Results for 'I.-Ierbert Hochberg'

23 found
Order:
  1.  42
    Universals, Particulars, and Predication.Herbert Hochberg - 1965 - Review of Metaphysics 19 (1):87 - 102.
    Both and agree that there are universals—that qualities are universals. To say that the quality white is a universal is to say, in part, that one and the same thing is connected in some way to both Plato and Socrates and accounts for the truth of the sentences "Plato is white" and "Socrates is white." To put it another way, the term "white" in both sentences refers to the same entity. What arguments are there for such a view? Russell elegantly (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  2. Particulars, Universals and Russell’s Late Ontology.Herbert Hochberg - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Research 21:129-137.
    Russell’s late ontology sought to avoid “wholly colourless particulars” (substrata, points of space, bare instants of time) by appealing to complexes of compresent qualities in place of particulars that exemplify qualitieso Yet he insisted on (i) calling qualities like redness “discontinuous,” “repeatable” particulars, and (ii) claiming that such qualities were not universals, since they were not exemplified but were ultimate subjects that exemplified universal relations and universal qualities. It is argued that his choice of terminology is not only misleading, but (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  3.  61
    Causality and Generality in the Treatise and the Tractatus.Herbert Hochberg - 1986 - Hume Studies 12 (1):1-17.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:CAUSALITY AND GENERALITY IN THE TREATISE AND THE TRACTATUS In the Tractatus Wittgenstein cryptically rejects the existence of a causal connection (or relation or nexus) : 5.135There is no possible way of making an inference from the existence of one situation to the existence of another, entirely different situation. 5.136There is no causal nexus to justify such an inference. 5.1361 We cannot infer the events of the future from (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Causal Connections, Universals, and Russell’s Hypothetico-Scientific Realism.Herbert Hochberg - 1994 - The Monist 77 (1):71-93.
    In the years spanning the first half of the 20th century Bertrand Russell wavered between two incompatible accounts of physical reality. On one account, physical objects were taken to be logical constructs of phenomenal entities, the immediate data of sense experience. Such a view roughly fits the familiar characterization of being a combination of “Hume plus mathematical logic.” This type of phenomenalism, in the empiricist tradition, contrasted starkly with a variant of scientific realism, including a realistic account of causal connections (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5.  42
    Perception as purposeful inquiry: We elect where to direct each glance, and determine what is encoded within and between glances.Julian Hochberg - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (4):619-620.
    In agreement with Barsalou's point that perceptions are not the records or the products of a recording system, and with a nod to an older system in which perception is an activity of testing what future glances bring, I argue that the behavior of perceptual inquiry necessarily makes choices in what is sampled; in what and how the sample is encoded, and what structure across samples is pursued and tested; and when to conclude the inquiry. Much of this is now (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  47
    Backdrop, flat, and prop: The stage for active perceptual inquiry.Julian Hochberg - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (4):414-415.
    Lehar's revival of phenomenology and his all-encompassing Gestalt Bubble model are ambitious and stimulating. I offer an illustrated caution about phenomenology, a more fractured alternative to his Bubble model, and two lines of phenomena that may disqualify his isomorphism. I think a perceptual-inquiry model can contend.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  84
    Physicalism, behaviorism and phenomena.Herbert Hochberg - 1959 - Philosophy of Science 26 (April):93-103.
    The issue of materialism has recently been raised again. Mr. Putnam argues against philosophical behaviorism [4]. Such a position holds, as he construes it, that statements like ‘Jones is angry’ can be analyzed in solely behavioral terms. When one argues against philosophical behaviorism, he might be expected to distinguish this metaphysical position from behavior science. Putnam, however, does not make the distinction. Consequently he argues against both. I shall first state the distinction between these two different things, namely, philosophical behaviorism (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  76
    The empirical philosophy of Roger and Francis Bacon.Herbert Hochberg - 1953 - Philosophy of Science 20 (4):313-326.
