Results for 'Federal Rules of Evidence'

952 found
Order:
  1. Shielding Parties to Title VII Actions for Sexual Harassment from the Discovery of their Sexual History - Should Rule 412 of the Federal Rules of Evidence be Applicable to Discovery?Richard Bell - 1998 - Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics and Public Policy 12 (1):285-342.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  67
    Epistemology, research methodology and rule 702 of the federal rules of evidence versus eva®.Stanley Paulo - 2003 - Journal of Business Ethics 44 (4):327 - 341.
    This article questions the continued use and application of EVA® (economic value added) because it is epistemologically a non-sequitur, fails to satisfy the requirements of sound research methodology in terms of being a reliable and valid metric, and is unlikely to satisfy the requirements of Rule 702 of the Federal Rules of Evidence. In the light of these insufficiencies, the continued use of EVA® is ethically questionable, and moreover in time is likely to result in class actions.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Brain Images as Legal Evidence.Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Adina Roskies, Teneille Brown & Emily Murphy - 2008 - Episteme 5 (3):359-373.
    This paper explores whether brain images may be admitted as evidence in criminal trials under Federal Rule of Evidence 403, which weighs probative value against the danger of being prejudicial, confusing, or misleading to fact finders. The paper summarizes and evaluates recent empirical research relevant to these issues. We argue that currently the probative value of neuroimages for criminal responsibility is minimal, and there is some evidence of their potential to be prejudicial or misleading. We also (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  4.  15
    Can Insurance Market Competition Coexist With Provider Price Regulation? Evidence From Medicare Advantage.Robert A. Berenson, Judith Feder & Laura Skopec - 2019 - Inquiry: The Journal of Health Care Organization, Provision, and Financing 56:004695801985528.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  25
    From Evidence‐Based Medicine to Evidence‐Based Practice.Michelle N. Meyer - 2013 - Hastings Center Report 43 (2):11-12.
    As a recent special report in the Hastings Center Report demonstrates, many bioethicists are rethinking the way we regulate both biomedical research and clinical practice, as well as the sharp boundary that the field has assumed can and should exist between them. Such a rethinking is long overdue. There is surely a meaningful normative distinction between activities whose expected risk‐benefit profile is and is not “reasonable” for participants (to echo the language in the Common Rule—the core set of human research (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  17
    Social policy.Eva Feder Kittay - 1998 - In Alison M. Jaggar & Iris Marion Young, A companion to feminist philosophy. Malden, Mass.: Blackwell. pp. 569–580.
    Social policy, broadly understood, is an intervention by government or other public institution designed to promote the well‐being of its members or intended to rectify perceived social problems. Governmental policy can issue from legislative, executive, or judicial actions. Regulations and rules governing major public establishments, such as universities or medical institutions, and directed at promoting the aims of the larger social body can also be considered instruments of social policy. Social policy is sometimes understood more narrowly as interventions of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  33
    The Expert Witness: Lessons from the U.S. Experience.Susan Haack - 2015 - Humana Mente 8 (28).
    The first section of this paper explains why assessing the worth of expert testimony poses special epistemological difficulties. The second traces the history of the various rules and procedures by means of which the U.S. legal system has tried to ensure, or at least control, the quality of the expert testimony on which it so often relies—from the Frye Rule, the Federal Rules of Evidence, and the Daubert trilogy to recent constitutional cases regarding the appearance of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  55
    Evidence, Logic, the Rule and the Exception in Renaissance Law and Medicine.Ian Maclean - 2000 - Early Science and Medicine 5 (3):227-256.
    This article sets out to investigate aspects of the uptake of Renaissance law and medicine from some of the logical and natural-philosophical components of the university arts course. Medicine is shown to have a much laxer operative logic than law, reflecting its commitment to the theory of idiosyncrasy as opposed to the demands made upon the law by the need for a uniform application of justice. Symptomatic of the different uptake arc the contrasting meanings of "regulariter" and "generaliter" in the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  9.  22
    School structure, bullying by teachers, moral disengagement, and students’ aggression: A mediation model.Valeria Ivaniushina & Daniel Alexandrov - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13:883750.
