Results for 'Aristotle's form'

963 found
Order:
  1.  70
    Aristotle's Forms of Justice.Ernest J. Weinrib - 1989 - Ratio Juris 2 (3):211-226.
    . In Aristotle's account, corrective and distributive justice are not particular substantive ideals, but are rather the formal patterns that inhere in interactions and in the legal arrangements that regulate them. Corrective and distributive justice are the structures of ordering internal to transactions and distributions, respectively. The Aristotelian. forms of justice thus constitute the rationality immanent to the relation ships of mutually external beings. This article stresses Aristotle's formalism, contrasting it to modem instrumental conceptions of legal rationality, and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2.  13
    Aristotle’s Form of the Species as Relation.Theodore Di Maria Jr - 2008 - Lyceum 9 (2).
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  85
    Aristotle’s Theory of Material Substance: Heat and Pneuma, Form and Soul.Christopher Shields & Gad Freudenthal - 1997 - Philosophical Review 106 (4):632.
    Fortunately, there is heat; and Freudenthal is keen to promote it as an overlooked central factor in Aristotle’s theory of material substance. He begins in agreement with the many scholars who argue that Aristotle’s theory of the four elements underdetermines the plain fact that there are organic substances which exhibit both synchronic and diachronic unity. He goes further than most, however, by arguing that left unaugmented Aristotle’s account of the four basic elements would positively preclude the existence of these forms (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  4. Aristotle’s Mereology And The Status Of Form.Kathrin Koslicki - 2006 - Journal of Philosophy 103 (12):715-736.
    In a difficult but fascinating passage in Metaphysics Z.17, Aristotle puts forward a proposal, by means of a regress argument, according to which a whole or matter/form-compound is one or unified, in contrast to a heap, due to the presence of form or essence. This proposal gives rise to two central questions: (i) the question of whether form itself is to be viewed, literally and strictly speaking, as part of the matter/form-compound; and (ii) the question of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  5.  91
    Aristotle's Eudemus and the Propaedeutic Use of the Dialogue Form.Matthew D. Walker - 2021 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 59 (3):399-427.
    By scholarly consensus, extant fragments from, and testimony about, Aristotle’s lost dialogue Eudemus provide strong evidence for thinking that Aristotle at some point defended the human soul’s unqualified immortality (either in whole or in part). I reject this consensus and develop an alternative, deflationary, speculative, but textually supported proposal to explain why Aristotle might have written a dialogue featuring arguments for the soul’s unqualified immortality. Instead of defending unqualified immortality as a doctrine, I argue, the Eudemus was most likely offering (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  1
    Aristotle’s Critique of Form-Number.Daniel Sung-Hyun Yang - 2024 - Elenchos: Rivista di Studi Sul Pensiero Antico 45 (2):229-254.
    Aristotle’s classification of ideal number in Metaphysics M 6 has often been considered an unfair presentation of Plato’s actual views. I take another look at the passage and argue that Aristotle is a more careful critic than has been usually recognised. In particular, I argue that much of the scholarly discussion on the passage has failed to take account of Aristotle’s deeper concern, namely, the conditions necessary for numbers to be ordinal. I then set Aristotle’s critique within the broader context (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  6
    Aristotle’s Employment of Platonic Forms in Zeta 6.G. T. Elshof - 1999 - Modern Schoolman 77 (1):79-94.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  42
    Aristotle's Classification of Forms of Government.W. L. Newman - 1892 - The Classical Review 6 (07):289-293.
  9.  38
    Aristotle's Classification of Forms of Government.H. Sidgwick - 1892 - The Classical Review 6 (04):141-144.
  10.  53
    Is Aristotle's Prime Mover a Pure Form?Sheilah O'Flynn Brennan - 1981 - Apeiron 15 (2):80 - 95.
  11. Aristotle’s Criticism of Non-Substance Forms and its Interpretation by the Neoplatonic Commentators.Pieter5 D'Hoine - 2011 - Phronesis 56 (3):262-307.
