Results for 'Hart, Dworkin, Social Thesis, Philosophy of Law, Legal Positivism, Natural Law'

971 found
Order:
  1. Contemporary legal philosophising: Schmitt, Kelsen, Lukács, Hart, & law and literature, with Marxism's dark legacy in Central Europe (on teaching legal philosophy in appendix).Csaba Varga - 2013 - Budapest: Szent István Társulat.
    Reedition of papers in English spanning from 1986 to 2009 /// Historical background -- An imposed legacy -- Twentieth century contemporaneity -- Appendix: The philosophy of teaching legal philosophy in Hungary /// HISTORICAL BACKGROUND -- PHILOSOPHY OF LAW IN CENTRAL & EASTERN EUROPE: A SKETCH OF HISTORY [1999] 11–21 // PHILOSOPHISING ON LAW IN THE TURMOIL OF COMMUNIST TAKEOVER IN HUNGARY (TWO PORTRAITS, INTERWAR AND POSTWAR: JULIUS MOÓR & ISTVÁN LOSONCZY) [2001–2002] 23–39: Julius Moór 23 / (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. The "Hart-Dworkin" debate : a short guide for the perplexed.Scott J. Shapiro - 2007 - In Arthur Ripstein (ed.), Ronald Dworkin. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 22--49.
    For the past four decades, Anglo-American legal philosophy has been preoccupied – some might say obsessed – with something called the “Hart-Dworkin” debate. Since the appearance in 1967 of “The Model of Rules I,” Ronald Dworkin’s seminal critique of H.L.A. Hart’s theory of legal positivism, countless books and articles have been written either defending Hart against Dworkin’s objections or defending Dworkin against Hart’s defenders. My purpose in this essay is not to declare an ultimate victor; rather it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  3. Between natural law and legal positivism: Dworkin and Hegel on legal theory.Thom Brooks - 2007 - Georgia State University Law Review 23 (3):513-60.
    In this article, I argue that - despite the absence of any clear influence of one theory on the other - the legal theories of Dworkin and Hegel share several similar and, at times, unique positions that join them together within a distinctive school of legal theory, sharing a middle position between natural law and legal positivism. In addition, each theory can help the other in addressing certain internal difficulties. By recognizing both Hegel and Dworkin as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  83
    Hart, Dworkin, Judges, and New Law.Robert J. Yanal - 1985 - The Monist 68 (3):388-402.
    Ronald Dworkin, beginning in about 1967, has written a series of articles attacking the dominant contemporary theory of law, the legal positivism of H. L. A. Hart. Dworkin’s articles, while largely critical, go far towards establishing his own theory of the law, a theory that while never explicitly and succinctly formulated can nonetheless be reconstructed from his critical remarks. The theory is a combination of positivism and natural law theory, and indeed has been named by one of its (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  32
    Kelsenian Legal Science and the Nature of Law.John McGarry, Ian Bryan & Peter Langford (eds.) - 2017 - Cham: Springer Verlag.
    This book critically examines the conception of legal science and the nature of law developed by Hans Kelsen. It provides a single, dedicated space for a range of established European scholars to engage with the influential work of this Austrian jurist, legal philosopher, and political philosopher. The introduction provides a thematization of the Kelsenian notion of law as a legal science. Divided into six parts, the chapter contributions feature distinct levels of analysis. Overall, the structure of the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  9
    Rewriting Hart's Postscript: Thoughts on the Development of Legal Positivism.Tom Campbell - 2011 - Problema. Anuario de Filosofía y Teoria Del Derecho 1 (5):23-52.
    The article suggests a reading of the 1st edition of H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (1961) which involves bringing to the fore the elements of moral prescription which accompany the descriptive/explanatory intent which Hart himself explicitly espouses. Thus, the functionalist account of the emergence of secondary rules in complex societies draws on the importance of social benefits, relating to justice and efficiency, benefits which Hart endorses. Consideration is then given to how the posthumous Postscript in the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  62
    Legal Positivism and Naturalistic Explanation of Action.Dan Priel - 2024 - Law and Philosophy 43 (1):31-59.