    AimUnderstanding interrelations between the factors predicting students’ aggressive behavior is a priority for bullying-prevention programs. Our study explores two possible mechanisms linking school disciplinary structure and students’ aggression. We test students’ moral disengagement and bullying by teachers as mediational pathways from school authoritative discipline to students’ aggressive behavior.MethodsWe used a regionally representative sample of 213 schools that participated in a school climate survey in Kaluga Oblast (a federal subject of Russia) in 2019. The analytical sample contained the anonymous responses (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. Some evidence that irregular forms are retrieved from memory but regular forms are rule generated.Sandeep Prasada, Steven Pinker & William Snyder - 1990 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 28 (6):519-519.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  11.  18
    Evidence That Indirect Object Movement Is a Structure-Preserving Rule.Joseph Emonds - 1972 - Foundations of Language 8 (4):546-561.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12.  13
    Medical Assistance in Dying for Persons Suffering Solely from Mental Illness in Canada.Chloe Eunice Panganiban & Srushhti Trivedi - 2025 - Voices in Bioethics 11.
    Photo ID 71252867© Stepan Popov| Dreamstime.com Abstract While Medical Assistance in Dying (MAiD) has been legalized in Canada since 2016, it still excludes eligibility for persons who have mental illness as a sole underlying medical condition. This temporary exclusion was set to expire on March 17th, 2024, but was set 3 years further back by the Government of Canada to March 17th, 2027. This paper presents a critical appraisal of the case of MAiD for individuals with mental illness as the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  24
    The journalism educator as expert witness.Roy L. Moore - 1997 - Journal of Mass Media Ethics 12 (2):82 – 95.
    Journalism educators who appear as expert witnesses and consultants in media law cases such as libel and invasion of privacy are often unfamiliar with the practical aspects of serving as an eflective, efficient, and ethical expert. These practical dimensions include federal and state rules of evidence and civil procedure, the process of deciding whether or not to accept a case, negotiations over fees and employment conditions, ethical conflicts associated with representation, the litigation process, and post-trial issues. It (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  27
    Conditional Relevance and Conditional Admissibility.Matthew Kotzen - 2023 - Law and Philosophy 42 (3):237-283.
    In this paper, I aim to explicate the distinction between ‘unconditional relevance’ and ‘conditional relevance’ as those terms and related concepts are applied in the context of admissibility determinations in modern trials. I take the U.S. Federal Rules of Evidence to be my model in analyzing these concepts, though on my view any reasonable approach to legal evidence will have to distinguish between these concepts and make appropriate provisions for their separate treatment. I begin by explaining (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Rules of evidence.A. DeVaney - 1990 - Journal of Thought 25 (172):6-1.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  13
    Commentary: Reaffirming the rule of law in federal sentencing.Tom Feeney - 2003 - Criminal Justice Ethics 22 (2):2-73.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. A Third Way: Ethics Guidance as Evidence-Informed Provisional Rules.Kirstin Borgerson & Joseph Millum - 2010 - American Journal of Bioethics 10 (6):20-22.
  18.  36
    Drinking Rules! Byron and Baudelaire.Joshua Wilner - 1997 - Diacritics 27 (3):34-48.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Drinking Rules! Byron and BaudelaireJoshua Wilner (bio)This essay 1 takes up two nineteenth-century texts on the theme of intoxication in which the poetic word can no longer, if it ever could, stably figure itself as the metaphoric other of the drug, that is, as a legitimate means of imaginative transport, and in which the writer’s enthrallment by the transporting substance of words shows us its addictive and, one (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  17
    Comparative law and English laws character evidence rules.Munday Roderick - 1993 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 13 (4):589-601.
  20. Disability Rights as a Necessary Framework for Crisis Standards of Care and the Future of Health Care.Laura Guidry-Grimes, Katie Savin, Joseph A. Stramondo, Joel Michael Reynolds, Marina Tsaplina, Teresa Blankmeyer Burke, Angela Ballantyne, Eva Feder Kittay, Devan Stahl, Jackie Leach Scully, Rosemarie Garland-Thomson, Anita Tarzian, Doron Dorfman & Joseph J. Fins - 2020 - Hastings Center Report 50 (3):28-32.
