Results for 'Peirce, esthetics, normative science, ideal ends'

967 found
Order:
  1.  37
    Charles S. Peirce: On Norms and Ideals.Vincent G. Potter - 1967 - New York: Fordham University Press.
    In Charles S. Peirce: On Norms and Ideals, Potter argues that Peirce's doctrine of the normative sciences is essential to his pragmatism. No part of Peirce's philosophy is bolder than his attempt to establish esthetics, ethics, and logic as the three normative sciences and to argue for the priority of esthetics among the trio. Logic, Potter cites, is normative because it governs thought and aims at truth; ethics is normative because it analyzes the ends to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  2. A estética de Peirce como uma ciência dos fins ideais.James Liszka - 2018 - Cognitio 18 (2):205.
    Argumenta-se aqui que a melhor interpretação da estética de Peirce é como uma ciência normativa de fins ideais. As influências de Peirce neste particular incluem a noção de kalos de Platão, A educação estética do homem de Friedrich Schiller, e a arquitetônica kantiana. Baseada principalmente nos rascunhos de Minute Logic em 1902 e as Palestras de Harvard em 1903, as características essenciais de uma ciência normativa são discutidas e a relação da estética às outras duas ciências normativas da lógica e (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  17
    Relation of normative sciences and the predisposition to act in Peirce's philosophy.José Luiz Zanette - 2023 - Cognitio 24 (1):e63651.
    The article aims to show that Peirce, after realizing the appropriation that James and others made of Pragmatism, taking it far from an ideal of justice and keeping it in the service of a “nauseating utility”, whose principle was that only individual utility, including spiritual well-being, would be the ultimate goal of all practice, he sought a philosophy that would keep logic and science united in a realistic manner with laws that could be metaphysically real. In this way, he (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Peirce’s Imaginative Community: On the Esthetic Grounds of Inquiry.Bernardo Andrade - 2022 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 58 (1):1-21.
    Departing from Anderson’s (2016) suggestion that there are three communities in Peirce’s thought corresponding to his three normative sciences of logic, ethics, and esthetics, I argue that these communities partake in a relationship of dependence similar to that found among the normative sciences. In this way, just as logic relies on ethics which relies on esthetics, so too would a logical community of inquirers rely on an ethical community of love, which would rely on an esthetic community of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  5.  41
    Charles S. Peirce on Norms and Ideals. [REVIEW]B. M. M. - 1968 - Review of Metaphysics 22 (1):151-152.
    The vitality of Peirce's ideas has recently stimulated the writing of several books and articles. This is not strictly a revival, but rather the first systematic presentation to the philosophic public of what Peirce hoped was an architectonic philosophy. While some commentators find Peirce's work to consist merely of brilliant fragments of an ultimate failure, Potter believes that Peirce "has achieved a partial synthesis with gaps and inconsistencies, some of which at least can be remedied." In this book Potter distinguishes (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  22
    An Overview of Charles Peirce on Ethics, Esthetics and the Normative Sciences.James Jakób Liszka - 2022 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 58 (3):219-226.
    Abstract:In Charles Peirce on Ethics, Esthetics and the Normative Sciences, I argue that Peirce was motivated to develop a normative science of ethics because of his growing concern with the corruption of science in the Gilded Age, and the recognition that the pragmatic maxim entailed an amoral instrumentalism. Rather than taking a Kantian approach to resolve the latter issue, he adopts an Aristotelian one, engaging in a search for an ultimate end that could order all other ends. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  18
    Charles Peirce on Ethics, Esthetics and the Normative Sciences: Response to Commentators.James Jakób Liszka - 2022 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 58 (3):253-264.
    Abstract:In my response to the commentators, I agree with Rosa Mayorga that Duns Scotus should be included as an important influence on Peirce's notion of agency, as well as his sense of the highest good. I explain, however, how Peirce's triadic view of agency is an improvement that relates to current debates between moral internalism and externalism. In response to Diana Heney, I defend Peirce's notion of evolutionary love as a form of intergenerational altruism, necessary to any community of inquiry. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  8.  73
    What Makes a Reasoning Sound? C. S. Peirce's Normative Foundation of Logic.Francesco Poggiani - 2012 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 48 (1):31.
    The immediate purpose of this paper is to expound C. S. Peirce's conception of reasoning as he refined it in his mature reflection on the normative sciences and their hierarchical relations (the dependence of logic on ethics and, in turn, that of ethics on esthetics). In order to clarify adequately Peirce's position, however, it is helpful to consider his rejection of Christoph Sigwart's attempt to ground logical soundness in subjective feeling. What is at stake in this debate is nothing (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  18
    The Work of the Normative Sciences: On Liszka's Charles Peirce on Ethics, Esthetics and the Normative Sciences.Diana B. Heney - 2022 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 58 (3):235-242.