    It is natural to think of legal positivism and jurisprudential naturalism as intellectually allied ideas. Legal positivism is associated with the idea that law is a matter of social fact; naturalism is a philosophical tenet that, among other things suggests the importance of scientific findings and methods to philosophy. At the very least, there seems to be a close family resemblance between the two views. In this essay, I challenge this view from a naturalistic perspective. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  69
    Philosophy of law.Brian Bix (ed.) - 2006 - Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon ; New York, NY: Routledge.
    The first two volumes of the collection are devoted primarily to analytical legal theory--in particular, theories about the nature of law. This is the idea of legal philosophy most familiar to jurisprudential students in the English-speaking world, and many of the civil-law countries. The last two volumes sample schools and theorists who mostly come from outside the analytical tradition, and who are, in one sense or another, critical theorists--theorists more interested in offering systematic critiques of law or (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  40
    Human Rights and the Debate on Legal Positivism.Delamar José Volpato Dutra - 2015 - Dialogue and Universalism 25 (1):264-273.
    This paper presents human rights in connection with the dispute between legal positivism and legal non-positivism. The importance of this topic can be evaluated by the debate that took place between Hart and Dworkin. Indeed, much of Dworkin’s work can be considered a reaction to Hart’s positivism. The presented study argues for the defense of the thesis that in order to understand such a debate it is important to take a position between moral noncognitivism and moral cognitivism. The (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  42
    The History and Foundations of Criticism of H.L.A. Hart’s Legal Positivism in R. Dworkin’s Philosophy of Law.Sofya V. Koval - 2019 - Russian Journal of Philosophical Sciences 62 (7):124-142.
    The paper discusses the Anglo-American philosophy of law of the 20th century, more specifically the philosophy of law of Ronald Myles Dworkin and his criticism of the legal positivism of Herbert Lionel Adolphus Hart. The author presents the history of the criticism of legal positivism in Ronald Dworkin’s philosophy of law and distinguishes historical stages. The subject of the study is the critique of legal positivism but not the Hart-Dworkin debate itself, well known in (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Legal Positivism and Scottish Common Sense Philosophy.Thomas Roberts - 2005 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 18 (2).
    This paper identifies a volitional theory of meaning common to speech act theory and legal positivism, represented by Hart and Kelsen. This model is compared and contrasted with the model of social operations developed by Reid, a Common Sense Enlightenment philosopher. Whereas the former subscribes to the view that meaning is generated by acts of will, the latter finds meaning to consist of the dual elements of sign and 'directedness'.The ability of positivist theories to provide a structural account (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12. Positivism And The Inseparability Of Law And Morals.Leslie Green - 2008 - New York University Law Review 83:1035--1058.
    This is the penultimate draft of a paper originally presented at the Hart-Fuller at 50 conference, held at the NYU Law School in February 2008. A revised version will appear in the NYU Law Review. The paper seeks to clarify and assess HLA Hart's famous claim that legal positivism somehow involves a 'separation of law and morals.' The paper contends that Hart's 'separability thesis should not be confused with the 'social thesis,' with the 'sources thesis,' or with a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  13.  91
    Implications of Indeterminacy: Naturalism in Epistemology and the Philosophy of Law II. [REVIEW]Mark Greenberg - 2011 - Law and Philosophy 30 (4):453-476.
    In a circulated but heretofore unpublished 2001 paper, I argued that Leiter’s analogy to Quine’s “naturalization of epistemology” does not do the philosophical work Leiter suggests. I revisit the issues in this new essay. I first show that Leiter’s replies to my arguments fail. Most significantly, if – contrary to the genuinely naturalistic reading of Quine that I advanced – Quine is understood as claiming that we have no vantage point from which to address whether belief in scientific theories is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  14.  92
    Were the legal realists legal positivists?Danny Priel - 2008 - Law and Philosophy 27 (4):309 - 350.