    In this essay, we suggest practical ways to shift the framing of crisis standards of care toward disability justice. We elaborate on the vision statement provided in the 2010 Institute of Medicine (National Academy of Medicine) “Summary of Guidance for Establishing Crisis Standards of Care for Use in Disaster Situations,” which emphasizes fairness; equitable processes; community and provider engagement, education, and communication; and the rule of law. We argue that interpreting these elements through disability justice entails a commitment to both (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  21.  26
    Evidence Matters: Science, Proof, and Truth in the Law.Susan Haack - 2014 - New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
    Is truth in the law just plain truth - or something sui generis? Is a trial a search for truth? Do adversarial procedures and exclusionary rules of evidence enable, or impede, the accurate determination of factual issues? Can degrees of proof be identified with mathematical probabilities? What role can statistical evidence properly play? How can courts best handle the scientific testimony on which cases sometimes turn? How are they to distinguish reliable scientific testimony from unreliable hokum? These (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  22. Rules and Right in Mill.Piers Norris Turner - 2015 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 53 (4):723-745.
    Recent scholarship on John Stuart Mill’s moral theory has settled on the view that he is committed to a form of rule utilitarianism. I argue that this consensus is mistaken. Mill’s explicit account of practical rules is incompatible with rule utilitarianism but consistent with sophisticated act utilitarianism. I also examine the direct, textual evidence cited by rule utilitarian interpreters, arguing that it is consistent with the act utilitarian account of practical rules. Finally, I argue that two systematic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  23.  29
    Implementing Regulatory Broad Consent Under the Revised Common Rule: Clarifying Key Points and the Need for Evidence.Holly Fernandez Lynch, Leslie E. Wolf & Mark Barnes - 2019 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 47 (2):213-231.
    The revised Common Rule includes a new option for the conduct of secondary research with identifiable data and biospecimens: regulatory broad consent. Motivated by concerns regarding autonomy and trust in the research enterprise, regulators had initially proposed broad consent in a manner that would have rendered it the exclusive approach to secondary research with all biospecimens, regardless of identifiability. Based on public comments from both researchers and patients concerned that this approach would hinder important medical advances, however, regulators decided to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  24.  40
    Research Misconduct Involving Noncompliance in Human Subjects Research Supported by the Public Health Service: Reconciling Separate Regulatory Systems.Barbara E. Bierer & Mark Barnes - 2014 - Hastings Center Report 44 (s3):2-26.
    Over the past three decades, two separate federal regulatory structures have emerged, each seeking to assure separate aspects of the integrity and ethics of research conducted using federal funding. One set of regulations is described in the Public Health Service Policies on Research Misconduct and relates to research misconduct, defined as consisting of fabrication of data or results, falsification of data and results, or plagiarism, in accordance with the federal‐wide definition adopted by the Office of Science and (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  13
    Corruption and Federalism: (When) Do Federal Criminal Prosecutions Improve Non-Federal Democracy?Roderick M. Hills - 2005 - Theoretical Inquiries in Law 6 (1):113-154.
    Are federal prosecutions of non-federal officials for corruption likely to improve non-federal government? This essay suggests that such prosecutions can undermine the distinctive style of democracy at the state and local level, an effect that can be harmful to democracy in America overall. This conclusion rests on a larger argument about the different nature of federal and non-federal democracy in the United States. To insure that each official maintains impartial loyalty to values defined by a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Evidence, Risk, and Proof Paradoxes: Pessimism about the Epistemic Project.Giada Fratantonio - 2021 - International Journal of Evidence and Proof:online first.
    Why can testimony alone be enough for findings of liability? Why statistical evidence alone can’t? These questions underpin the “Proof Paradox” (Redmayne 2008, Enoch et al. 2012). Many epistemologists have attempted to explain this paradox from a purely epistemic perspective. I call it the “Epistemic Project”. In this paper, I take a step back from this recent trend. Stemming from considerations about the nature and role of standards of proof, I define three requirements that any successful account in line (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  27.  37
    A Strategy to Improve Knowledge about Health Policies and Evidence Based Medicine for Federal Magistrates in Health Litigation.Bruno Barcala Reis, Marcus Carvalho Borin, Marcelo Dolzany da Costa, Renato Luís Dresch, Osvaldo Oliveira Araújo Firmo, Melissa Cordeiro Guimarães, Carla Barbosa Morais Alves, Nelio Gomes Ribeiro Junior, Ludmila Peres Gargano, Túlio Tadeu Rocha Sarmento, Pâmela Santos Azevedo, Isabella de Figueiredo Zuppo, Carolina Zampirolli Dias, Vania Cristina Canuto dos Santos, Juliana Alvares-Teodoro, Francisco de Assis Acurcio & Augusto Afonso Guerra Junior - 2022 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 50 (4):807-817.