    To this date Roger Bacon remains one of the controversial and colorful figures in the history of empirical science. This paper is an attempt to ascertain his views regarding the nature and function of empirical science and to compare his writings on this topic with those of the more famous Francis Bacon. The ground for comparison is the fact that both men have often been cast in the same role in the history of science; i.e., they have both been acclaimed (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  52
    Professor Quine, pegasus, and dr. Cartwright.Herbert Hochberg - 1957 - Philosophy of Science 24 (2):191-203.
    In a recent issue of this journal Dr. Cartwright attempted to defend some views of Professor Quine's by arguing that my criticism [5] of these views was based on “serious misunderstandings of Quine,” “confusions,” and “mistakes.” I shall here attempt to show that in spite of Dr. Cartwright's vigorous characterizations my criticism of Quine was well founded and neither confused nor mistaken. First, I shall briefly discuss the notion of an ideal language.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10. exemplification'tie'(or several'ties'): the nominalist recognises particular quality-instances and a universal'similarity tie'. Thus, while Russell's argument is neither blocked nor denied, it is seemingly deprived of its sting. I shall argue that the moderate nominalist, s argument fails for a number. [REVIEW]Herbert Hochberg - 1988 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66 (2).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  88
    Nominalism, General Terms, and Predication.Herbert Hochberg - 1978 - The Monist 61 (3):460-475.
    Platonism, in its most recent and seemingly most cogent form, has rested on (a) the supposed indispensability of descriptive predicate terms in so-called "improved," or "clarified," or "perspicuous" languages; (b) the distinction between subject and predicate terms based on the asymmetry of the predication relation; and (c) the claimed ontological significance of the different categories of terms implied by (a) and (b). Nominalism, in one of its most pervasive recent forms, has involved the denial of the criterion of ontological commitment (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12. I Tjing. Het boek der veranderingen, 2 vol.Richard Wilhelm, C. G. Jung & A. Hochberg-van Wallinga - 1957 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 19 (3):517-518.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  95
    How Hochberg Helped Us Take the Ontological Turn: An Introduction.Fraser MacBride - 2014 - Dialectica 68 (2):163-169.
    In this paper I briefly describe Hochberg's role in helping bringing about the ontological turn through his critique of Quine's ostrich nominalism and his arguments in favour of truth-making. I compare Hochberg and Armstrong's fact-centred metaphysics, where the former was an influence for the latter, before charting some of Hochberg's contributions to the history of philosophy.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  64
    Relations and Idealism: On Some Arguments of Hochberg against Trope Nominalism.Peter Simons - 2014 - Dialectica 68 (2):305-315.
    In a recent article, Herbert Hochberg portrays my ontological position, that of a trope nominalist who is sceptical about relational tropes, as deviating into idealism. Since there are few philosophical views I find more repugnant than idealism, I must either resist the accusation or recant. I choose to resist, by showing how relational tropes are not needed as truth-makers for a wide range of truths, and raising the real possibility that they may not be needed at all, without lapsing (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  15. What are Tropes, Fundamentally? A Formal Ontological Account.Jani Hakkarainen - 2018 - Acta Philosophica Fennica 94:129-159.
    In this paper, I elaborate on the Strong Nuclear Theory (SNT) of tropes and substances, which I have defended elsewhere, using my metatheory about formal ontology and especially fundamental ontological form. According to my metatheory, for an entity to have an ontological form is for it to be a relatum of a formal ontological relation or relations jointly in an order. The full fundamental ontological form is generically identical to a simple formal ontological relation or relations jointly in an order. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  16. Relational Order and Onto-Thematic Roles.Francesco Orilia - 2011 - Metaphysica 12 (1):1-18.
