Results for 'Bounded‐variable infinitary logic'

969 found
Order:
  1.  21
    Logics with Zero‐One Laws that Are Not Fragments of Bounded‐Variable Infinitary Logic.Iain A. Stewart - 1997 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 43 (2):158-178.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  87
    Bounded variable logics: two, three, and more. [REVIEW]Martin Otto - 1999 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 38 (4-5):235-256.
    Consider the bounded variable logics $L^k_{\infty\omega}$ (with k variable symbols), and $C^k_{\infty\omega}$ (with k variables in the presence of counting quantifiers $\exists^{\geq m}$ ). These fragments of infinitary logic $L_{\infty\omega}$ are well known to provide an adequate logical framework for some important issues in finite model theory. This paper deals with a translation that associates equivalence of structures in the k-variable fragments with bisimulation equivalence between derived structures. Apart from a uniform and intuitively appealing treatment of these equivalences, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Completeness of Infinitary Heterogeneous Logic.Christian Espíndola - 2025 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic -1:1-17.
    Given a regular cardinal κ such that κ<κ=κ (e.g., if the generalized continuum hypothesis holds), we develop a proof system for classical infinitary logic that includes heterogeneous quantification (i.e., infinite alternating sequences of quantifiers) within the language Lκ+,κ, where there are conjunctions and disjunctions of at most κ many formulas and quantification (including the heterogeneous one) is applied to less than κ many variables. This type of quantification is interpreted in Set using the usual second-order formulation in terms (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  31
    Elimination of bound variables in logic with an arbitrary quantifier.Roman Doraczyński - 1973 - Studia Logica 32 (1):117 - 129.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5. Bounded Variable Logics and Counting. A Study in Finite Model Theory.M. Otto - 2000 - Studia Logica 65 (2):288-290.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Binding bound variables in epistemic contexts.Brian Rabern - 2021 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 64 (5-6):533-563.
    ABSTRACT Quine insisted that the satisfaction of an open modalised formula by an object depends on how that object is described. Kripke's ‘objectual’ interpretation of quantified modal logic, whereby variables are rigid, is commonly thought to avoid these Quinean worries. Yet there remain residual Quinean worries for epistemic modality. Theorists have recently been toying with assignment-shifting treatments of epistemic contexts. On such views an epistemic operator ends up binding all the variables in its scope. One might worry that this (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  7. Infinitary logics and very sparse random graphs.James Lynch - 1997 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (2):609-623.
    Let L ω ∞ω be the infinitary language obtained from the first-order language of graphs by closure under conjunctions and disjunctions of arbitrary sets of formulas, provided only finitely many distinct variables occur among the formulas. Let p(n) be the edge probability of the random graph on n vertices. It is shown that if p(n) ≪ n -1 satisfies certain simple conditions on its growth rate, then for every σ∈ L ω ∞ω , the probability that σ holds for (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  33
    How to define a linear order on finite models.Lauri Hella, Phokion G. Kolaitis & Kerkko Luosto - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 87 (3):241-267.
    We carry out a systematic investigation of the definability of linear order on classes of finite rigid structures. We obtain upper and lower bounds for the expressibility of linear order in various logics that have been studied extensively in finite model theory, such as least fixpoint logic LFP, partial fixpoint logic PFP, infinitary logic Lω∞ω with a finite number of variables, as well as the closures of these logics under implicit definitions. Moreover, we show that the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  9.  46
    Generalized quantifiers and pebble games on finite structures.Phokion G. Kolaitis & Jouko A. Väänänen - 1995 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 74 (1):23-75.
    First-order logic is known to have a severely limited expressive power on finite structures. As a result, several different extensions have been investigated, including fragments of second-order logic, fixpoint logic, and the infinitary logic L∞ωω in which every formula has only a finite number of variables. In this paper, we study generalized quantifiers in the realm of finite structures and combine them with the infinitary logic L∞ωω to obtain the logics L∞ωω, where Q (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  10.  46
    Martin Otto. The expressive power of fixed-point logic with counting. The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 61 , pp. 147–176. - Martin Otto. Bounded variable logics and counting. A study infinite models. Lecture notes in logic, no. 9. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg, New York, etc., 1997, ix + 183 pp. [REVIEW]Anuj Dawar - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (1):329-331.