    Aristotle's criticism of Platonic Forms in the Metaphysics has been a major source for the understanding and developments of the theory of Forms in later Antiquity. One of the cases in point is Aristotle's argument, in Metaphysics I 9, 990b22-991a2, against Forms of non-substances. In this paper, I will first provide a careful analysis of this passage. Next, I will discuss how the argument has been interpreted - and refuted - by the fifth-century Neoplatonists Syrianus and Proclus. This (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12. Aristotle's theory of material substance: heat and pneuma, form and soul.Gad Freudenthal - 1995 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book offers an original new account of one of Aristotle's central doctrines. Freudenthal He recreates from Aristotle's writings a more complete theory of material substance which is able to explain the problematical areas of the way matter organizes itself and the persistence of matter, to show that the hitherto ignored concept of vital heat is as central in explaining material substance as soul or form.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  13.  38
    Aristotle's Theory of Material Substance: Heat and Pneuma, Form and Soul. Gad Freudenthal.David Furley - 1996 - Isis 87 (3):533-534.
  14.  54
    Aristotle's Theory of Substance : The Categories and Metaphysics Zeta: The Categories and Metaphysics Zeta.Michael V. Wedin - 2000 - Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Aristotle's views on the fundamental nature of reality are usually taken to be inconsistent. The two main sources for these views are the Categories and the central books of the Metaphysics, particularly book Zeta. In the early theory of the Categories the basic entities of the world are concrete objects such as Socrates: Aristotle calls them 'primary substances'. But the later theory awards this title to the forms of concrete objects. Michael Wedin proposes a compatibilist solution to this long-standing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  15. On Ideas: Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato’s Theory of Forms.Gail Fine - 1993 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The Peri ide^on is the only work in which Aristotle systematically sets out and criticizes arguments for the existence of Platonic forms. Gail Fine presents the first full-length treatment in English of this important but neglected work. She asks how, and how well, Aristotle understands Plato's theory of forms, and why and with what justification he favors an alternative metaphysical scheme. She examines the significance of the Peri ide^on for some central questions about Plato's theory of forms--whether, for example, there (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  16.  31
    Della Rocca’s Critique of Aristotle’s Form and Substance and the Arguments in Metaphysics vii 17.Christos Panayides - 2024 - Ancient Philosophy 44 (1):147-167.
    This paper examines Della Rocca’s critique of Aristotle’s conception of substance. The key point of the paper is that Aristotle’s homonymy principle and concept of enformed matter undermine Della Rocca’s claim that Aristotle is subject to a John Wayne moment. (To undergo a John Wayne moment is to propose an unilluminating or empty explanation, as in Wayne’s statement ‘A man’s gotta do what a man’s gotta do’.).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  49
    Aristotle’s Employment of Platonic Forms in Zeta 6.Gregg Ten Elshof - 1999 - Modern Schoolman 77 (1):79-94.
  18.  40
    Substantial Form in Aristotle's "Metaphysics" Z; II.Ellen Stone Haring - 1957 - Review of Metaphysics 10 (3):482 - 501.
    Aristotle's reasoning in Z, 10-11 has three stages. In the first, Aristotle proposes two different definitions for our consideration. The definitions contrast, at least superficially, for one appears to elucidate a whole by reference to its material parts, while the other does not appear to do so. Aristotle then in effect shows that the form of a whole can be taken in three somewhat different ways: We may be concerned with form by itself, or with the essential (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Aristotle’s Hylomorphism: The Causal-Explanatory Model.Michail Peramatzis - 2018 - Metaphysics 1 (1):12-32.
    There are several innocuous or trivial ways in which to explicate Aristotle’s hylomorphism. For example: objects are characterisable in terms of matter and form; or analysable into matter and form; or understood on the basis of matter and form. Serious problems arise when we seek to specify the sorts of relation holding among the different contributors to the hylomorphic picture. Here are some central general questions: a. What types of relation are most suitable for each n-tuple of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  20.  27
    Aristotle’s Syllogistic as a Form of Geometry.Vangelis Triantafyllou - 2023 - History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 27 (1):30-78.
    This article is primarily concerned with Aristotle’s theory of the syllogistic, and the investigation of the hypothesis that logical symbolism and methodology were in these early stages of a geometrical nature; with the gradual algebraization that occurred historically being one of the main reasons that some of the earlier passages on logic may often appear enigmatic. The article begins with a brief introduction that underlines the importance of geometric thought in ancient Greek science, and continues with a short exposition of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. On Ideas: Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's Theory of Forms.Gail Fine - 1994 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 99 (3):406-408.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  22. Aristotle’s argument from universal mathematics against the existence of platonic forms.Pieter Sjoerd Hasper - 2019 - Manuscrito 42 (4):544-581.