    States of affairs involving a non-symmetric relation such as loving are said to have a relational order, something that distinguishes, for instance, Romeo’s loving Juliet from Juliet’s loving Romeo. Relational order can be properly understood by appealing to o-roles, i.e., ontological counterparts of what linguists call thematic roles, e.g., agent, patient, instrument, and the like. This move allows us to meet the appropriate desiderata for a theory of relational order. In contrast, the main theories that try to do without o-roles, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  17.  32
    Dialogo con Maurizio Blondel (review).Paul T. Fuhrmann - 1964 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 2 (2):285-285.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:BOOK REVIEWS 285 than" which is both immanent and transcendent, a kind of "coincidentia oppositorum" beyond logic and definition. It is the realm of the "person" within which, although the tragic conflict is not resolved, there arises the free self from whose non-dual perspective the unity and eternity of life are seen. Within this realm the individual gains an illumination the result of which is "amor fad," his free (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  43
    Essays in Ontology (review).Avrum Stroll - 1964 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 2 (2):285-287.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:BOOK REVIEWS 285 than" which is both immanent and transcendent, a kind of "coincidentia oppositorum" beyond logic and definition. It is the realm of the "person" within which, although the tragic conflict is not resolved, there arises the free self from whose non-dual perspective the unity and eternity of life are seen. Within this realm the individual gains an illumination the result of which is "amor fad," his free (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  93
    Complex Predication and the Metaphysics of Properties.Bryan Pickel - 2014 - Dialectica 68 (2):209-230.
    The existence of complex predicates seems to support an abundant conception of properties. Specifically, the application conditions for complex predicates seem to be explained by the distribution of a sparser base of predicates. This explanatory link might suggest that the existence and distribution of properties expressed by complex predicates are explained by the existence and distribution of a sparser base of properties. Thus, complex predicates seem to legitimize the assumption of a wide array of properties. The additional properties are no (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. States of Affairs.Maria Elisabeth Reicher (ed.) - 2009 - Heusenstamm: Ontos.
    States of affairs raise, among others, the following questions: What kind of entity are they (if there are any)? Are they contingent, causally efficacious, spatio-temporal and perceivable entities, or are they abstract objects? What are their constituents and their identity conditions? What are the functions that states of affairs are able to fulfil in a viable theory, and which problems and prima facie counterintuitive consequences arise out of an ontological commitment to them? Are there merely possible (non-actual, non-obtaining) states of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21.  13
    Perception; selected readings in science and phenomenology.Paul Tibbetts - 1969 - Chicago,: Quadrangle Books.
    Introduction to sensory psychology, by C. Mueller.--Some reflections on brain and mind, by R. Brain.--In search of the engram, by K. Lashly.--Cerebral organization and behavior, by R. W. Sperry.--Relations between the central nervous system and the peripheral organs, by E. von Holst.--Effects of the Gestalt revolution, by J. E. Hochberg.--Seeing in depth, by R. L. Gregory.--The stimulus variables for visual depth perception, by J. J. Gibson.--The elaboration of the universe, by J. Piaget.--Visual perception approached by the method of stabilized (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  22. Difference, Identity and Quantification.Nicholas Mantegani - 2014 - Dialectica 68 (2):183-207.
    Most theorists treat the ‘relation’ of identity as being more fundamental (or basic) than the ‘relation’ of (numerical) difference. Herbert Hochberg suggests, instead, that difference is to be treated as basic. My goal in this paper is to answer two related questions. First, what is it for a theorist to treat difference or identity as basic? Second, which of these two ‘relations’ is to be treated as basic? I begin by outlining four reasons that one might be motivated to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23. Perception: Selected Readings in Science and Phenomenology. [REVIEW]B. M. M. - 1970 - Review of Metaphysics 24 (1):147-147.
    The 21 selections are divided into three conceptual approaches to the study of perception: the neurophysiology, the psychology, and the phenomenology of perception, with a final section, some problematic studies. In effect, however, the editor is challenging the metaphysical position hidden in the attitude that behavioral physiology should be an "exact science" without philosophical commitments. Parts II and IV, no less than the explicit statements of Husserl, Merleau-Ponty, Gurwitsch and Erwin Strauss in Part III, stand over against a point of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark