Results for 'Christopher Law'

942 found
Order:
  1.  15
    Law Week Dinner.Law Council C. E. O. Peter Webb, Justice Mary Finn, Amy Burr, Warwick Burr, Christopher Ryan, Councillor Linda Crebbin & Michael Flynn - forthcoming - Ethos: Journal of the Society for Psychological Anthropology.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Complicity: Ethics and Law for a Collective Age.Christopher Kutz - 2000 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    We live in a morally flawed world. Our lives are complicated by what other people do, and by the harms that flow from our social, economic and political institutions. Our relations as individuals to these collective harms constitute the domain of complicity. This book examines the relationship between collective responsibility and individual guilt. It presents a rigorous philosophical account of the nature of our relations to the social groups in which we participate, and uses that account in a discussion of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   157 citations  
  3. The belief-desire law.Christopher Gauker - 2005 - Facta Philosophica 7 (2):121-144.
    Many philosophers hold that for various reasons there must be psychological laws governing beliefs and desires. One of the few serious examples that they offer is the _belief-desire law_, which states, roughly, that _ceteris paribus_ people do what they believe will satisfy their desires. This paper argues that, in fact, there is no such law. In particular, decision theory does not support the contention that there is such a law.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  4.  11
    Natural Law Today: The Present State of the Perennial Philosophy.Christopher Wolfe & Steven Brust (eds.) - 2018 - Lanham, Maryland: Lexington Books.
    Natural Law Today gives a strong voice to classical natural law theory as the best answers to the fundamental questions of ethics and as the best framework for political and social life. It explains various aspects of that theory and defends it against common misperceptions and criticisms.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  77
    Law and Violence: Chirstoph Menke in dialogue.Christoph Menke - 2018 - Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press.
    A interlocution containing a stimulating lead essay on the relationship between law and violence by one of the key third-generation Frankfurt School philosophers, Christoph Menke, and engaged responses by a variety of influential critics.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  6. Is There a Duty to Obey the Law?Christopher Wellman & John Simmons - 2005 - New York: Cambridge University Press. Edited by A. John Simmons.
    The central question in political philosophy is whether political states have the right to coerce their constituents and whether citizens have a moral duty to obey the commands of their state. In this 2005 book, Christopher Heath Wellman and A. John Simmons defend opposing answers to this question. Wellman bases his argument on samaritan obligations to perform easy rescues, arguing that each of us has a moral duty to obey the law as his or her fair share of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  7.  18
    Kant and the Divine: From Contemplation to the Moral Law.Christopher J. Insole - 2020 - Oxford University Press.
    The philosopher Kant is a key thinker in shaping our contemporary concept of morality, freedom, and happiness. This book argues that Kant believes in God, but that he is not a Christian, and that this opens up an important and neglected dimension of Western Philosophy.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  7
    The idea of a pure theory of law.Christoph Kletzer - 2018 - Portland, Oregon: Hart Publishing.
    Most contemporary legal philosophers tend to take force to be an accessory to the law. According to this prevalent view the law primarily consists of a series of demands made on us; force, conversely, comes into play only when these demands fail to be satisfied. This book claims that this model should be jettisoned in favour of a radically different one: according to the proposed view, force is not an accessory to the law but rather its attribute. The law is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  24
    Legal Powers in Private Law.Christopher Essert - 2015 - Legal Theory 21 (3-4):136-155.
    This article explores the nature and role of legal powers in private law. I show how powers are special in that they allow agents to change their (and others’) legal circumstances merely by communicating an intention to do so, without having also to change the nonnormative facts of the world. This feature of powers is, I argue, particularly salient in private law, with its correlative or bipolar normative structure; understanding powers and their role in private law thus requires careful attention (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10. The Difference Uniforms Make: Collective Violence in Criminal Law and War.Christopher Kutz - 2005 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 33 (2):148-180.
  11.  44
    Criminal Law Exceptionalism as an Affirmative Ideology, and its Expansionist Discontents.Christoph Burchard - 2023 - Criminal Law and Philosophy 17 (1):17-27.
    Criminal law exceptionalism, or so I suggest, has turned into an ideology in German and Continental criminal law theory. It rests on interrelated claims about the (ideal or real) extraordinary qualities and properties of the criminal law and has led to exceptional doctrines in constitutional criminal law and criminal law theory. It prima facie paradoxically perpetuates and conserves the criminal law, and all too often leads to ideological thoughtlessness, which may blind us to the dark sides of criminal laws in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  5
    Natural Law and Scapegoating.Christopher S. Morrissey - 2014 - Philosophy, Culture, and Traditions 10:185-201.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Reading the Laws.Christopher Bobonich - 1996 - In Christopher Gill & Mary Margaret McCabe (eds.), Form and Argument in Late Plato. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 249--82.