    Several countries maintain universal health coverage, which implies responsibility to organize delivery formats of healthcare services and products for citizens. In Brazil, the health system has a principle of universal access for more than 30 years, but many deficiencies remain and the country observes a day practice for those seeking judicial decisions to determine provision of healthcare.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Rules and Reason: Perspectives on Constitutional Political Economy.Ram Mudambi, Pietro Navarra & Giuseppe Sobbrio (eds.) - 2001 - Cambridge University Press.
    Polarization in Western democracies and the collapse of centrally planned economies have led to calls for a redefinition of the state's core functions. This volume explores shifting conceptions of constitutional political economy anchoring the state from the viewpoints of theory, systems, and applications. It suggests why changes may be desirable and how these might be implemented. Part I addresses the writing of constitutions, the dynamic between constitutional order and civil society, the struggle between competitive and protectionist interests, the conflict between (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Rules and Principles in Moral Decision Making: An Empirical Objection to Moral Particularism.Jennifer L. Zamzow - 2015 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 18 (1):123-134.
    It is commonly thought that moral rules and principles, such as ‘Keep your promises,’ ‘Respect autonomy,’ and ‘Distribute goods according to need ,’ should play an essential role in our moral deliberation. Particularists have challenged this view by arguing that principled guidance leads us to engage in worse decision making because principled guidance is too rigid and it leads individuals to neglect or distort relevant details. However, when we examine empirical literature on the use of rules and principles (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  30. Epistemic Rules.Paul A. Boghossian - 2008 - Journal of Philosophy 105 (9):472-500.
    According to a very natural picture of rational belief, we aim to believe only what is true. However, as Bernard Williams used to say, the world does not just inscribe itself onto our minds. Rather, we have to try to figure out what is true from the evidence available to us. To do this, we rely on a set of epistemic rules that tell us in some general way what it would be most rational to believe under various (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   89 citations  
  31.  32
    Effects of amount of evidence and range of rule on the use of hypothesis and target tests by groups in rule-discovery tasks.Christine Hoffmann & Helmut Crott - 2004 - Thinking and Reasoning 10 (4):321 – 354.
    This experiment investigated the use of positive and negative hypothesis and target tests by groups in an adaptation of the 2-4-6 Wason task. The experimental variables were range of rule (small vs large), amount of evidence (low vs high), and trial block (1 vs 2). The results were in accordance with Klayman and Ha's (1987) analysis of base rate probabilities of falsification and with additional theoretical considerations. Base rate probabilities were more descriptive of participants' behaviour in target than in (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Evidence and Justification.David Kelley - 1991 - Reason Papers 16:165-179.
    Knowledge must be grounded in evidence in accordance with epistemological principles. This monograph distinguishes two kinds of principle: rules of evidence and rules of justification. -/- Rules of evidence, such the canons of inductive and deductive logic, specify what sort of evidence is relevant to what sort of conclusion. Rules of justification specify what a person's cognitive state must be if he is to be justified in accepting a conclusion. This distinction makes (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  33.  2
    Limited evidence that fitness interdependence produces historical origin myths.Andreas Wimmer - 2024 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 47:e194.
    This commentary points out some theoretical lacuna in the argument and then evaluates, in a preliminary way, its main comparative empirical hypotheses. It finds very limited support for the observable implications of the evolutionary theory. By contrast, the historical remoteness of foundational myths is closely associated with how long a society has been ruled by a centralized state, pointing at the important role of political history.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  65
    Unspoken Rules: Resolving Underdetermination With Closure Principles.Shaun Nichols & Jerry Gaus - 2018 - Cognitive Science 42 (8):2735-2756.
    When people learn normative systems, they do so based on limited evidence. Many of the possible actions that are available to an agent have never been explicitly permitted or prohibited. But people will often need to figure out whether those unspecified actions are permitted or prohibited. How does a learner resolve this incompleteness? The learner might assume if an action-type is not expressly forbidden, then acts of that type are permitted. This closure principle is one of Liberty. Alternatively, the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35. Less Evidence, Better Knowledge.Kenneth M. Ehrenberg - 2015 - McGill Law Journal 60 (2):173-214.