    Responds to Leiter's naturalist/realist approach to jurisprudence - particularly his claim that such an approach implies exclusive positivism. Considers analogy with naturalized epistemology. "With regard to the first step the realists were anti-foundationalists in the sense that they 'denied that legal reasons justify a unique decision: the legal reasons underdetermine the decision '. The second step, the replacement suggests that instead of a justificatory account of adjudication, i.e. some prescription as to how judges should decide cases, the reaslists (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  32
    Philosophical foundations of the nature of law.Wilfrid J. Waluchow & Stefan Sciaraffa (eds.) - 2013 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    Part I. Furthering debate between leading theories of Law -- The Explantory Role of the Weak Natural Law Thesis -- In Defense of Hart -- Law's Authority is not a Claim to Preemption -- The Normative Fallacy Regarding Law's Authority -- The Problem about the Nature of Law vis-à-vis Legal Rationality Revisited : Towards an Integrative Jurisprudence -- Part II. The Power of Legal Systems -- Law as Power : Two Rule of Law Requirements -- A Comprehensive (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  56
    Essentially Ambiguous Concepts and the Fuller-Hart-Dworkin Debate.Wibren van der Burg - 2009 - Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 95 (3):305-326.
    Concepts such as law, religion or morality may refer both to a practice (or process) and to a doctrine (or product). My thesis is that we should not regard these as separate phenomena, but as two partly incompatible models of the same phenomenon. Law, religion and morality are therefore essentially ambiguous concepts (EAC). An EAC is a concept which refers to a dynamic phenomenon that may only be described and modeled in at least two different ways that are each essentially (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  17.  86
    Bibliographical essay / legal positivism, natural law, and the Hart/Dworkin debate.Stephen W. Ball - 1984 - Criminal Justice Ethics 3 (2):68-85.
  18. The Philosophy of law.Ronald Dworkin (ed.) - 1977 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Echoing the debate about the nature of law that has dominated legal philosophy for several decades, this volume includes essays on the nature of law and on law not as it is but as it should be. Wherever possible, essays have been chosen that have provoked direct responses from other legal philosophers, and in two cases these responses are included. Contributors include H.L.A. Hart, R.M. Dworkin, Lord Patrick Devlin, John Rawls, J.J. Thomson, J. Finnis, and T.M. Scanlon.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  19.  35
    Natural law and justice.Lloyd L. Weinreb - 1987 - Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
    "Human beings are a part of nature and apart from it." The argument of Natural Law and Justice is that the philosophy of natural law and contemporary theories about the nature of justice are both efforts to make sense of the fundamental paradox of human experience: individual freedom and responsibility in a causally determined universe. Professor Weinreb restores the original understanding of natural law as a philosophy about the place of humankind in nature. He traces (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  20. The Functions of Law.Kenneth M. Ehrenberg - 2016 - Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press.
    What is the nature of law and what is the best way to discover it? This book argues that law is best understood in terms of the social functions it performs wherever it is found in human society. In order to support this claim, law is explained as a kind of institution and as a kind of artefact. To say that it is an institution is to say that it is designed for creating and conferring special statuses to people (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  21.  22
    The Long Arc of Legality: Hobbes, Kelsen, Hart.David Dyzenhaus - 2021 - Cambridge University Press.
    The Long Arc of Legality breaks the current deadlock in philosophy of law between legal positivism and natural law by showing that any understanding of law as a matter of authority must account for the interaction of enacted law with fundamental principles of legality. This interaction conditions law's content so that officials have the moral resources to answer the legal subject's question, 'But, how can that be law for me?' David Dyzenhaus brings Thomas Hobbes and Hans (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Negotiating the Meaning of “Law”: The Metalinguistic Dimension of the Dispute Over Legal Positivism.David Plunkett - 2016 - Legal Theory 22 (3-4):205-275.
