Results for 'Mays Theorem'

956 found
Order:
  1.  14
    Ernst Kapp und die Anthropologie der Medien.Harun Maye, Leander Scholz & Eduard Kolosoff (eds.) - 2019 - Berlin: Kulturverlag Kadmos.
    Alles, was der Mensch von sich wissen kann, lässt sich an den Werkzeugen und Medien ablesen, die er gebraucht. Diese These steht im Mittelpunkt des Werks von Ernst Kapp (1808-1896), Gymnasiallehrer für Geschichte und Erdkunde, Technikphilosoph und Farmer in Texas. Obwohl Ernst Kapp unbestritten als Begründer der modernen Technikphilosophie gilt, ist sein anthropologischer Ansatz bislang kaum systematisch rezipiert worden. Zwar wird sein Werk in Überblicken meist als wichtiger Ausgangspunkt für die Technikphilosophie des 20. Jahrhunderts genannt, sein heuristisches Theorem der (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2.  15
    An extension of May's Theorem to three alternatives: axiomatizing Minimax voting.Wesley H. Holliday & Eric Pacuit - manuscript
    May's Theorem [K. O. May, Econometrica 20 (1952) 680-684] characterizes majority voting on two alternatives as the unique preferential voting method satisfying several simple axioms. Here we show that by adding some desirable axioms to May's axioms, we can uniquely determine how to vote on three alternatives. In particular, we add two axioms stating that the voting method should mitigate spoiler effects and avoid the so-called strong no show paradox. We prove a theorem stating that any preferential voting (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. A conditional defense of plurality rule: generalizing May's theorem in a restricted informational environment.Robert E. Goodin & Christian List - 2006 - American Journal of Political Science 50 (4):940-949.
    May's theorem famously shows that, in social decisions between two options, simple majority rule uniquely satisfies four appealing conditions. Although this result is often cited in support of majority rule, it has never been extended beyond decisions based on pairwise comparisons of options. We generalize May's theorem to many-option decisions where voters each cast one vote. Surprisingly, plurality rule uniquely satisfies May's conditions. This suggests a conditional defense of plurality rule: If a society's balloting procedure collects only a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  4. Propensities may satisfy Bayes's theorem.David Miller - 2002 - In Miller David, Bayes's Theorem. pp. 111-116.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  24
    Cantor’s Theorem May Fail for Finitary Partitions.Guozhen Shen - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-18.
    A partition is finitary if all its members are finite. For a set A, $\mathscr {B}(A)$ denotes the set of all finitary partitions of A. It is shown consistent with $\mathsf {ZF}$ (without the axiom of choice) that there exist an infinite set A and a surjection from A onto $\mathscr {B}(A)$. On the other hand, we prove in $\mathsf {ZF}$ some theorems concerning $\mathscr {B}(A)$ for infinite sets A, among which are the following: (1) If there is a finitary (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  12
    Theorem Proving with Analytic Tableaux and Related Methods: 5th International Workshop, Tableaux '96, Terrasini (Palermo), Italy, May 15 - 17, 1996. Proceedings.Pierangelo Miglioli, Ugo Moscato, Daniele Mundici & Mario Ornaghi - 1996 - Springer Verlag.
    This books presents the refereed proceedings of the Fifth International Workshop on Analytic Tableaux and Related Methods, TABLEAUX '96, held in Terrasini near Palermo, Italy, in May 1996. The 18 full revised papers included together with two invited papers present state-of-the-art results in this dynamic area of research. Besides more traditional aspects of tableaux reasoning, the collection also contains several papers dealing with other approaches to automated reasoning. The spectrum of logics dealt with covers several nonclassical logics, including modal, intuitionistic, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. There May Be Many Arithmetical Gödel Sentences.Kaave Lajevardi & Saeed Salehi - 2021 - Philosophia Mathematica 29 (2):278–287.