    Abstract:This piece offers a reflection on James Liszka's book, Charles Peirece on Ethics, Esthetics, and the Normative Sciences. I consider Liszka's approach to Peirce's writings, especially the Minute Logic and "Evolutionary Love", and explore his extension of Peirce's ethical thought. I conclude that Liszka's work in this volume shows us what reasonableness as self-correction might require of us, and suggests ways in which we can take up the work of the normative sciences.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  13
    Remarks on James Liszka's Charles Peirce on Ethics, Esthetics and the Normative Sciences.Aaron B. Wilson - 2022 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 58 (3):243-252.
    Abstract:Peirce held a convergence theory of moral truth, as James Liszka persuasively argues in Charles Peirce on Ethics, Esthetics, and the Normative Sciences (2021). Here I emphasize: (1) that Peirce's convergence theory follows from the application of the maxim of pragmatism to the concept of moral goodness or rightness; (2) that in connection with Peirce's account of the ethical summum bonum, morally right action can be understood as action that conforms or contributes to the growth of concrete reasonableness; and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  29
    The normative sciences, the sign universe, self-control and rationality–according to Peirce.Bent Sørensen & Torkild Leo Thellefsen - 2010 - Cosmos and History 6 (1):142-152.
    Although Charles S. Peirce, strictly speaking, never formulated a ‘full-blown’ normative theory—a single over-all architectonic system—we believe that there lies within his work a valuable sketch of the ideal for feeling, action, and thought, and how this ideal should be followed, and in connection to this, Peirce offered a model for rational behaviour, including self-control. In the following essay we will try, modestly, to draw a rough outline of this sketch. Firstly, we will focus on the three (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12.  24
    Where There's a Will... There's a Choice: Comments on Liszka's Charles Peirce on Ethics, Esthetics and the Normative Sciences.Rosa Maria Mayorga - 2022 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 58 (3):227-234.
    Abstract:The influence of John Duns Scotus' doctrine of the free will on Charles Peirce's normative theory is proposed in the context of commentaries on James J. Liszka's latest book on Peirce and the normative sciences.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  66
    The normative sciences at work and play.Charles G. Conway - 2008 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 44 (2):pp. 288-311.
    This essay posits that Peirce puts the Normative Sciences implicitly to work at three junctures of his Neglected Argument for the Reality of God (NARG): (1) in the distinguishing of musement from play; (2) in the generation of the Humble Argument via musement; and (3) in the portrayal of the Humble Argument as the first stage of an inquiry into its confirmability. Then, focus shifts to Peirce’s notions of the initiating “play” and the “plausibility” of the God-hypothesis, as a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. (1 other version)Peirce's esthetics: A taste for signs in art.Martin Lefebvre - 2007 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 43 (2):319-344.
    : Is Peirce's esthetic relevant for the philosophy of art—what is usually referred to today as aesthetics? At first glance Peirce's idiosyncratic esthetic seems quite unconcerned with issues of art. Yet a careful examination reveals that this is not the case. Thus, rather than attempt to "apply" Peirce's views to some aspect of the practice or the theory of art (e.g., creativity, historiography of art, style, genre), or even to a particular work of art, my intention is to examine how (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  15. Reconstructing the Normative Sciences: Reconstruindo as Ciências Normativas.Kelly Parker - 2003 - Cognitio 4 (1).
    : From 1902 onward, Peirce viewed esthetics, ethics, and logic as "normative sciences," interconnected spheres of philosophical inquiry that constitute his main work in value theory. The normative sciences provide the basis for a theoretical investigation of questions of value detached from practical interests. Because the normative sciences maintain Peirce's well-known insistence on realism, they set his pragmaticism apart from the more "nominalistic" pragmatism of James and Dewey. The paper aims to clarify Peirce's idea of the (...) sciences, to show how his realism applies in the sphere of value, and to explore his views on the proper relation between theory and practice. The concluding section suggests examples of how we might understand Peirce's rich and innovative concept of normative esthetics.Resumo: De 1902 em diante, Peirce considerava a estética, a ética e a lógica como "ciências normativas", esferas interconexas de inquirição filosófica que constituem seu principal trabalho em teoria do valor. As ciências normativas fornecem a base para uma investigação teorética de questões sobre valor independentes de interesses práticos. Porque as ciências normativas mantém a notória insistência de Peirce no realismo, elas colocam seu pragmaticismo à parte do pragmatismo mais "nominalista" de James e Dewey. O artigo almeja esclarecer a idéia de Peirce das ciências normativas, mostrar como seu realismo se aplica à esfera do valor, e explorar suas visões da própria relação entre ciência e prática. A seção concludente sugere exemplos de como podemos entender o rico e inovador conceito peirciano de estética normativa. (shrink)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16.  19
    Minutes of the Annual General Meeting 2023.Cornelis de Waal, Richard Kenneth Atkins, André De Tienne & Elizabeth Cooke - 2024 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 60 (1):118-128.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Minutes of the Annual General Meeting 2023Cornelis de Waal, Editor-in-Chief, Richard Kenneth Atkins, André De Tienne, Director and General Editor, and Elizabeth Cooke[as approved on January 17, 2024]The Annual General Meeting of the Charles S. Peirce Society was held in conjunction with the Eastern Division Meeting of the APA on January 5, 2023, at the Sheraton Le Centre, Montréal, Quebec. Rosa Maria Mayorga chaired the meeting and called it (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Pragmatic norms in science: making them explicit.María Caamaño Alegre - 2013 - Synthese 190 (15):3227-3246.