    In Metaphysics M.2, 1077a9-14, Aristotle appears to argue against the existence of Platonic Forms on the basis of there being certain universal mathematical proofs which are about things that are ‘beyond’ the ordinary objects of mathematics and that cannot be identified with any of these. It is a very effective argument against Platonism, because it provides a counter-example to the core Platonic idea that there are Forms in order to serve as the object of scientific knowledge: the universal of which (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23. Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's Form of the Good: Ethics Without Metaphysics?Gerasimos Santas - 1989 - Philosophical Papers 18 (2):137-160.
  24. On Ideas--Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's Theory of Forms.Jonathan Barnes - 1996 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2):489-491.
    In Chapter 9 of the first book of the Metaphysics Aristotle criticizes “those who posit the Ideas as causes”. His second group of criticisms urges that “the ways in which we try to prove that the forms exist” are unsatisfactory, and he enumerates five such ‘ways’. Alexander of Aphrodisias, in his commentary on the passage, offers to explain in more detail what the five ways were and why each is a cul-de-sac. Gail Fine’s On Ideas is a commentary on this (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25. Aristotle's universe: Its form and matter.Mohan Matthen & R. J. Hankinson - 1993 - Synthese 96 (3):417 - 435.
    It is argued that according to Aristotle the universe is a single substance with its own form and matter.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26. Aristotle's Definitions of Psuche.J. L. Ackrill - 1973 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 73:119 - 133.
    J. L. Ackrill; VIII*—Aristotle's Definitions of Psuche, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 73, Issue 1, 1 June 1973, Pages 119–134, https://doi.org.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  27. Aristotle's Metaphysics: Form, Matter and Identity.Laura M. Castelli - 2010 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 18 (5):941-943.
  28. 'Aristotle's Intermediates and Xenocrates' Mathematicals'.Phillip Sidney Horky - 2022 - Revue de Philosophie Ancienne 40 (1):79-112.
    This paper investigates the identity and function of τὰ μεταξύ in Aristotle and the Early Academy by focussing primarily on Aristotle’s criticisms of Xenocrates of Chalcedon, the third scholarch of Plato’s Academy and Aristotle’s direct competitor. It argues that a number of passages in Aristotle’s Metaphysics (at Β 2, Μ 1-2, and Κ 12) are chiefly directed at Xenocrates as a proponent of theories of mathematical intermediates, despite the fact that Aristotle does not mention Xenocrates there. Aristotle complains that the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29. Form and Inheritance in Aristotle's Embryology.Jessica Gelber - 2010 - In Brad Inwood (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Volume 39. Oxford University Press.
  30.  30
    Aristotle’s Criticism of the Platonic Forms as Causes in De Generatione et Corruptione II 9. A Reading Based on Philoponus’ Exegesis.Melina G. Mouzala - 2016 - Peitho 7 (1):123-148.
    In the De Generatione et Corruptione II 9, Aristotle aims to achieve the confirmation of his theory of the necessity of the efficient cause. In this chapter he sets out his criticism on the one hand of those who wrongly attributed the efficient cause to other kinds of causality and on the other, of those who ignored the efficient cause. More specifically Aristotle divides all preceding theories which attempted to explain generation and corruption into two groups: i) those which offered (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  45
    Aristotle’s Mark of Sentience.Alain Ducharme - 2014 - Apeiron 47 (3):293-309.
    I reconsider Aristotle’s account of perception by way of an ‘organic’ reading of the sensitive mean. I argue that the mean serves as a homeostatic mechanism that allows for the replication of forms in the organs in the process of perceptual alteration. The mean, as a product of properly constituted organs, is that by which Aristotle separates animals from plants.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32. Aristotle's on the Soul: A Critical Guide.Caleb M. Cohoe (ed.) - 2021 - New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
    Aristotle's On the Soul aims to uncover the principle of life, what Aristotle calls psuchē. For Aristotle, soul is the form which gives life to a body and causes all its living activities, from breathing to thinking. Aristotle develops a general account of all types of living through examining soul's causal powers. The thirteen new essays in this Critical Guide demonstrate the profound influence of Aristotle's inquiry on biology, psychology and philosophy of mind from antiquity to the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Aristotle’s Pluralistic Realism.Devin Henry - 2011 - The Monist 94 (2):197-220.