  14. Should Trees Have Standing?: Law, Morality, and the Environment.Christopher D. Stone - 2010 - Oup Usa.
    Originally published in 1972, Should Trees Have Standing? was a rallying point for the then burgeoning environmental movement, launching a worldwide debate on the basic nature of legal rights that reached the U.S. Supreme Court. Now, in the 35th anniversary edition of this remarkably influential book, Christopher D. Stone updates his original thesis and explores the impact his ideas have had on the courts, the academy, and society as a whole. At the heart of the book is an eminently (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  15. Diogenes the Cynic on Law and World Citizenship.Christopher Paone - 2018 - Polis 35 (2):478–498.
    Against the traditional reading of Cynic cosmopolitanism, this essay advances the thesis that Diogenes’ world citizenship is a positive claim supported by philosophical argument and philosophical example. Evidence in favor of this thesis is a new interpretation of Diogenes’ syllogistic argument concerning law (nomos) (D.L. 6.72). Important to the argument are an understanding of Diogenes’ philanthropic character and his moral imperative to ‘re-stamp the currency’. Whereas Socrates understands his care as attached specially to Athens, Diogenes’ philosophical mission and form of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  20
    Law, morality and religion in a secular society.Christopher Cherry - 1968 - Philosophical Books 9 (2):15-17.
  17.  89
    Plato's 'Laws': A Critical Guide.Christopher Bobonich (ed.) - 2010 - New York: Cambridge University Press.
    Long understudied, Plato's Laws has been the object of renewed attention in the past decade and is now considered to be his major work of political philosophy besides the Republic. In his last dialogue, Plato returns to the project of describing the foundation of a just city and sketches in considerable detail its constitution, laws and other social institutions. Written by leading Platonists, the essays in this volume cover a wide range of topics central for understanding the Laws, such as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  18. The Nomic Likelihood Account of Laws.Christopher J. G. Meacham - 2023 - Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 9 (9):230-284.
    An adequate account of laws should satisfy at least five desiderata: it should provide a unified account of laws and chances, it should yield plausible relations between laws and chances, it should vindicate numerical chance assignments, it should accommodate dynamical and non-dynamical chances, and it should accommodate a plausible range of nomic possibilities. No extant account of laws satisfies these desiderata. This paper presents a non-Humean account of laws, the Nomic Likelihood Account, that does.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  19.  48
    Moral Consensus and Law.Christopher F. Mooney - 1976 - Thought: Fordham University Quarterly 51 (3):231-254.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  62
    Explaining the gambler's fallacy: Testing a gestalt explanation versus the “law of small numbers”.Christopher J. R. Roney & Natalie Sansone - 2015 - Thinking and Reasoning 21 (2):193-205.
    The present study tests a gestalt explanation for the gambler's fallacy which posits that runs in random events will be expected to reverse only when the run is open or ongoing. This is contrasted with the law of small numbers explanation suggesting that people expect random outcomes to balance out generally. Sixty-one university students placed hypothetical guesses and bets on a series of coin tosses. Either heads or tails were dominant . In a closed run condition the run ended prior (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  24
    Rule of Law, Misrule of Men.Christopher Irwin - 2013 - The European Legacy 18 (2):235-237.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  9
    Hobbes, Bentham et la Common Law.Christophe Béal - 2021 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 146 (3):311-325.
    La doctrine classique de la Common Law est la cible de nombreuses critiques de la part de Hobbes et de Bentham. Tous deux remettent en cause les principes qui fondent et justifient cette composante fondamentale du droit anglais. Sont notamment visés le caractère coutumier qui lui est attribué, sa prétendue rationalité ainsi que l’interprétation qu’en font les juges. Moment décisif dans l’histoire des théories du droit, cette controverse tend à faire prévaloir l’idée d’un droit créé par un acte de volonté (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  9
    The Critique of Law and the Law of Critique.Christoph Menke - 2020 - In María Del Del Rosario Acosta López & Colin McQuillan (eds.), Critique in German Philosophy: From Kant to Critical Theory. Albany: SUNY Press. pp. 377-394.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  35
    Natural law and modern meta-ethics.Christopher Tollefsen - 2004 - In Mark J. Cherry (ed.), Natural Law and the Possibility of a Global Ethics. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 39--56.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  28
    Teaching Medical Ethics through Medical Law in advance.Christopher Cowley - forthcoming - Teaching Philosophy.
    Medical ethics is normally taught in a combination of three ways: through discussions of normative theories and principles; through for-and-against debating of topics; or through case studies. I want to argue that a fourth approach might be better, and should be used more: teaching medical ethics through medical law. Medical law is already deeply imbued with ethical concepts, principles and reasons, and allows the discussion of ethics through the “back door,” as it were. The two greatest advantages of the law (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  63
    Psychological research on heuristics meets the law.Christoph Engel - 2000 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 23 (5):747-747.