    We argue that, under the usual assumptions for sufficiently strong arithmetical theories that are subject to Gödel’s First Incompleteness Theorem, one cannot, without impropriety, talk about *the* Gödel sentence of the theory. The reason is that, without violating the requirements of Gödel’s theorem, there could be a true sentence and a false one each of which is provably equivalent to its own unprovability in the theory if the theory is unsound.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  8.  21
    Γ0 May Be Minimal Subrecursively Inaccessible.Andreas Weiermann - 2001 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 47 (3):397-408.
    Let T be the standard Veblen 1908 ordinal notation system for Γ0 as defined, for example, in Schütte's 1977 textbook [13] on Proof Theory. We define a slight modification of the standard assignment of fundamental sequences for the limit ordinals in T and prove that Γ0 is subrecursively inaccessible for this assignment, i.e. the induced slow and fast growing hierarchy match up at Γ0 for the first time.The results of this paper also indicate that φε00 may be considered as a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  9.  29
    Burkhart W. H.. Theorem minimization. Proceedings of the Association for Computing Machinery, Jointly sponsored by the Association for Computing Machinery and the Mellon Institute, Pittsburgh, Pa., May 2 and 3, 1952, photo-offset, Richard Rimbach Associates, Pittsburgh 1952, pp. 259–263. [REVIEW]Raymond J. Nelson - 1953 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 18 (4):348-348.
  10. Logic may be simple. Logic, congruence and algebra.Jean-Yves Béziau - 1997 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 5:129-147.
    This paper is an attempt to clear some philosophical questions about the nature of logic by setting up a mathematical framework. The notion of congruence in logic is defined. A logical structure in which there is no non-trivial congruence relation, like some paraconsistent logics, is called simple. The relations between simplicity, the replacement theorem and algebraization of logic are studied (including MacLane-Curry’s theorem and a discussion about Curry’s algebras). We also examine how these concepts are related to such (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11.  15
    In § 2 I shall say something about logical consequence, starting from the observation that two systems of many-valued logic may have identical truth-values and truth-tables and theorems and still differ over the inferences they count as valid.T. J. Smiley - 1976 - In John P. Cleave & Stephan Körner, Philosophy of logic: papers and discussions. Berkeley: University of California Press. pp. 74.
  12.  20
    Theorems of hyperarithmetic analysis and almost theorems of hyperarithmetic analysis.James S. Barnes, Jun le Goh & Richard A. Shore - 2022 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 28 (1):133-149.
    Theorems of hyperarithmetic analysis occupy an unusual neighborhood in the realms of reverse mathematics and recursion-theoretic complexity. They lie above all the fixed iterations of the Turing jump but below ATR $_{0}$. There is a long history of proof-theoretic principles which are THAs. Until the papers reported on in this communication, there was only one mathematical example. Barnes, Goh, and Shore [1] analyze an array of ubiquity theorems in graph theory descended from Halin’s [9] work on rays in graphs. They (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  32
    Almost Theorems of Hyperarithmetic Analysis.Richard A. Shore - forthcoming - Journal of Symbolic Logic:1-33.
    Theorems of hyperarithmetic analysis (THAs) occupy an unusual neighborhood in the realms of reverse mathematics and recursion theoretic complexity. They lie above all the fixed (recursive) iterations of the Turing Jump but below ATR $_{0}$ (and so $\Pi _{1}^{1}$ -CA $_{0}$ or the hyperjump). There is a long history of proof theoretic principles which are THAs. Until Barnes, Goh, and Shore [ta] revealed an array of theorems in graph theory living in this neighborhood, there was only one mathematical denizen. In (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14. A Representation Theorem for Frequently Irrational Agents.Edward Elliott - 2017 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 46 (5):467-506.
    The standard representation theorem for expected utility theory tells us that if a subject’s preferences conform to certain axioms, then she can be represented as maximising her expected utility given a particular set of credences and utilities—and, moreover, that having those credences and utilities is the only way that she could be maximising her expected utility. However, the kinds of agents these theorems seem apt to tell us anything about are highly idealised, being always probabilistically coherent with infinitely precise (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  15. Partition-theorems for causal decision theories.Jordan Howard Sobel - 1989 - Philosophy of Science 56 (1):70-93.