    In this paper I explore Aristotle’s views on natural kinds and the compatibility of pluralism and realism, a topic that has generated considerable interest among contemporary philosophers. I argue that, when it came to zoology, Aristotle denied that there is only one way of organizing the diversity of the living world into natural kinds that will yield a single, unified system of classification. Instead, living things can be grouped and regrouped into various cross-cutting kinds on the basis of objective similarities (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34.  79
    Aristotle’s Phenomenology of Form.Christopher P. Long - 2007 - Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 11 (2):435-448.
    Scholars often assume that Aristotle uses the terms morphē and eidos interchangeably. Translators of Aristotle's works rarely feel the need to carry the distinctionbetween these two Greek terms over into English. This article challenges the orthodox view that morphē and eidos are synonymous. Careful analysis of texts fromthe Categories, Physics, and Metaphysics in which these terms appear in close proximity reveals a fundamental tension of Aristotle's thinking concerning the being of natural beings. Morphē designates the form as (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  19
    On Ideas: Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's Theory of Forms.Theodore Scaltsas - 1994 - Philosophical Quarterly 44 (176):379-382.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36. Aristotle’s de Interpretatione: Contradiction and Dialectic.C. W. A. Whitaker - 1996 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press UK.
    Aristotle's treatise De Interpretatione is one of his central works; it continues to be the focus of much attention and debate. C. W. A. Whitaker presents the first systematic study of this work, and offers a radical new view of its aims, its structure, and its place in Aristotle's system, basing this view upon a detailed chapter-by-chapter analysis.By treating the work systematically, rather than concentrating on certain selected passages, Whitaker is able to show that, contrary to traditional opinion, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  37. Aristotle’s Theological System of Concepts Reconsidered.Es`haq Taheri Sarteshnizi - 2013 - پژوهشنامه فلسفه دین 11 (2):5-28.
    Aristotle’s theology is founded upon his physical studies. Aristotle, originally following the goal of pre-Socratic natural philosophers, has organized a set of philosophical concepts including ousia, matter, form, potentiality, actuality and entelechia to explain natural changes and motions. His way of study, therefore, is based on experience and observation. In this way, he has proved the existence of an unmoved mover and presented a concept of God. Yet, the failures and ambiguities of the concepts, their essential state of naturality (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  94
    Aristotle's political theory: an introduction for students of political theory.R. G. Mulgan - 1977 - New York: Clarendon Press.
    This book aims to provide an introduction to Aristotle's Politics, highlighting the major themes and arguments offered in the scholar's work. It begins with a discussion on what Aristotle perceives as human good, which he had described as the ethical purpose of political science, and how he views the political community, or the polis, as a community of persons formed with a view to some good purpose and a supreme entity in the sense that it is not just one (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  39.  49
    Aristotle’s Prototype Rule-Based Underlying Logic.John Corcoran - 2018 - Logica Universalis 12 (1-2):9-35.
    This expository paper on Aristotle’s prototype underlying logic is intended for a broad audience that includes non-specialists. It requires as background a discussion of Aristotle’s demonstrative logic. Demonstrative logic or apodictics is the study of demonstration as opposed to persuasion. It is the subject of Aristotle’s two-volume Analytics, as its first sentence says. Many of Aristotle’s examples are geometrical. A typical geometrical demonstration requires a theorem that is to be demonstrated, known premises from which the theorem is to be deduced, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40.  60
    Logical Extensions of Aristotle’s Square.Dominique Luzeaux, Jean Sallantin & Christopher Dartnell - 2008 - Logica Universalis 2 (1):167-187.
    . We start from the geometrical-logical extension of Aristotle’s square in [6,15] and [14], and study them from both syntactic and semantic points of view. Recall that Aristotle’s square under its modal form has the following four vertices: A is □α, E is , I is and O is , where α is a logical formula and □ is a modality which can be defined axiomatically within a particular logic known as S5 (classical or intuitionistic, depending on whether is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  41.  14
    Aristotle’s Notion of Deduction.Marta Vlasáková - 2023 - Disputatio 15 (68):90-114.