  11.  32
    Hierarchies in transitive closure logic, stratified Datalog and infinitary logic.Erich Grädel & Gregory L. McColm - 1996 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 77 (2):169-199.
    We establish a general hierarchy theorem for quantifier classes in the infinitary logic L∞ωωon finite structures. In particular, it is shown that no infinitary formula with bounded number of universal quantifiers can express the negation of a transitive closure.This implies the solution of several open problems in finite model theory: On finite structures, positive transitive closure logic is not closed under negation. More generally the hierarchy defined by interleaving negation and transitive closure operators is strict. This (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12.  33
    Hybrid logics with infinitary proof systems.Rineke Verbrugge, Gerard Renardel de Lavalette & Barteld Kooi - unknown
    We provide a strongly complete infinitary proof system for hybrid logic. This proof system can be extended with countably many sequents. Thus, although these logics may be non-compact, strong completeness proofs are provided for infinitary hybrid versions of non-compact logics like ancestral logic and Segerberg’s modal logic with the bounded chain condition. This extends the completeness result for hybrid logics by Gargov, Passy, and Tinchev.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13.  7
    A Logic Programming Language with Lambda-abstraction, Function Variables, and Simple Unification.Dale Miller - 1991 - LFCS, Department of Computer Science, University of Edinburgh.
    As a result of these restrictions, an implementation of L [subscript lambda] does not need to implement full higher-order unification. Instead, an extension to first-order unification that respects bound variable names and scopes is all that is required. Such unification problems are shown to be decidable and to possess most general unifiers when unifiers exist. A unification algorithm and logic programming interpreter are described and proved correct. Several examples of using L[subscript lambda] as a meta-programming language are presented.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  14. Bound Anaphora and Type Logical Grammar.David Dowty - unknown
    (Though it is now known that many pronouns once lumped under ”bound variables” are in fact referential indefinites or other phenomena better accounted for in a DRT-like view of referents, there remain many true instances of sentenceinternally bound anaphora: this talk concerns only the latter.) Almost all versions of categorial grammar (CG) are differentiated from other syntactic theories in treating a multi-argument verb as an Ò-place predicate phrase (PrdP) that combines with a NP or other argument to yield a (Ò-1)-place (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  26
    Infinitary Action Logic with Multiplexing.Stepan L. Kuznetsov & Stanislav O. Speranski - 2023 - Studia Logica 111 (2):251-280.
    Infinitary action logic can be naturally expanded by adding exponential and subexponential modalities from linear logic. In this article we shall develop infinitary action logic with a subexponential that allows multiplexing (instead of contraction). Both non-commutative and commutative versions of this logic will be considered, presented as infinitary sequent calculi. We shall prove cut admissibility for these calculi, and estimate the complexity of the corresponding derivability problems: in both cases it will turn out (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  67
    Finite variable logics in descriptive complexity theory.Martin Grohe - 1998 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 4 (4):345-398.
    Throughout the development of finite model theory, the fragments of first-order logic with only finitely many variables have played a central role. This survey gives an introduction to the theory of finite variable logics and reports on recent progress in the area.For each k ≥ 1 we let Lk be the fragment of first-order logic consisting of all formulas with at most k variables. The logics Lk are the simplest finite-variable logics. Later, we are going to consider (...) variants and extensions by so-called counting quantifiers.Finite variable logics have mostly been studied on finite structures. Like the whole area of finite model theory, they have interesting model theoretic, complexity theoretic, and combinatorial aspects. For finite structures, first-order logic is often too expressive, since each finite structure can be characterized up to isomorphism by a single first-order sentence, and each class of finite structures that is closed under isomorphism can be characterized by a first-order theory. The finite variable fragments seem to be promising candidates with the right balance between expressive power and weakness for a model theory of finite structures. This may have motivated Poizat [67] to collect some basic model theoretic properties of the Lk. Around the same time Immerman [45] showed that important complexity classes such as polynomial time or polynomial space can be characterized as collections of all classes of finite structures definable by uniform sequences of first-order formulas with a fixed number of variables and varying quantifier-depth. (shrink)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. The addition of bounded quantification and partial functions to a computational logic and its theorem prover.Robert Boyer - manuscript
    We describe an extension to our quantifier-free computational logic to provide the expressive power and convenience of bounded quantifiers and partial functions. By quantifier we mean a formal construct which introduces a bound or indicial variable whose scope is some subexpression of the quantifier expression. A familiar quantifier is the Σ operator which sums the values of an expression over some range of values on the bound variable. Our method is to represent expressions of the logic as objects (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  24
    From finitary to infinitary second‐order logic.George Weaver & Irena Penev - 2005 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 51 (5):499-506.