    One of the central debates in legal philosophy is the debate over legal positivism. Roughly, positivists say that law is ultimately grounded in social facts alone, whereas antipositivists say it is ultimately grounded in both social facts and moral facts. In this paper, I argue that philosophers involved in the dispute over legal positivism sometimes employ distinct concepts when they use the term “law” and pick out different things in the world using these concepts. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  23.  50
    Naturalizing jurisprudence: essays on American legal realism and naturalism in legal philosophy.Brian Leiter - 2007 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    Introduction: From legal realism to naturalized jurisprudence -- A note on legal indeterminacy -- Part I. American legal realism and its critics -- Rethinking legal realism: toward a naturalized jurisprudence (1997) -- Legal realism and legal positivism reconsidered (2001) -- Is there an "American" jurisprudence? (1997) -- Postscript to Part I: Interpreting legal realism -- Part II. Ways of naturalizing jurisprudence -- Legal realism, hard positivism, and the limits of conceptual analysis (1998, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  24.  12
    Hart y el problema del positivismo jurídico. Una reconstrucción en tres actos = Hart and the problem of legal positivism. A reconstruction in three acts.Francisco M. Mora-Sifuentes - 2019 - UNIVERSITAS Revista de Filosofía Derecho y Política 31:2-32.
    RESUMEN: Este trabajo tiene como finalidad destacar la contribución específica de H.L.A. Hart sobre el problema del positivismo jurídico. A juicio del autor, el tratamiento que Hart dio a la polémica entre positivismo jurídico y Derecho Natural estuvo marcada por dos extremos aparentemente contradictorios. Por una parte, se abocó a clarificar las diversas tesis que anidan tras la etiqueta “positivismo jurídico”, así como las posiciones que suelen referirse como tales. Al hacerlo abrió el camino para mostrar en qué sentido (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  7
    The soundest theory of law.C. L. Ten - 2004 - New York: Marshall Cavendish Academic.
    The papers in this volume focus on two central issues in the philosophy of law, the relationship between law and morality, and crime and punishment. In the essay that gives the title to this volume, it is argued that, although in many legal systems there are in fact significant connections between law and morality, these connections are not conceptually or logically necessary. They depend on various social practices. Ronald Dworkin's famous attempt to undermine the legal positivist's (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  63
    The “War” Between Natural Law Philosophy and Legal Positivism.Norman E. Bowie - 1974 - Idealistic Studies 4 (2):145-155.
    The war between natural law philosophy and legal positivism is an ancient one. For a time the stunning victories of Bentham and Austin virtually drove the forces of natural law from the battlefield. However, upon the collapse of Germany and Japan at the end of the Second World War, natural law became a useful tool in attempting to resolve the practical difficulties of trying war criminals. This fact and the rise of two able antagonistic generals, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. African Jurisprudence as Historical Co-extension of Diffused Legal Theories.Leye Komolafe - 2022 - Thought and Practice: A Journal of the Philosophical Association of Kenya 8 (1):51-68.
    African jurisprudence, like African philosophy, continues to be hotly debated. This article contends that the debate straddles the uniqueness claim which either emphasises the existence or possibility of a peculiar legal framework on the continent, and a historical co-extensional position reiterating that African jurisprudence is a continuum of other legal traditions. The article argues that there is no uniquely African jurisprudence, and that what obtains within the structures of jurisprudence on the continent also exists within various (...) traditions elsewhere, and as such can at best be described as ‘jurisprudence in Africa’ rather than ‘African jurisprudence’. It defends this thesis through analytic and comparative explications of the content of natural law theory and legal positivism as experienced on the continent. It concedes that relics of the colonial legal experience create contestations that inform scholars’ calls for a return to traditional legal systems. It concludes that a reconstructive jurisprudence in Africa must take cognisance of the continent’s historical and evolutionary legal experiences, but that a unified or monolithic theory may not be sufficient to address the choice of functional jurisprudence. Keywords African jurisprudence, jurisprudence in Africa, African legal evolution, diffused legal theories. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  34
    The Logic of Showing Possibility Claims. A Positive Argument for Inclusive Legal Positivism and Moral Grounds of Law.Kenneth Einar Himma - 2014 - Revus 23.