    Heuristics make decisions not only fast and frugally, but often nearly as well as “full” rationality or even better. Using such heuristics should therefore meet health care standards under liability law. But an independent court often has little chance to verify the necessary information. And judgments based on heuristics might appear to have little legitimacy, given the widespread belief in formal rationality.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  34
    Common law of human rights?: Transnational judicial conversations on constitutional rights.Mccrudden Christopher - 2000 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 20 (4):499-532.
    It is now commonplace in many jurisdictions for judges to refer to the decisions of the courts of foreign jurisdictions when interpreting domestic human rights guarantees. But there has also been a persistent undercurrent of scepticism about this trend, and the emergence of a growing debate about its appropriateness. This issue is of particular relevance in jurisdictions that have relatively recently incorporated human rights provisions that are significantly judicially enforced. In the UK, a reconsideration of the use of comparative judicial (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  28.  38
    Rights Forfeiture and Punishment.Christopher Heath Wellman - 2016 - Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
    In Rights Forfeiture and Punishment, Christopher Heath Wellman argues that those who seek to defend the moral permissibility of punishment should shift their focus from general justifying aims to moral side constraints. On Wellman's view, punishment is permissible just in case the wrongdoer has forfeited her right against punishment.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  29.  9
    Why the law matters to you: citizenship, agency, and public identity.Christoph Hanisch - 2013 - Berlin: De Gruyter.
    This book presents an answer to the question of why modern legal institutions and the idea of citizenship are important for leading a free life. The majority of views in political and legal philosophy regard the law merely as a useful instrument, employed to render our lives more secure and to enable us to engage in cooperate activities more efficiently. The view developed here defends a non-instrumentalist alternative of why the law matters. It identifies the law as a constitutive feature (...)
  30. New natural law foundations of human rights.Christopher Tollefsen - 2022 - In Tom P. S. Angier, Iain T. Benson & Mark Retter (eds.), The Cambridge handbook of natural law and human rights. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  52
    Fundamental laws and ad hoc decisions: A reply to Curry.Christopher Ray - 1991 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 23 (4):661-664.
  32.  61
    Morals, manners, and law.Christopher Morris - 2000 - Journal of Value Inquiry 34 (1):45-59.
  33.  5
    6. Law and Domination.Christoph Menke - 2017 - In Cristina Lafont & Penelope Deutscher (eds.), Critical Theory in Critical Times: Transforming the Global Political and Economic Order. New York, USA: Columbia University Press. pp. 117-138.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Law and violence.Christoph Menke - 2018 - In Law and Violence: Chirstoph Menke in dialogue. Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  16
    Recasting (the near-miss to) Weber's law.Christopher W. Doble, Jean-Claude Falmagne & Bruce G. Berg - 2003 - Psychological Review 110 (2):365-375.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  50
    Nature as Reason: A Thomistic Theory of the Natural Law.Christopher Kaczor - 2006 - International Philosophical Quarterly 46 (1):121-122.
  37.  88
    Making Amends: Atonement in Law, Morality and Politics.Christopher Bennett - 2011 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 8 (1):165-167.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  9
    The philosophy of criminal law: an introduction.Christopher Cowley - 2024 - New York, NY: Routledge. Edited by Nicola Padfield.
    The Philosophy of Criminal Law: An Introduction explores the central concepts of criminal law, such as intention, complicity, duress, and how they work, both within criminal law practice and in our everyday lives, from legal and philosophical perspectives. At the heart of the book is the central philosophical concept of responsibility: what does it mean to be responsible for an act, to hold someone responsible for an act, or to give an excuse in order to avoid responsibility for an act? (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  16
    Primitive Law.Christoph Kletzer - 2013 - Jurisprudence 4 (2):263-272.
    This paper considers an instance of Ancient Germanic Law in order to open up a new perspective on understanding the nature and functioning of our modern law. The paper claims, along Kelsenian lines, that the law should be understood as an organisation of force and an interpretation of violence. The law orders society by schematising interpretation. The law orders society not by demanding or prohibiting action, but by allowing a certain interpretation of states of affairs, ultimately, the interpretation of violence (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40. New natural law foundations of human rights.Christopher Tollefsen - 2022 - In Tom P. S. Angier, Iain T. Benson & Mark Retter (eds.), The Cambridge handbook of natural law and human rights. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  39
    The derivation of Poiseuille’s law: heuristic and explanatory considerations.Christopher Pincock - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3-4):11667-11687.