    A back and forth condition on interpretations for those second-order languages without functional variables whose non-logical vocabulary is finite and excludes functional constants is presented. It is shown that this condition is necessary and sufficient for the interpretations to be equivalent in the language. When applied to second-order languages with an infinite non-logical vocabulary, excluding functional constants, the back and forth condition is sufficient but not necessary. It is shown that there is a class of infinitary second-order languages whose (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  19. (1 other version)Truth, Partial Logic and Infinitary Proof Systems.Martin Fischer & Norbert Gratzl - 2017 - Studia Logica 106 (3):1-26.
    In this paper we apply proof theoretic methods used for classical systems in order to obtain upper bounds for systems in partial logic. We focus on a truth predicate interpreted in a Kripke style way via strong Kleene; whereas the aim is to connect harmoniously the partial version of Kripke–Feferman with its intended semantics. The method we apply is based on infinitary proof systems containing an ω-rule.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20.  64
    Foundations of nominal techniques: logic and semantics of variables in abstract syntax.Murdoch J. Gabbay - 2011 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 17 (2):161-229.
    We are used to the idea that computers operate on numbers, yet another kind of data is equally important: the syntax of formal languages, with variables, binding, and alpha-equivalence. The original application of nominal techniques, and the one with greatest prominence in this paper, is to reasoning on formal syntax with variables and binding. Variables can be modelled in many ways: for instance as numbers (since we usually take countably many of them); as links (since they may `point' to a (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21.  24
    Complexity of the Infinitary Lambek Calculus with Kleene Star.Stepan Kuznetsov - 2021 - Review of Symbolic Logic 14 (4):946-972.
    We consider the Lambek calculus, or noncommutative multiplicative intuitionistic linear logic, extended with iteration, or Kleene star, axiomatised by means of an$\omega $-rule, and prove that the derivability problem in this calculus is$\Pi _1^0$-hard. This solves a problem left open by Buszkowski (2007), who obtained the same complexity bound for infinitary action logic, which additionally includes additive conjunction and disjunction. As a by-product, we prove that any context-free language without the empty word can be generated by a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  50
    On Conservative Extensions in Logics with Infinitary Predicates.Miklós Ferenczi - 2009 - Studia Logica 92 (1):121-135.
    If the language is extended by new individual variables, in classical first order logic, then the deduction system obtained is a conservative extension of the original one. This fails to be true for the logics with infinitary predicates. But it is shown that restricting the commutativity of quantifiers and the equality axioms in the extended system and supposing the merry-go-round property in the original system, the foregoing extension is already conservative. It is shown that these restrictions are crucial (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  24
    Infinitary generalizations of deligne’s completeness theorem.Christian Espíndola - 2020 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 85 (3):1147-1162.
    Given a regular cardinal $\kappa $ such that $\kappa ^{<\kappa }=\kappa $, we study a class of toposes with enough points, the $\kappa $ -separable toposes. These are equivalent to sheaf toposes over a site with $\kappa $ -small limits that has at most $\kappa $ many objects and morphisms, the topology being generated by at most $\kappa $ many covering families, and that satisfy a further exactness property T. We prove that these toposes have enough $\kappa $ -points, that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  24. Modal Languages and Bounded Fragments of Predicate Logic.Hajnal Andréka, István Németi & Johan van Benthem - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (3):217 - 274.
    What precisely are fragments of classical first-order logic showing “modal” behaviour? Perhaps the most influential answer is that of Gabbay 1981, which identifies them with so-called “finite-variable fragments”, using only some fixed finite number of variables (free or bound). This view-point has been endorsed by many authors (cf. van Benthem 1991). We will investigate these fragments, and find that, illuminating and interesting though they are, they lack the required nice behaviour in our sense. (Several new negative results support this (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  25.  41
    Computing with cylindric modal logics and arrow logics, lower Bounds.Maarten Marx - 2002 - Studia Logica 72 (2):233-252.
