. However, both Plato and Aristotle also provide other analyses of (...). How to deal with this variety of explanations and tensions between them? In this paper, I argue that if we differentiate between several kinds of change, most of Plato’s and Aristotle’s analyses provide a thorough insight into the nature of change. For processes such as locomotion, change occurs exclusively within time. For changes where both the initial and final states occur only in time, such as a transition from motion to rest, change takes place in the ‘now’. However, for changes where both the initial and final states occur in both time and in the ‘now’ – for example, a qualitative change from being white to not being white – change does not occur in time nor in the ‘now’, but instead happens instantaneously. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  65
    Passive Potentiality in the Physical Realm: Plotinus' Critique of Aristotle in Enneads II 5 [25].Cinzia Arruzza - 2011 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 93 (1):24-57.
    This article analyzes the status of passive potentiality of prime matter and sensible objects in Plotinus' Enneads. In particular, it will focus on Enneads II 5 [25] and confront it with other treatises, specifically Enneads III 6 [26]; II 6 [17]; VI 2 [43] and VI 3 [44]. It aims at offering a new interpretation of treatise 25 and at proposing a reconstruction of Plotinus' notion of change in the sensible realm that illustrates both his critique of Aristotle's notion (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  51
    (1 other version)Instantaneous change and the physics of sanctification: "Quasi-aristotelianism" in Henry of ghent's.Susan Brower-Toland - 2002 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 40 (1):19-46.
    In Quodlibet XV q.13, Henry of Ghent considers whether the Virgin Mary was immaculately conceived. He argues that she was not, but rather possessed sin only at the first instant of her existence. Because Henry’s defense of this position involves an elaborate discussion of motion and mutation, his discussion marks an important contribution to medieval discussions of Aristotelian natural philosophy. In fact, a number of scholars have identified Henry’s discussion as the source of an unusual fourteenth-century theory of change (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  31
    A Hylomorphic Reading of Non-Genuine Qualitative Changes in Aristotle’s Physics VII.3.Fei-Ting Chen - 2017 - Apeiron 50 (2):247-275.
    Journal Name: Apeiron Issue: Ahead of print.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  63
    The Subjects of Natural Generations in Aristotle’s Physics I.7.Scott O'Connor - 2015 - Apeiron 48 (1):45-75.
    In 'Physics' I.7, Aristotle claims that plants and animals are generated from sperma. Since most understood sperma to be an ovum, this claim threatens to undermine the standard view that, for Aristotle, the matter natural beings are generated from persists through their generation. By focusing on Aristotle’s discussion of sperma in the first book of the 'Generation of Animals', I show that, for Aristotle, sperma in the female is surplus blood collected in the uterus and not an ovum. I subsequently (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  31
    Robert Wardy. The Chain of Change: A Study of Aristotle's Physics VII. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990. Pp. x + 345. ISBN 0-521-37327-1. £35.00, $59.50. [REVIEW]David Bostock - 1992 - British Journal for the History of Science 25 (2):259-263.
1 — 50 / 952