    Two partition-theorems are proved for a particular causal decision theory. One is restricted to a certain kind of partition of circumstances, and analyzes the utility of an option in terms of its utilities in conjunction with circumstances in this partition. The other analyzes an option's utility in terms of its utilities conditional on circumstances and is quite unrestricted. While the first form seems more useful for applications, the second form may be of theoretical importance in foundational exercises. Comparisons are made (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  16.  72
    Inaccessible set axioms may have little consistency strength.L. Crosilla & M. Rathjen - 2002 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 115 (1-3):33-70.
    The paper investigates inaccessible set axioms and their consistency strength in constructive set theory. In ZFC inaccessible sets are of the form Vκ where κ is a strongly inaccessible cardinal and Vκ denotes the κth level of the von Neumann hierarchy. Inaccessible sets figure prominently in category theory as Grothendieck universes and are related to universes in type theory. The objective of this paper is to show that the consistency strength of inaccessible set axioms heavily depend on the context in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  17.  60
    Theorems as meaningful cultural artifacts: Making the world additive.Martin H. Krieger - 1991 - Synthese 88 (2):135 - 154.
    Mathematical theorems are cultural artifacts and may be interpreted much as works of art, literature, and tool-and-craft are interpreted. The Fundamental Theorem of the Calculus, the Central Limit Theorem of Statistics, and the Statistical Continuum Limit of field theories, all show how the world may be put together through the arithmetic addition of suitably prescribed parts (velocities, variances, and renormalizations and scaled blocks, respectively). In the limit — of smoothness, statistical independence, and large N — higher-order parts, such (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  85
    Probabilism, Representation Theorems, and Whether Deliberation Crowds Out Prediction.Edward Elliott - 2017 - Erkenntnis 82 (2):379-399.
    Decision-theoretic representation theorems have been developed and appealed to in the service of two important philosophical projects: in attempts to characterise credences in terms of preferences, and in arguments for probabilism. Theorems developed within the formal framework that Savage developed have played an especially prominent role here. I argue that the use of these ‘Savagean’ theorems create significant difficulties for both projects, but particularly the latter. The origin of the problem directly relates to the question of whether we can have (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19.  38
    Wang Hao. Formalization and automatic theorem-proving. Information processing 1965, Proceedings of IFIP Congress 65, organized by the International Federation for Information Processing, New York City, May 24–29, 1965, Volume 1, edited by Kalenich Wayne A., Spartan Books, Inc., Washington, D.C., and Macmillan and Co., Ltd., London, 1965, pp. 51–58. [REVIEW]Joyce Friedman - 1974 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 39 (2):350-350.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  19
    G ödel has emphasized the important role that his philosophical views had played in his discoveries. Thus, in a letter to Hao Wang of December 7, 1967, explaining why Skolem and others had not obtained the completeness theorem for predicate calculus, Gödel wrote: This blindness (or prejudice, or whatever you may call it) of logicians. [REVIEW]Akihiro Kanamori - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (2).
  21. The Bell Theorem as a Special Case of a Theorem of Bass.Karl Hess & Walter Philipp - 2005 - Foundations of Physics 35 (10):1749-1767.
    The theorem of Bell states that certain results of quantum mechanics violate inequalities that are valid for objective local random variables. We show that the inequalities of Bell are special cases of theorems found 10 years earlier by Bass and stated in full generality by Vorob’ev. This fact implies precise necessary and sufficient mathematical conditions for the validity of the Bell inequalities. We show that these precise conditions differ significantly from the definition of objective local variable spaces and as (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  22.  47
    Cannonito Frank B.. The Gödel incompleteness theorem and intelligent machines. AFIPS, Proceedings 1962 Spring Joint Computer Conference, San Francisco, Calif., May 1–3, 1962, vol. 21, The National Press, Palo Alto 1962, pp. 71–77. [REVIEW]Perry Smith - 1971 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 36 (4):693-693.