    The present work constitutes an attempt to make explicit those pragmatic norms successfully operating in empirical science. I will first comment on the initial presuppositions of the discussion, in particular, on those concerning the instrumental character of scientific practice and the nature of scientific goals. Then I will depict the moderately naturalistic frame in which, from this approach, the pragmatic norms make sense. Third, I will focus on the specificity of the pragmatic norms, making special emphasis on what I regard (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  36
    La comunidad abierta de Peirce a la luz del sentimentalismo y las ciencias normativas.Jorge Alejandro Flórez & Juliana Acosta López de Mesa - 2022 - Estudios de Filosofía (Universidad de Antioquia) 65:177-192.
    Peirce’s idea of an unlimited community has been usually analyzed from its role in science and the normative ideal of truth. However, it is essential to understand the role of the community of inquiry in light of the other normative sciences, aesthetics and ethics, since according to Peirce, any endeavor to know that is not guided by the esthetical ideal of admirable per se should not be considered as proper science, but as a power tool to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  26
    Peirce's Normative Science Revisited.Richard A. Smyth - 2002 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 38 (1/2):283 - 306.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  14
    El lugar de la imaginación en la semiótica de Peirce.Fernando Andacht - 1996 - Anuario Filosófico 29 (56):1265-1290.
    This work aims to re-evaluate the importance of the human imagination in the semiotic of C. S. Peirce. Based on a selection of texts from the Collected Papers (from 1878 to 1903), it attempts to describe the formal relationship between imagination and the controversial notion of semiotic ground. This account of the imagination as a prerequisite for the creation of new beliefs and habits also draws from the Aristotelian notion of "ascending mimesis" and the Peircean normative science of esthetics.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  21.  31
    The Cosmopolitan Peirce: The Impact of his European Experience.Jaime Nubiola - 2014 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 50 (3):425.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:The Cosmopolitan Peirce:The Impact of His European ExperienceJaime Nubiola, Guest EditorKeywordsCharles S. Peirce, Europe, ScienceThe common image of Charles Sanders Peirce as an isolated thinker writing in Arisbe without any contact with the world is not only historically inaccurate, but also makes it difficult to understand some key elements of his philosophy. Charles S. Peirce traveled to Europe on five different occasions. The five trips occurred between the years (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Peirce's Suspended Second, and Art's 'Ethical Phenomenology'.Nat Trimarchi - 2024 - Cosmos and History 20 (2):318-399.
    The fundamental problem for theoretical aesthetics is its inability to account for art’s meaning-value (Trimarchi, 2022). As previously argued, Art’s higher meaning is only found emerging from the artwork’s tacit dimensions, where empirical-historical intentionality is almost completely inconsequential (Trimarchi, 2024b). The latter’s interpretable ‘phenomenology of sequence’ produces a false theorising tendency, disconnecting art from the history of ideas and severing aesthetics from ethics and logic. Art appears ‘infinitely interpretable’, hence entirely subjective. Adapting Arnold’s (2011) actantial processual approach, I show how (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Transcendent Action in the Light of C.S. Peirce's Architectonic System.Piotr Janik - 2007 - Forum Philosophicum: International Journal for Philosophy 12 (1):131-138.
    The article presents the key problems relevant to the issue of “transcendent Action,” as Peirce calls it. The author focuses on the relation between “belief” and the “transcendentals:” unity, truth, goodness, and beauty, in their peculiar Peirceian context. He considers firstly “belief” in the sense of “an original impulse to act consistently, to have a definite intention” and, secondly, “Normative Science, which investigates the universal and necessary laws of the relation of Phenomena to Ends, that is, perhaps, to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24. L'etica del Novecento. Dopo Nietzsche.Sergio Cremaschi - 2005 - Roma RM, Italia: Carocci.