    In this essay, I argue for a view that inclusive positivists share with Ronald Dworkin. According to the Moral Incorporation Thesis (MIT), it is logically possible for a legal system to incorporate moral criteria of legality (or “grounds of law,” as Dworkin puts it). Up to this point, the debate has taken the shape of attacks on the coherence of MIT with the defender of MIT merely attempting to refute the attacking argument. I give a positive argument for MIT. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Grounding-based formulations of legal positivism.Samuele Chilovi - 2020 - Philosophical Studies 177 (11):3283-3302.
    The goal of this paper is to provide an accurate grounding-based formulation of positivism in the philosophy of law. I start off by discussing some simple formulations, based on the ideas that social facts are always either full or partial grounds of legal facts. I then raise a number of objections against these definitions: the full grounding proposal rules out possibilities that are compatible with positivism; the partial grounding proposal fails, on its own, to vindicate the distinctive (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  30.  4
    Philosophy of law: a very short introduction.Raymond Wacks - 2014 - New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
    Natural law -- Legal positivism -- Dworkin : the moral integrity of law -- Rights and justice -- Law and society -- Critical legal theory -- Understanding law : a very short epilogue.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  19
    Hart's The Concept of Law as a Study in Social Philosophy.Eerik Lagerspetz - 2011 - Problema. Anuario de Filosofía y Teoria Del Derecho 1 (5):243-264.
    El concepto de derecho de H. L. A. Hart es un clásico moderno de la teoría jurídica. Pero también es relevante para la filosofía moral y social. En este artículo se argumenta que las críticas de Hart hacia Austin y Bentham, así como sus teorías sobre la naturaleza del derecho, la moral y la coerción, retoman una tradición de pensamiento iniciada por David Hume. Además, la filosofía social de Hart tiene implicaciones normativas interesantes. Este artículo se concentrará en (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  24
    Continental perspectives on natural law theory and legal positivism.Jes Bjarup - 2004 - In Martin P. Golding & William A. Edmundson (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 287--299.
    This chapter contains section titled: Continental and Noncontinental Perspectives The English Perspective: The Rejection of Natural Law and Natural Rights The Continental Perspective: Kant on Natural Law and Natural Right The Continental Perspective: The Critique of Natural Right and Natural Law The Revival of Natural Law: The Thomistic Perspective The Transformation of Natural Law: Stammler's Doctrine of the Social Ideal Natural Law as a Worldview: Radbruch's Theory of Law and Justice (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  86
    Legal positivism and the nature of legal obligation.T. Christiano & S. Sciaraffa - 2003 - Law and Philosophy 22 (5):487-512.
  34. A Positivist Account of Legal Principles.Kenneth Einar Himma - 2001 - Dissertation, University of Washington
    In The Concept of Law, H. L. A. Hart propounds three central theses about the nature of law: a standard of behavior is a law in a society S if and only if that standard has been promulgated in accordance with the procedures specified in S's rule of recognition ; there are no necessary substantive moral constraints on the content of law ; and judges have discretion in hard cases to base their decisions on extralegal standards; thus, judges decide hard (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. (1 other version)Philosophy of Law: An Introduction.Mark Tebbit - 2000 - New York, NY: Routledge.
    __ _Philosophy of Law: An Introduction_ provides an ideal starting point for students of philosophy and law. Setting it clearly against the historical background, Mark Tebbit quickly leads readers into the heart of the philosophical questions that dominate philosophy of law today. He provides an exceptionally wide-ranging overview of the contending theories that have sought to resolve these problems. He does so without assuming prior knowledge either of philosophy or law on the part of the reader. The (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  46
    The Planning Theory and Natural Law.George Duke - 2015 - Law and Philosophy 34 (2):173-200.