  23.  75
    Saharon Shelah. Infinite abelian groups, Whitehead problem and some constructions. Israel journal of mathematics, vol. 18 , pp. 243–256. - Saharon Shelah. A compactness theorem for singular cardinals, free algebras, Whitehead problem and transversals. Israel journal of mathematics, vol. 21 , pp. 319–349. - Sharaon Shelah. Whitehead groups may be not free, even assuming CH, I. Israel journal of mathematics, vol. 28 , pp. 193–204. - Saharon Shelah. Whitehead groups may not be free even assuming CH, II. Israel journal of mathematics, vol. 35 , pp. 257–285. - Saharon Shelah. On uncountable abelian groups. Israel journal of mathematics, vol. 32 , pp. 311–330. - Shai Ben-David. On Shelah's compactness of cardinals. Israel journal of mathematics, vol. 31 , pp. 34–56 and p. 394. - Howard L. Hiller and Saharon Shelah. Singular cohomology in L. Israel journal of mathematics, vol. 26 , pp. 313–319. - Howard L. Hiller, Martin Huber, and Saharon Shelah. The structure of Ext and V = L. Mathematische. [REVIEW]Ulrich Felgner - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (4):1068-1070.
  24. Twenty-five basic theorems in situation and world theory.Edward N. Zalta - 1993 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 22 (4):385-428.
    The foregoing set of theorems forms an effective foundation for the theory of situations and worlds. All twenty-five theorems seem to be basic, reasonable principles that structure the domains of properties, relations, states of affairs, situations, and worlds in true and philosophically interesting ways. They resolve 15 of the 19 choice points defined in Barwise (1989) (see Notes 22, 27, 31, 32, 35, 36, 39, 43, and 45). Moreover, important axioms and principles stipulated by situation theorists are derived (see Notes (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   60 citations  
  25.  68
    On the coase theorem and coalitional stability: the principle of equal relative concession.Partha Gangopadhyay - 2000 - Theory and Decision 48 (2):179-191.
    The Coase theorem is argued to be incompatible with bargaining set stability due to a tension between the grand coalition and sub-coalitions. We provide a counter-intuitive argument to demonstrate that the Coase theorem may be in complete consonance with bargaining set stability. We establish that an uncertainty concerning the formation of sub-coalitions will explain such compatibility: each agent fears that others may `gang up' against him and this fear forces the agents to negotiate. The grand coalition emerges from (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  76
    No Free Lunch Theorem, Inductive Skepticism, and the Optimality of Meta-induction.Gerhard Schurz - 2017 - Philosophy of Science 84 (5):825-839.
    The no free lunch theorem is a radicalized version of Hume’s induction skepticism. It asserts that relative to a uniform probability distribution over all possible worlds, all computable prediction algorithms—whether ‘clever’ inductive or ‘stupid’ guessing methods —have the same expected predictive success. This theorem seems to be in conflict with results about meta-induction. According to these results, certain meta-inductive prediction strategies may dominate other methods in their predictive success. In this article this conflict is analyzed and dissolved, by (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  27. Quantum no-go theorems and consciousness.Danko Georgiev - 2013 - Axiomathes 23 (4):683-695.
    Our conscious minds exist in the Universe, therefore they should be identified with physical states that are subject to physical laws. In classical theories of mind, the mental states are identified with brain states that satisfy the deterministic laws of classical mechanics. This approach, however, leads to insurmountable paradoxes such as epiphenomenal minds and illusionary free will. Alternatively, one may identify mental states with quantum states realized within the brain and try to resolve the above paradoxes using the standard Hilbert (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  28. How Godel's theorem supports the possibility of machine intelligence.Taner Edis - 1998 - Minds and Machines 8 (2):251-262.