    The complexity of the satisfiability problems of various arrow logics and cylindric modal logics is determined. As is well known, relativising these logics makes them decidable. There are several parameters that can be set in such a relativisation. We focus on the following three: the number of variables involved, the similarity type and the kind of relativised models considered. The complexity analysis shows the importance and relevance of these parameters.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  37
    Syntactically free, semantically bound. A note on variables.Hugues Leblanc - 1968 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 9 (2):167-170.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  22
    Canonization for two variables and puzzles on the square.Martin Otto - 1997 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 85 (3):243-282.
    We consider infinitary logic with only two variable symbols, both with and without counting quantifiers, i.e. L2 L∞ω2 and C2 L∞ω2mεω. The main result is that finite relational structures admit canonization with respect to L2 and C2: there are polynomial time com putable functors mapping finite relational structures to unique representatives of their equivalence class with respect to indistinguishability in either of these logics. In fact we exhibit in verses to the natural invariants that characterize structures up to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28. On the decision problem for two-variable first-order logic.Erich Grädel, Phokion G. Kolaitis & Moshe Y. Vardi - 1997 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 3 (1):53-69.
    We identify the computational complexity of the satisfiability problem for FO 2 , the fragment of first-order logic consisting of all relational first-order sentences with at most two distinct variables. Although this fragment was shown to be decidable a long time ago, the computational complexity of its decision problem has not been pinpointed so far. In 1975 Mortimer proved that FO 2 has the finite-model property, which means that if an FO 2 -sentence is satisfiable, then it has a (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  29.  26
    An Event-Based Fragment of First-Order Logic over Intervals.Savas Konur - 2011 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 20 (1):49-68.
    We consider a new fragment of first-order logic with two variables. This logic is defined over interval structures. It constitutes unary predicates, a binary predicate and a function symbol. Considering such a fragment of first-order logic is motivated by defining a general framework for event-based interval temporal logics. In this paper, we present a sound, complete and terminating decision procedure for this logic. We show that the logic is decidable, and provide a NEXPTIME complexity bound (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  53
    Small substructures and decidability issues for first-order logic with two variables.Emanuel Kieroński & Martin Otto - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (3):729-765.
    We study first-order logic with two variables FO² and establish a small substructure property. Similar to the small model property for FO² we obtain an exponential size bound on embedded substructures, relative to a fixed surrounding structure that may be infinite. We apply this technique to analyse the satisfiability problem for FO² under constraints that require several binary relations to be interpreted as equivalence relations. With a single equivalence relation, FO² has the finite model property and is complete for (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  31.  52
    Independent choices and the interpretation of IF logic.Theo M. V. Janssen - 2002 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 11 (3):367-387.
    In this paper it is argued that Hintikka's game theoreticalsemantics for Independence Friendly logic does not formalize theintuitions about independent choices; it rather is aformalization of imperfect information. Furthermore it is shownthat the logic has several remarkable properties (e.g.,renaming of bound variables is not allowed). An alternativesemantics is proposed which formalizes intuitions aboutindependence.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  32. On the number of different variables required to define the n-density or the bounded n-width of Kripke frames with some consequences for Sahlqvist formulae.Petar Iliev - 2025 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 33 (1):95-124.
    We show that both the $n$-density and the bounded $n$-width of Kripke frames can be modally defined not only with natural and well-known Sahlqvist formulae containing a linear number of different propositional variables but also with formulae of polynomial length with a logarithmic number of different propositional variables and then we prove that this exponential decrease in the number of variables leads us outside the class of Sahlqvist formulae.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  49
    Complexity Results for Modal Dependence Logic.Peter Lohmann & Heribert Vollmer - 2013 - Studia Logica 101 (2):343-366.
    Modal dependence logic was introduced recently by Väänänen. It enhances the basic modal language by an operator = (). For propositional variables p 1, . . . , p n , = (p 1, . . . , p n-1, p n ) intuitively states that the value of p n is determined by those of p 1, . . . , p n-1. Sevenster (J. Logic and Computation, 2009) showed that satisfiability for modal dependence logic is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  34. (1 other version)How is it that infinitary methods can be applied to finitary mathematics? Gödel's T: a case study.Andreas Weiermann - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (4):1348-1370.
    Inspired by Pohlers' local predicativity approach to Pure Proof Theory and Howard's ordinal analysis of bar recursion of type zero we present a short, technically smooth and constructive strong normalization proof for Gödel's system T of primitive recursive functionals of finite types by constructing an ε 0 -recursive function [] 0 : T → ω so that a reduces to b implies [a] $_0 > [b]_0$ . The construction of [] 0 is based on a careful analysis of the Howard-Schütte (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  35. Monsters in Kaplan’s logic of demonstratives.Brian Rabern - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 164 (2):393-404.
    Kaplan (1989a) insists that natural languages do not contain displacing devices that operate on character—such displacing devices are called monsters. This thesis has recently faced various empirical challenges (e.g., Schlenker 2003; Anand and Nevins 2004). In this note, the thesis is challenged on grounds of a more theoretical nature. It is argued that the standard compositional semantics of variable binding employs monstrous operations. As a dramatic first example, Kaplan’s formal language, the Logic of Demonstratives, is shown to contain monsters. (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  36.  18
    Parametrization over inductive relations of a bounded number of variables.Gregory L. McColm - 1990 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 48 (2):103-134.
  37. Notes on a semantic analysis of variable binding term operators.J. Corcoran & John Herring - 1971 - Logique Et Analyse 55:644-657.
    -/- A variable binding term operator (vbto) is a non-logical constant, say v, which combines with a variable y and a formula F containing y free to form a term (vy:F) whose free variables are exact ly those of F, excluding y. -/- Kalish-Montague proposed using vbtos to formalize definite descriptions, set abstracts {x: F}, minimalization in recursive function theory, etc. However, they gave no sematics for vbtos. Hatcher gave a semantics but one that has flaws. We give a correct (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  38.  38
    More free logic.Scott Lehmann - 2002 - In D. M. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (eds.), Handbook of Philosophical Logic Vol. 5. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 197-259.
    By a free logic is generally meant a variant of classical first-order logic in which constant terms may, under interpretation, fail to refer to individuals in the domain D over which the bound variables range, either because they do not refer at all or because they refer to individuals outside D. If D is identified with what is assumed by the given interpretation to exist, in accord with Quine’s dictum that “to be is to be the value of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  39.  91
    Omitting types for finite variable fragments and complete representations of algebras.Hajnal Andréka, István Németi & Tarek Sayed Ahmed - 2008 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 73 (1):65-89.
    We give a novel application of algebraic logic to first order logic. A new, flexible construction is presented for representable but not completely representable atomic relation and cylindric algebras of dimension n (for finite n > 2) with the additional property that they are one-generated and the set of all n by n atomic matrices forms a cylindric basis. We use this construction to show that the classical Henkin-Orey omitting types theorem fails for the finite variable fragments of (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  40.  30
    Equivalence and quantifier rules for logic with imperfect information.Xavier Caicedo, Francien Dechesne & Theo Janssen - 2008 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 17 (1):91-129.
    In this paper, we present a prenex form theorem for a version of Independence Friendly logic, a logic with imperfect information. Lifting classical results to such logics turns out not to be straightforward, because independence conditions make the formulas sensitive to signalling phenomena. In particular, nested quantification over the same variable is shown to cause problems. For instance, renaming of bound variables may change the interpretations of a formula, there are only restricted quantifier extraction theorems, and slashed connectives (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  41.  41
    Λ-normal forms in an intensional logic for English.J. Friedman - 1980 - Studia Logica 39:311.
    Montague [7] translates English into a tensed intensional logic, an extension of the typed -calculus. We prove that each translation reduces to a formula without -applications, unique to within change of bound variable. The proof has two main steps. We first prove that translations of English phrases have the special property that arguments to functions are modally closed. We then show that formulas in which arguments are modally closed have a unique fully reduced -normal form. As a corollary, translations (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  42. How set theory impinges on logic.Jesus Mosterin - unknown
    Standard (classical) logic is not independent of set theory. Which formulas are valid in logic depends on which sets we assume to exist in our set-theoretical universe. Second-order logic is just set theory in disguise. The typically logical notions of validity and consequence are not well defined in second-order logic, at least as long as there are open issues in set theory. Such contentious issues in set theory as the axiom of choice, the continuum hypothesis or (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  8
    Fragments of first-order logic.Ian Pratt-Hartmann - 2023 - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    A sentence of first-order logic is satisfiable if it is true in some structure, and finitely satisfiable if it is true in some finite structure. The question arises as to whether there exists an algorithm for determining whether a given formula of first-order logic is satisfiable, or indeed finitely satisfiable. This question was answered negatively in 1936 by Church and Turing (for satisfiability) and in 1950 by Trakhtenbrot (for finite satisfiability).In contrast, the satisfiability and finite satisfiability problems are (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Binding On the Fly: Cross-Sentential Anaphora in Variable— Free Semantics.Anna Szabolcsi - 2003 - In R. Oehrle & J. Kruijff (eds.), resource sensitivity, binding, and anaphora. kluwer. pp. 215--227.