    The practical, normative dimension of planning is a plausible source of the ‘family resemblances’ noted by a number of legal theorists between Scott Shapiro’s Planning Theory and natural law jurisprudence. Foremost among these resemblances is Shapiro’s contention that the law, necessarily, has a moral aim. The moral aim thesis is at first glance surprising given Shapiro’s intention to defend exclusive legal positivism and unequivocal rejection of what he takes to be the core commitments of natural law (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  11
    Law's reality: a philosophy of law.Allan Beever - 2021 - Northampton, Massachusetts: Edward Elgar Publishing.
    520 "Allan Beever lays the foundation for a timely philosophical and empirical study of the nature of law with a detailed examination of the structure of evolving law through declaratory speech acts. This engaging book demonstrates both how law itself is achieved and also its ability to generate rights, duties, obligations, permissions and powers. Structured into three distinct parts - the philosophy of law and jurisprudence, the structure of the social word and the ontology of law, and the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  11
    Dworkin and Unjust Law.David Dyzenhaus - 2016 - In Wil Waluchow & Stefan Sciaraffa (eds.), The Legacy of Ronald Dworkin. New York, NY: Oxford University Press USA.
    The existence of unjust laws and unjust legal orders poses a large problem for natural law theories that assert a necessary relationship between law and morality and thus seems to support the positivist tradition, which argues that the relationship is contingent. Ronald Dworkin’s theory of law as a matter of moral principle was plagued by the problem. But here, I argue that the same problem vexes the legal positivism of H.L.A. Hart, for Hart thought that legal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. “How to Hold the Social Fact Thesis – a Reply to Greenberg and Toh,”.Barbara Baum Levenbook - 2013 - In “How to Hold the Social Fact Thesis – a Reply to Greenberg and Toh,”. Oxford UK: Oxford University Press. pp. 75-102.
    The social fact thesis, is, roughly, that law is ultimately a matter of social fact. Mark Greenberg and Kevin Toh have launched transcendental arguments against important or interesting general versions of the social fact thesis. Together, they can be read as posing a dilemma for the thesis. Suppose that many correct assertions of law are normative. Then, according to Toh, the considerations in virtue of which they are correct cannot ultimately be social facts, because the derivation (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. The Ideals of Law: Judging and the Constitution.Jana Mohr Lone - 1996 - Dissertation, University of Washington
    The United States Constitution embodies both the real and the ideal. It is a concrete written text that uses particular words, has a history, and possesses certain limits; it is also a statement of the aspirations and dreams of a society. This dual identity requires that the Constitution be understood both as written positive law, and as an expression of a national vision and set of ideals. ;I argue for a conceptual theory of law that is positivistic in the sense (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Hart and Raz on the Non-Instrumental Moral Value of the Rule of Law: A Reconsideration. [REVIEW]Mark J. Bennett - 2011 - Law and Philosophy 30 (5):603-635.
    HLA Hart and Joseph Raz are usually interpreted as being fundamentally opposed to Lon Fuller’s argument in The Morality of Law that the principles of the rule of law are of moral value. Hart and Raz are thought to make the ‘instrumental objection’, which says that these principles are of no moral value because they are actually principles derived from reflection on how to best allow the law to guide behaviour. Recently, many theorists have come to Fuller’s defence against Hart (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  42. An argument against the social fact thesis (and some additional preliminary steps towards a new conception of legal positivism).Kevin Toh - 2008 - Law and Philosophy 27 (5):445 - 504.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  43.  49
    Erratum to: Implications of Indeterminacy: Naturalism in Epistemology and the Philosophy of Law II.Mark Greenberg - 2012 - Law and Philosophy 31 (6):619-642.
    In a circulated but heretofore unpublished 2001 paper, I argued that Leiter's analogy to Quine's 'naturalization of epistemology' does not do the philosophical work Leiter suggests. I revisit the issues in this new essay. I first show that Leiter's replies to my arguments fail. Most significantly, if — contrary to the genuinely naturalistic reading of Quine that I advanced — Quine is understood as claiming that we have no vantage point from which to address whether belief in scientific theories is (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  5
    Legal Pluralism and the Limits of Law.Margaret Davies - forthcoming - Res Publica:1-16.
    More than any other legal philosopher in the Anglo-American jurisprudence of the 1970s and 1980s Joseph Raz defined with analytical clarity the parameters for a theory of the limits of laws and legal systems. This work was foundational not only for those wishing to defend such theory but also for others (like myself) who took a systematic approach to challenging it. In laying out the conditions for a limited understanding of laws and legal systems, the early works (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Pragmatism, Rights, and Philosophy of Law.Michael Sullivan - 2000 - Dissertation, Vanderbilt University
    This project explores the potential for pragmatism to contribute to debates in philosophy of law. In particular, it claims that the method of reconstruction developed in the work of John Dewey can be fruitfully applied to contemporary legal institutions. As an example, a pragmatic approach to rights is defended as not only theoretically attractive, contra Ronald Dworkin, but as offering practical advantages over competing communitarian alternatives. Moreover, it is claimed that by proceeding in a self-consciously genealogical fashion and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  39
    Nazism, Legal Positivism and Radbruch's Thesis on Statutory Injustice.Thomas Mertens - 2003 - Law and Critique 14 (3):277-295.
    The small article “Statutory Injustice and Suprastatutory Law” published in 1946 by Gustav Radbruch is one of the most important texts in 20th century legal philosophy. Until recently, its importance was said to stem from its renewal of ‘natural law’ and from its ‘formula’, according to which the value of justice should override that of legal certainty in extreme cases. In this contribution, a close examination will show that Radbruch's text is less univocal than often suggested. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47. What is the rule of recognition ?Scott J. Shapiro - unknown
    One of the principal lessons of The Concept of Law is that legal systems are not only comprised of rules, but founded on them as well. As Hart painstakingly showed, we cannot account for the way in which we talk and think about the law - that is, as an institution which persists over time despite turnover of officials, imposes duties and confers powers, enjoys supremacy over other kinds of practices, resolves doubts and disagreements about what is to be (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  48. Inclusive legal positivism.Wilfrid J. Waluchow - 1994 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This book develops a general theory of law, inclusive legal positivism, which seeks to remain within the tradition represented by authors such as Austin, Hart, MacCormick, and Raz, while sharing some of the virtues of both classical and modern theories of natural law, as represented by authors such as Aquinas, Fuller, Finnis, and Dworkin. Its central theoretical questions are: Does the existence or content of positive law ever depend on moral considerations? If so, is this fact consistent with (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  49.  86
    Kant’s Non-Positivistic Concept of Law.Robert Alexy - 2019 - Kantian Review 24 (4):497-512.
    The main thesis of this article is that Kant’s concept of law is a non-positivistic one, notwithstanding the fact that his legal philosophy includes very strong positivistic elements. My argument takes as its point of departure the distinction of three elements, around which the debate between positivism and non-positivism turns: first, authoritative issuance, second, social efficacy, and, third, moral correctness. All positivistic theories are confined to the first two elements. As soon as a necessary connection between these (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50.  29
    The Depiction of Unwritten Law.Benjamin L. S. Nelson - 2016 - Dissertation, University of Waterloo
    Even though tacit legal norms are deeply important to our past, present, and future, the very idea of unwritten law has been difficult to pin down, and problematic in a range of ways. Existing discussions of the phenomenon fall short of adequacy on one of several fronts: either they have focused on describing the normative features of one kind of unwritten law, or completely conflated the study of unwritten law with natural law, or else offered examinations of unwritten (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 971