    Gödel's Theorem is often used in arguments against machine intelligence, suggesting humans are not bound by the rules of any formal system. However, Gödelian arguments can be used to support AI, provided we extend our notion of computation to include devices incorporating random number generators. A complete description scheme can be given for integer functions, by which nonalgorithmic functions are shown to be partly random. Not being restricted to algorithms can be accounted for by the availability of an arbitrary (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29. Bayes' Theorem.Richard Swinburne - 2004 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 194 (2):250-251.
    Richard Swinburne: Introduction Elliott Sober: Bayesianism - its scopes and limits Colin Howson: Bayesianism in Statistics A P Dawid: Bayes's Theorem and Weighing Evidence by Juries John Earman: Bayes, Hume, Price, and Miracles David Miller: Propensities May Satisfy Bayes's Theorem 'An Essay Towards Solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chances' by Thomas Bayes, presented to the Royal Society by Richard Price. Preceded by a historical introduction by G A Barnard.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  53
    Weak Cardinality Theorems.Till Tantau - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (3):861 - 878.
    Kummer's Cardinality Theorem states that a language A must be recursive if a Turing machine can exclude for any n words ω1...., ωn one of the n + 1 possibilities for the cardinality of {ω1...., ωn} ∩ A. There was good reason to believe that this theorem is a peculiarity of recursion theory: neither the Cardinality Theorem nor weak forms of it hold for resource-bounded computational models like polynomial time. This belief may be flawed. In this paper (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  43
    Theorem Proving in Lean.Jeremy Avigad, Leonardo de Moura & Soonho Kong - unknown
    Formal verification involves the use of logical and computational methods to establish claims that are expressed in precise mathematical terms. These can include ordinary mathematical theorems, as well as claims that pieces of hardware or software, network protocols, and mechanical and hybrid systems meet their specifications. In practice, there is not a sharp distinction between verifying a piece of mathematics and verifying the correctness of a system: formal verification requires describing hardware and software systems in mathematical terms, at which point (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  7
    Coding theorems of information theory.Jacob Wolfowitz - 1961 - Englewood Cliffs, N.J.,: Prentice-Hall.
    The objective of the present edition of this monograph is the same as that of earlier editions, namely, to provide readers with some mathemati cal maturity a rigorous and modern introduction to the ideas and principal theorems of probabilistic information theory. It is not necessary that readers have any prior knowledge whatever of information theory. The rapid development of the subject has had the consequence that any one book can now cover only a fraction of the literature. The latter is (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  64
    A theorem on initial segments of degrees.S. K. Thomason - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 35 (1):41-45.
    A set S of degrees is said to be an initial segment if c ≤ d ∈ S→-c∈S. Shoenfield has shown that if P is the lattice of all subsets of a finite set then there is an initial segment of degrees isomorphic to P. Rosenstein [2] (independently) proved the same to hold of the lattice of all finite subsets of a countable set. We shall show that “countable set” may be replaced by “set of cardinality at most that of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  91
    An Improved Dutch Book Theorem for Conditionalization.Michael Rescorla - 2022 - Erkenntnis 87 (3):1013-1041.
    Lewis proved a Dutch book theorem for Conditionalization. The theorem shows that an agent who follows any credal update rule other than Conditionalization is vulnerable to bets that inflict a sure loss. Lewis’s theorem is tailored to factive formulations of Conditionalization, i.e. formulations on which the conditioning proposition is true. Yet many scientific and philosophical applications of Bayesian decision theory require a non-factive formulation, i.e. a formulation on which the conditioning proposition may be false. I prove a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  35. Arrow’s impossibility theorem and the national security state.S. M. Amadae - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 36 (4):734-743.
    This paper critically engages Philip Mirowki's essay, "The scientific dimensions of social knowledge and their distant echoes in 20th-century American philosophy of science." It argues that although the cold war context of anti-democratic elitism best suited for making decisions about engaging in nuclear war may seem to be politically and ideologically motivated, in fact we need to carefully consider the arguments underlying the new rational choice based political philosophies of the post-WWII era typified by Arrow's impossibility theorem. A distrust (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  46
    Contextual Deduction Theorems.J. G. Raftery - 2011 - Studia Logica 99 (1-3):279-319.
    Logics that do not have a deduction-detachment theorem (briefly, a DDT) may still possess a contextual DDT —a syntactic notion introduced here for arbitrary deductive systems, along with a local variant. Substructural logics without sentential constants are natural witnesses to these phenomena. In the presence of a contextual DDT, we can still upgrade many weak completeness results to strong ones, e.g., the finite model property implies the strong finite model property. It turns out that a finitary system has a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37. The Gödel Incompleteness Theorems (1931) by the Axiom of Choice.Vasil Penchev - 2020 - Econometrics: Mathematical Methods and Programming eJournal (Elsevier: SSRN) 13 (39):1-4.
    Those incompleteness theorems mean the relation of (Peano) arithmetic and (ZFC) set theory, or philosophically, the relation of arithmetical finiteness and actual infinity. The same is managed in the framework of set theory by the axiom of choice (respectively, by the equivalent well-ordering "theorem'). One may discuss that incompleteness form the viewpoint of set theory by the axiom of choice rather than the usual viewpoint meant in the proof of theorems. The logical corollaries from that "nonstandard" viewpoint the relation (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  88
    Arrow’s theorem and theory choice.Davide Rizza - 2014 - Synthese 191 (8):1847-1856.
    In a recent paper (Okasha, Mind 120:83–115, 2011), Samir Okasha uses Arrow’s theorem to raise a challenge for the rationality of theory choice. He argues that, as soon as one accepts the plausibility of the assumptions leading to Arrow’s theorem, one is compelled to conclude that there are no adequate theory choice algorithms. Okasha offers a partial way out of this predicament by diagnosing the source of Arrow’s theorem and using his diagnosis to deploy an approach that (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  39. Generalized Kochen-Specker theorem.Asher Peres - 1996 - Foundations of Physics 26 (6):807-812.
    A generalized Kochen-Specker theorem is proved. It is shown that there exist sets of n projection operators, representing n yes-no questions about a quantum system, such that none of the 2″ possible answers is compatible with sum rules imposed by quantum mechanics. Namely, if a subset of commuting projection operators sums up to a matrix having only even or only odd eigenvalues, the number of “yes” answers ought to he even or odd, respectively. This requirement may lead to contradictions. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  40.  74
    Brouwer’s Fan Theorem as an axiom and as a contrast to Kleene’s alternative.Wim Veldman - 2014 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 53 (5):621-693.
    The paper is a contribution to intuitionistic reverse mathematics. We introduce a formal system called Basic Intuitionistic Mathematics BIM, and then search for statements that are, over BIM, equivalent to Brouwer’s Fan Theorem or to its positive denial, Kleene’s Alternative to the Fan Theorem. The Fan Theorem is true under the intended intuitionistic interpretation and Kleene’s Alternative is true in the model of BIM consisting of the Turing-computable functions. The task of finding equivalents of Kleene’s Alternative is, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  41.  69
    Ramsey's Theorem and Cone Avoidance.Damir D. Dzhafarov & Carl G. Jockusch - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (2):557-578.
    It was shown by Cholak, Jockusch, and Slaman that every computable 2-coloring of pairs admits an infinite low₂ homogeneous set H. We answer a question of the same authors by showing that H may be chosen to satisfy in addition $C\,\not \leqslant _T \,H$, where C is a given noncomputable set. This is shown by analyzing a new and simplified proof of Seetapun's cone avoidance theorem for Ramsey's theorem. We then extend the result to show that every computable (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  42.  19
    The Separability Theorems.John Broome - 1991 - In Weighing Goods: Equality, Uncertainty and Time. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 60–89.
    This chapter sets out the theorems, and presents some examples that show in a rough way how the theorems work. It explains separability precisely, and states the theorems. The chapter starts the work of interpreting the theorems, and also explains the significance of their conclusions from a formal, mathematical point of view. It then discusses a significant assumption that is used in the proofs of the theorems. The published proofs of both the separability theorems depend on an assumption that may (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Gödel's incompleteness theorems, free will and mathematical thought.Solomon Feferman - 2011 - In Richard Swinburne, Free Will and Modern Science. New York: OUP/British Academy.