    In his 1827 work Rationale of Judicial Evidence, Jeremy Bentham famously argued against exclusionary rules such as hearsay, preferring a policy of “universal admissibility” unless the declarant is easily available. Bentham’s claim that all relevant evidence should be considered with appropriate instructions to fact finders has been particularly influential among judges, culminating in the “principled approach” to hearsay in Canada articulated in R. v. Khelawon. Furthermore, many scholars attack Bentham’s argument only for ignoring the realities of juror (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Defeasible rules and interpersonal accountability.Bruce Chapman - 2012 - In Jordi Ferrer Beltrán & Giovanni Battista Ratti, The Logic of Legal Requirements: Essays on Defeasibility. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press.
    Defeasible rules are said to allow for the following two-staged sequence, viz., that p → q and yet p & r → not-q. This is puzzling because in the logic of conditionals the sufficiency of p for q cannot normally be undermined if one adds to the antecedent a further proposition r. Critics argue that the better approach to comprehending defeasibility is explicitly to represent the limiting factor r in a single-stage articulation of the rule, viz., as p & (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Rules for reasoning.Richard E. Nisbett (ed.) - 1993 - Hillsdale, N.J.: L. Erlbaum Associates.
    This book examines two questions: Do people make use of abstract rules such as logical and statistical rules when making inferences in everyday life? Can such abstract rules be changed by training? Contrary to the spirit of reductionist theories from behaviorism to connectionism, there is ample evidence that people do make use of abstract rules of inference -- including rules of logic, statistics, causal deduction, and cost-benefit analysis. Such rules, moreover, are easily alterable (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  38.  25
    Federal provider conscience regulation: unconscionable.Robert F. Card - 2009 - Journal of Medical Ethics 35 (8):471-472.
    This paper argues that the provider conscience regulation recently put into place in the USA is misguided. The rule is too broad in the scope of protection it affords, and its conception of what constitutes assistance in the performance of an objectionable procedure reveals that it is unworkable in practice. Furthermore, the regulation wrongly treats refusal of other reproductive services as on a par with conscientious objection to participation in abortion. Finally, the rule allows providers to refuse even to discuss (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  34
    U.S. Federal Regulations for Emergency Research: A Practical Guide and Commentary.Andrew McRae & Charles Weijer - unknown
    Emergency medicine research requires the enrollment of subjects with varying decision-making capacities, including capable adults, adults incapacitated by illness or injury, and children. These different categories of subjects are protected by multiple federal regulations. These include the federal Common Rule, the Department of Health and Human Services (DHHS) regulations for pediatric research, and the Food and Drug Administration's (FDA) Final Rule for the Exception from the Requirements of Informed Consent in Emergency Situations. Investigators should be familiar with the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  44
    Public Choice in a Federal System.Jean-Luc Migué - 1996 - Journal des Economistes Et des Etudes Humaines 7 (1):3-18.
    A part les contraintes imposées aux décisions publiques par 1a mobilité, l’analyse reçue des choix publics postule que le processus politique fonctionne essentiellement de la même façon en régime fédéral qu’en régime unitaire. Il s’avère cependant qu’il existe une dimension du processus politique en régime fédéral qui se prête spécifiquement à l’analyse économique, nommément le fait que, là où les fonctions se recoupent dans un même territoire, il se trouve deux niveaux de gouvernement qui se concurrencent dans l’offre des mêmes (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  31
    Inference Rules in Nelson’s Logics, Admissibility and Weak Admissibility.Sergei Odintsov & Vladimir Rybakov - 2015 - Logica Universalis 9 (1):93-120.
    Our paper aims to investigate inference rules for Nelson’s logics and to discuss possible ways to determine admissibility of inference rules in such logics. We will use the technique offered originally for intuitionistic logic and paraconsistent minimal Johannson’s logic. However, the adaptation is not an easy and evident task since Nelson’s logics do not enjoy replacement of equivalences rule. Therefore we consider and compare standard admissibility and weak admissibility. Our paper founds algorithms for recognizing weak admissibility and admissibility (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Respecting all the evidence.Paulina Sliwa & Sophie Horowitz - 2015 - Philosophical Studies 172 (11):2835-2858.
    Plausibly, you should believe what your total evidence supports. But cases of misleading higher-order evidenceevidence about what your evidence supports—present a challenge to this thought. In such cases, taking both first-order and higher-order evidence at face value leads to a seemingly irrational incoherence between one’s first-order and higher-order attitudes: you will believe P, but also believe that your evidence doesn’t support P. To avoid sanctioning tension between epistemic levels, some authors have abandoned the thought (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  43. Rules.Ron Mallon & Shaun Nichols - 2010 - In John Doris, Moral Psychology Handbook. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press.