    Combinatory logic (Curry and Feys 1958) is a “variable-free” alternative to the lambda calculus. The two have the same expressive power but build their expressions differently. “Variable-free” semantics is, more precisely, “free of variable binding”: it has no operation like abstraction that turns a free variable into a bound one; it uses combinators—operations on functions—instead. For the general linguistic motivation of this approach, see the works of Steedman, Szabolcsi, and Jacobson, among others. The standard view in linguistics is that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45. Logic and AI in China: An Introduction.Fenrong Liu & Kaile Su - 2013 - Minds and Machines 23 (1):1-4.
    The year 2012 has witnessed worldwide celebrations of Alan Turing’s 100th birthday. A great number of conferences and workshops were organized by logicians, computer scientists and researchers in AI, showing the continued flourishing of computer science, and the fruitful interfaces between logic and computer science. Logic is no longer just the concept that Frege had about one hundred years ago, let alone that of Aristotle twenty centuries before. One of the prominent features of contemporary logic is its (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  40
    A nonasymptotic lower time bound for a strictly bounded second-order arithmetic.Anatoly P. Beltiukov - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 141 (3):320-324.
    We obtain a nonasymptotic lower time bound for deciding sentences of bounded second-order arithmetic with respect to a form of the random access machine with stored programs. More precisely, let P be an arbitrary program for the model under consideration which recognized true formulas with a given range of parameters. Let p be the length of P and let N be an arbitrary natural number. We show how to construct a formula G with one free variable with length not more (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. An infinitely descending chain of ground without a lower bound.Jon Erling Litland - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (5):1361-1369.
    Using only uncontentious principles from the logic of ground I construct an infinitely descending chain of ground without a lower bound. I then compare the construction to the constructions due to Dixon and Rabin and Rabern.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  48. Discourse and logical form: pronouns, attention and coherence.Una Stojnić, Matthew Stone & Ernie Lepore - 2017 - Linguistics and Philosophy 40 (5):519-547.
    Traditionally, pronouns are treated as ambiguous between bound and demonstrative uses. Bound uses are non-referential and function as bound variables, and demonstrative uses are referential and take as a semantic value their referent, an object picked out jointly by linguistic meaning and a further cue—an accompanying demonstration, an appropriate and adequately transparent speaker’s intention, or both. In this paper, we challenge tradition and argue that both demonstrative and bound pronouns are dependent on, and co-vary with, antecedent expressions. Moreover, the semantic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  49.  28
    Imitating Quantum Probabilities: Beyond Bell’s Theorem and Tsirelson Bounds.Marek Czachor & Kamil Nalikowski - 2024 - Foundations of Science 29 (2):281-305.
    Local hidden-variable model of singlet-state correlations discussed in Czachor (Acta Phys Polon A 139:70, 2021a) is shown to be a particular case of an infinite hierarchy of local hidden-variable models based on an infinite hierarchy of calculi. Violation of Bell-type inequalities can be interpreted as a ‘confusion of languages’ problem, a result of mixing different but neighboring levels of the hierarchy. Mixing of non-neighboring levels results in violations beyond the Tsirelson bounds.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  52
    Hi-individuals and Where to Find Them—Towards a Hi-world Semantics for Quantified Modal Logic.Cheng-Chih Tsai - 2020 - Acta Analytica 35 (2):165-179.
    If to be is to be the value of a bound variable, then the acknowledgment and denial of the existence of chairs amounts to a serious disagreement about the range of a quantifier. However, by resorting to the intrinsic hierarchical structure of hi-world semantics, we find that the varying of domains from worlds to worlds can actually be accommodated within a unified framework. With the introduction of a universal domain D of hi-individuals and an existence predicate E that serves as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 969