    The determinism-free will debate is perhaps as old as philosophy itself and has been engaged in from a great variety of points of view including those of scientific, theological, and logical character. This chapter focuses on two arguments from logic. First, there is an argument in support of determinism that dates back to Aristotle, if not farther. It rests on acceptance of the Law of Excluded Middle, according to which every proposition is either true or false, no matter whether the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  44.  16
    The Interpersonal Addition Theorem.John Broome - 1991 - In Weighing Goods: Equality, Uncertainty and Time. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 202–223.
    This chapter explains the interpersonal addition theorem. The theorem leads to two remarkable points. Firstly, it links the aggregation of good across the dimension of people with its aggregation across the dimension of states of nature. The result is that, in favourable circumstances, it links the value of equality in the distribution of good with the value of avoiding risk to good. The chapter also explains this link. The second point is even more remarkable. The theorem shows (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Beth's theorem and deflationism.Timothy Bays - 2009 - Mind 118 (472):1061-1073.
    In 1999, Jeffrey Ketland published a paper which posed a series of technical problems for deflationary theories of truth. Ketland argued that deflationism is incompatible with standard mathematical formalizations of truth, and he claimed that alternate deflationary formalizations are unable to explain some central uses of the truth predicate in mathematics. He also used Beth’s definability theorem to argue that, contrary to deflationists’ claims, the T-schema cannot provide an ‘implicit definition’ of truth. In this article, I want to challenge (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  46. Ramsey’s representation theorem.Richard Bradley - 2004 - Dialectica 58 (4):483–497.
    This paper reconstructs and evaluates the representation theorem presented by Ramsey in his essay 'Truth and Probability', showing how its proof depends on a novel application of Hölder's theory of measurement. I argue that it must be understood as a solution to the problem of measuring partial belief, a solution that in many ways remains unsurpassed. Finally I show that the method it employs may be interpreted in such a way as to avoid a well known objection to it (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  47. Bell's theorem and Bayes' theorem.A. J. M. Garrett - 1990 - Foundations of Physics 20 (12):1475-1512.
    Bell's theorem is expounded as an analysis in Bayesian probabilistic inference. Assume that the result of a spin measurement on a spin-1/2 particle is governed by a variable internal to the particle (local, “hidden”), and examine pairs of particles having zero combined angular momentum so that their internal variables are correlated: knowing something about the internal variable of one tells us something about that of the other. By measuring the spin of one particle, we infer something about its internal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48. Range theorems for quantum probability and entanglement.Itamar Pitowsky - unknown
    We consider the set of all matrices of the form pij = tr[W (Ei ⊗ Fj)] where Ei, Fj are projections on a Hilbert space H, and W is some state on H ⊗ H. We derive the basic properties of this set, compare it with the classical range of probability, and note how its properties may be related to a geometric measures of entanglement.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49.  91
    Montague’s Theorem and Modal Logic.Johannes Stern - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (3):551-570.
    In the present piece we defend predicate approaches to modality, that is approaches that conceive of modal notions as predicates applicable to names of sentences or propositions, against the challenges raised by Montague’s theorem. Montague’s theorem is often taken to show that the most intuitive modal principles lead to paradox if we conceive of the modal notion as a predicate. Following Schweizer (J Philos Logic 21:1–31, 1992) and others we show this interpretation of Montague’s theorem to be (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  50. Generalization of Bell's theorem.Nick Herbert & Jack Karush - 1978 - Foundations of Physics 8 (3-4):313-317.
    A concise proof of Bell's theorem on the necessary nonlocality of any theory which models individual measurements in correlated quantum mechanical systems is presented. A family of inequalities is derived which may be applied to a broad class of correlated systems to test the assumption of locality.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
1 — 50 / 956