    Is it wrong to torture prisoners of war for fun? Is it wrong to yank on someone’s hair with no provocation? Is it wrong to push an innocent person in front of a train in order to save five innocent people tied to the tracks? If you are like most people, you answered "yes" to each of these questions. A venerable account of human moral judgment, influential in both philosophy and psychology, holds that these judgments are underpinned by internally represented (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  44.  12
    Evidence and ethics in medicine.John Worrall - 2008 - Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 51 (3):418-431.
    Ethics and epistemology in medicine are more closely and more interestingly intertwined than is usually recognized. To explore this relationship, I present a case study, clinical trials of extracorporeal membrane oxygenation (ECMO; an intervention for persistent pulmonary hypertension of the newborn).Three separate ethical issues that arise from this case study-whether or not it is ethical to perform a certain trial at all, whether stopping rules for trials are ethically mandated, and the issue of informed consent-are all shown to be (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  45.  30
    The Obama Administration's Regulatory Review Initiative: A 21st Century Federal Regulatory Initiative?Thomas A. Hemphill - 2012 - Business and Society Review 117 (2):185-195.
    On January 18, 2011, President Obama signed Executive Order 13563, Improving Regulation and Regulatory Review, which instructs federal regulators to do the following: coordinate their agencies activities to simplify and harmonize rules that may be overlapping, inconsistent, or redundant; determine whether the present and future benefits of a proposed regulation justify its potential costs (including taking into account both quantitative and qualitative factors); increase participation of industry, experts, and the public (“stakeholders”) in the formal rule‐making process; encourage the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  43
    Rules, Equilibria and Virtual Control: How to Explain Persistence, Resilience and Fragility.Frank Hindriks - 2023 - Erkenntnis 88 (4):1367-1389.
    Institutions are often regarded either as rules or as equilibria sustained by self-interested agents. I ask how these two theories can be combined. According to Philip Pettit’s _Virtual Control Theory_, they explain different things: rules explain why regularities persist; self-interest why they are resilient. Thus, his theory reconciles the two theories by adjusting their domains of application. However, the available evidence suggests that rules and self-interest often combine as sources of motivation. Because of this, it is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47. Dual Processes and Moral Rules.Ron Mallon & Shaun Nichols - 2011 - Emotion Review 3 (3):284-285.
    Recent work proclaims a dominant role for automatic, intuitive, and emotional processes in producing ordinary moral judgment, despite the fact that we have little direct evidence about moral judgment “in the wild.” Indirect support comes via an assumption of dual-process theory: that conscious, reasoning processes are resource intensive. We argue that reasoning that employs consciously available moral rules undermines this assumption, but this has not been appreciated because of a failure to distinguish between explanation and justification. We conclude (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  48. Updating without evidence.Yoaav Isaacs & Jeffrey Sanford Russell - 2023 - Noûs 57 (3):576-599.
    Sometimes you are unreliable at fulfilling your doxastic plans: for example, if you plan to be fully confident in all truths, probably you will end up being fully confident in some falsehoods by mistake. In some cases, there is information that plays the classical role of evidence—your beliefs are perfectly discriminating with respect to some possible facts about the world—and there is a standard expected‐accuracy‐based justification for planning to conditionalize on this evidence. This planning‐oriented justification extends to some (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  49.  7
    Rules, Regs, and What's Right.Gregory E. Kaebnick - 2014 - Hastings Center Report 44 (4):2-2.
    Several items in this issue of the Hastings Center Report try to fill gaps or resolve uncertainties in the regulatory systems that govern research on human subjects. The biggest of these items is a special report, published as a supplement to the issue, that considers a long‐running and vexing regulatory problem: the uncertain relationship between the two sets of federal regulations for research. The goal of the report is to provide guidance.The lead article inside the issue addresses a problem (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50. Turing's rules for the imitation game.Gualtiero Piccinini - 2000 - Minds and Machines 10 (4):573-582.
    In the 1950s, Alan Turing proposed his influential test for machine intelligence, which involved a teletyped dialogue between a human player, a machine, and an interrogator. Two readings of Turing's rules for the test have been given. According to the standard reading of Turing's words, the goal of the interrogator was to discover which was the human being and which was the machine, while the goal of the machine was to be indistinguishable from a human being. According to the (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
1 — 50 / 952