    This paper illustrates how an experimental discovery can prompt the search for a theoretical explanation and also how obtaining such an explanation can provide heuristic benefits for further experimental discoveries. The case considered begins with the discovery of Poiseuille’s law for steady fluid flow through pipes. The law was originally supported by careful experiments, and was only later explained through a derivation from the more basic Navier–Stokes equations. However, this derivation employed a controversial boundary condition and also relied on a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  48
    Code is law: how COMPAS affects the way the judiciary handles the risk of recidivism.Christoph Engel, Lorenz Linhardt & Marcel Schubert - forthcoming - Artificial Intelligence and Law:1-22.
    Judges in multiple US states, such as New York, Pennsylvania, Wisconsin, California, and Florida, receive a prediction of defendants’ recidivism risk, generated by the COMPAS algorithm. If judges act on these predictions, they implicitly delegate normative decisions to proprietary software, even beyond the previously documented race and age biases. Using the ProPublica dataset, we demonstrate that COMPAS predictions favor jailing over release. COMPAS is biased against defendants. We show that this bias can largely be removed. Our proposed correction increases overall (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Plato's Theory of Goods in the Laws and Philebus.Christopher Bobonich - 1995 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 11:101-136.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  44.  61
    Assisted Death: A Study in Ethics and Law.Christopher Belshaw - 2014 - Philosophical Quarterly 64 (254):157-158.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  8
    An Introduction to Plato's Laws.Christopher Rowe - 1984 - Philosophical Books 25 (4):195-197.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. (1 other version)Persuasion, Compulsion and Freedom in Plato's Laws.Christopher Bobonich - 1991 - Classical Quarterly 41 (2):365-388.
    One of the distinctions that Plato in the Laws stresses most heavily in his discussion of the proper relation between the individual citizen and the laws of the city is that between persuasion and compulsion. Law, Plato believes, should try to persuade rather than compel the citizens. Near the end of the fourth book of the Laws, the Athenian Stranger, Plato's spokesman in this dialogue, asks whether the lawgiver for their new city of Magnesia should in making laws ‘explain straightaway (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  47.  33
    From Actuality to Goodness: Aristotle’s Rejection of Hume’s Law.Christopher Shields - 2024 - In David Keyt & Christopher Shields (eds.), Principles and Praxis in Ancient Greek Philosophy: Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy in Honor of Fred D. Miller, Jr. Springer Verlag. pp. 175-194.
    Aristotle’s Metaphysics Λ.7 features an argumentative progression from the unwavering actuality of the unmoved mover through its necessity to its goodness, which goodness in turn grounds the manner in which it serves as the ultimate principle of motion, namely, by being an object of love and desire (1072b4-12). One link in this progression is especially brief and startling, namely the second of two inferences in this short sentence: “It is a being of necessity, therefore, and in so far as [it (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  21
    From colonial violence to decriminalisation and recognition: An interdisciplinary appraisal of perspectives on Indian LGBTQ+ community’s encounter with law.Ashitha Mary Christopher & Unni Krishnan Karikkat - 2023 - Journal for Cultural Research 27 (1):105-119.
    This article explores the duality of law with regard to the LGBTQ+ community, examining both its historical regulation of non-heteronormative genders and sexualities and its contradictory potential to transcend such regulations over time. Situated within a postcolonial analytical framework, it undertakes a thematic overview and narrative appraisal of research materials, drawn from a diverse array of social science disciplinary intersections, spanning the timeline from 1990 to 2022, that expounds on the intricate and overlapping imbrications between law and the LGBTQ+ community (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  29
    Must Penal Law Be Insulated from Public Influence?Christopher D. Berk - 2020 - Law and Philosophy 40 (1):67-87.
    Punishment and democracy appear to exacerbate each other’s worst features. The institutions and moral intuitions used to punish those that break the law can hollow out civic participation, distort the electorate, and undermine core democratic values. Likewise, many have argued the decentralized character of democracy is a key, albeit indirect, cause of increasingly punitive public policies that are divorced from any reasonable penological purpose. Given the effects of electoral politics, many have called for the separation, or general insulation, of state (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Salmon on explanatory relevance.Christopher Read Hitchcock - 1995 - Philosophy of Science 62 (2):304-320.
    One of the motivations for Salmon's (1984) causal theory of explanation was the explanatory irrelevance exhibited by many arguments conforming to Hempel's covering-law models of explanation. However, the nexus of causal processes and interactions characterized by Salmon is not rich enough to supply the necessary conception of explanatory relevance. Salmon's (1994) revised theory, which is briefly criticized on independent grounds, fares no better. There is some possibility that the two-tiered structure of explanation described by Salmon (1984) may be pressed into (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   103 citations  
1 — 50 / 942