    Aristotle’s notion of deduction (syllogism) differs from the conception of logical consequence in classical logic in two essential features, which are required by Aristotle’s definition of syllogism and are incorporated into his formalisation of deduction: in addition to the standard necessary truth-preservation, Aristotle requires relevance of premises for the conclusion and non-repetition of premises in the conclusion. These requirements, together with Aristotle’s conception of simple propositions, lead to the result that valid deductive steps (syllogisms) must have very specific forms, namely (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  9
    Form and argument in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics: Some Observations.Dorothea Frede - 2013 - In Michael Erler & Jan Erik Heßler (eds.), Argument Und Literarische Form in Antiker Philosophie: Akten des 3. Kongresses der Gesellschaft Für Antike Philosophie 2010. De Gruyter. pp. 215-238.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  19
    Aristotle’s Philosophy of Histories.Andrew Hull - 2022 - Polis 39 (3):527-552.
    Aristotle is often considered to have a very pessimistic view about what histories can tell us, considering them too particular and lacking the generality required for scientific knowledge. Most importantly, they are considered to lack causal explanations. I argue against this view and instead that Aristotle considers histories to provide a highly practical level of knowledge. Histories can provide instances of both accidental and hypothetically necessary causation. I draw on the Athenian Constitution and the Constitution of the Spartans to show (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  57
    Aristotle's Theory of Material Substance: Heat and Pneuma, Form and Soul. [REVIEW]Charlotte Witt - 1997 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 35 (1):134-135.
  45.  37
    Aristotle's Metaphysics: Form, Matter and Identity.Jeremy Kirby - 2008 - Continuum.
    " "Jeremy Kirby addresses a difficulty in Aristotle's metaphysics, namely the possibility that two organisms of the same species might share the same matter.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  10
    Exploring Aristotle’s Modal Syllogism.Murat Keli̇kli̇ - 2023 - Beytulhikme An International Journal of Philosophy 13 (13:3):01-16.
    Aristotle’s viewpoints on modal propositions have been subjects of debate and exploration among scholars since his immediate successors. This study delves into how Aristotle defines assertoric and modal propositions and elucidates the correlations between these propositions and assertoric ones. Traditionally, commentators have interpreted propositions based on the premise that what belongs to the subject also belongs to the predicate. However, in this research, propositions are interpreted as ones in which what is predicated on the predicate will also be predicated on (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. Aristotle on Plato's Forms as Causes.Christopher Byrne - 2023 - In Mark J. Nyvlt (ed.), The Odyssey of Eidos: Reflections on Aristotle's Response to Plato. Eugene, Oregon: Wipf and Stock. pp. 19-39.
    Much of the debate about Aristotle’s criticisms of Plato has focused on the separability of the Forms. Here the dispute has to do with the ontological status of the Forms, in particular Plato’s claim for their ontological priority in relation to perceptible objects. Aristotle, however, also disputes the explanatory and causal roles that Plato claims for the Forms. This second criticism is independent of the first; even if the problem of the ontological status of the Forms were resolved to Aristotle’s (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. The relevance of Aristotle’s conception of eudaimonia for the psychological study of happiness.Alan S. Waterman - 1990 - Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 10 (1):39-44.
    According to the ethical system of eudaimonism, a philosophy that predates Aristotle, individuals have a responsibility to recognize and live in accordance with their daimon or "true self." The daimon refers to the potentialities of each person, the realization of which represents the greatest fulfillment in living of which each is capable. The daimon is an ideal in the sense of being an excellence, a perfection toward which one strives and, hence, it can give meaning and direction to one's life. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  49. Form and Inheritance in Aristotle's Embryology.Jessica Gelber - 2010 - In Brad Inwood (ed.), Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy Volume 39. Oxford University Press. pp. 183-212.
    This article argues for an interpretation of Aristotle’s biological account of familial resemblance that allows us to read Aristotle’s embryology as employing the same concept of “form” as he employs in his Metaphysics. The dominant view for the last several decades has been that in order to account for the phenomenon of inherited characteristics, Aristotle’s biology must appeal to a “sub-specific” form, one that includes all of the traits that parents pass on to their offspring. That view, however, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  50.  20
    Aristotle's Practical Epistemology.Dhananjay Jagannathan - 2024 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Aristotle's ethical writings are among the most influential in the history of Western thought. Key to these writings is the idea that some people better understand how they should act in order to lead successful lives as part of their communities. Their knowledge is called practical wisdom (phronēsis). Some of what Aristotle says suggests that this kind of knowledge is intuitive or unreflective, but at other times it seems abstruse and theoretical. -/- Aristotle's Practical Epistemology presents a novel (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 963