    TWENTIETH-CENTURY ETHICS. AFTER NIETZSCHE -/- Preface This book tells the story of twentieth-century ethics or, in more detail, it reconstructs the history of a discussion on the foundations of ethics which had a start with Nietzsche and Sidgwick, the leading proponents of late-nineteenth-century moral scepticism. During the first half of the century, the prevailing trends tended to exclude the possibility of normative ethics. On the Continent, the trend was to transform ethics into a philosophy of existence whose self-appointed task (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  37
    Charles S. Peirce on Norms and Ideals.Manley Thompson - 1967 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 4 (3):163-168.
  26.  92
    Breve storia dell'etica.Sergio Cremaschi - 2012 - Roma RM, Italia: Carocci.
    The book reconstructs the history of Western ethics. The approach chosen focuses the endless dialectic of moral codes, or different kinds of ethos, moral doctrines that are preached in order to bring about a reform of existing ethos, and ethical theories that have taken shape in the context of controversies about the ethos and moral doctrines as means of justifying or reforming moral doctrines. Such dialectic is what is meant here by the phrase ‘moral traditions’, taken as a name for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  27.  68
    Book Review: Strands of System: The Philosophy of Charles Peirce. [REVIEW]Robert W. Burch - 1995 - Philosophy and Literature 19 (2):384-385.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Strands of System: The Philosophy of Charles PeirceRobert W. BurchStrands of System: The Philosophy of Charles Peirce, by Douglas R. Anderson; xiv & 204pp. West Layfayette, Indiana: Purdue University Press, 1995, $24.95 cloth, $13.95 paper.The Purdue University Press Series in the History of Philosophy was created to “present well-edited basic texts to be used in courses and seminars and for teachers looking for a succinct exposition of the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Vincent G. Potter, S. J., "Charles S. Peirce on Norms and Ideals". [REVIEW]Isabel S. Stearns - 1970 - Man and World 3 (1):136.
  29.  12
    Norms and Ideals in Peirce's Speculative Rhetoric.Ignacio Redondo - 2012 - In Cornelis De Waal & Krzysztof Piotr Skowroński, The normative thought of Charles S. Peirce. New York: Fordham University Press. pp. 214.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. (4 other versions)The Fixation of Belief.C. S. Peirce - 1877 - Popular Science Monthly 12 (1):1-15.
    “Probably Peirce’s best-known works are the first two articles in a series of six that originally were collectively entitled Illustrations of the Logic of Science and published in Popular Science Monthly from November 1877 through August 1878. The first is entitled ‘The Fixation of Belief’ and the second is entitled ‘How to Make Our Ideas Clear.’ In the first of these papers Peirce defended, in a manner consistent with not accepting naive realism, the superiority of the scientific method over other (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   303 citations  
  31. The purposefulness in our thought: A Kantian aid to understanding some essential features of Peirce.Gabriele Gava - 2008 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 44 (4):pp. 699-727.
    This paper aims to shed light on the role played by purposefulness in Peirce’s account of thought by means of a comparison with Kant’s regulative principles. Purposefulness, as an orientation toward an end involved in a thought process, is distinguished from purposiveness, as conformity to an end. Peirce’s architectonic, cosmology, and theory of natural classes are briefly analyzed in light of these concepts. Then, a comparison between Peirce’s esthetic ideal and regulative hopes and Kant’s regulative ideas and principle of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  41
    Peirce on Semiotics as Normative Science.Joshua Ziemkowski - 2006 - Semiotics:26-36.
  33.  21
    The Relation of the Normative Sciences to Peirce's Theory of Inquiry.Thomas V. Curley - 1969 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 5 (2):90 - 106.
  34.  91
    The Pragmatic Maxim and the Normative Sciences: Peirce's Problematical ‘Fourth’ Grade of Clarity.Marco Stango - 2015 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 51 (1):34.
    One of the crucial debates within pragmatism concerns the import of Charles S. Peirce’s “pragmatic maxim.” The aim of this article is to show that Peirce maintains a twofold attitude toward his maxim. I would call this twofold approach ‘problematical,’ not because it is the origin of inconsistencies within Peirce’s thought, but because the collocation and use of the pragmatic maxim constitutes a genuine problem upon which Peirce continued to reflect throughout his life.1 This problem concerns the relationship among semantics, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  35.  31
    Peirce's Analysis of Normative Science.Vincent G. Potter - 1966 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 2 (1):5 - 32.
  36.  1
    From aesthetics to anthropology: ideal beauty in Camper’s (1722–1789) theory of race.Jorge L. García & Xiaoyu Wang - 2025 - History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 47 (1):1-33.
    The problem of providing an objective characterization of human variation have been often intermingled with the questionable task of providing scientific grounds for racism. The source of this confusion lies in the misconception that Petrus Camper’s (1722–1789) theory of the facial line demonstrates the superiority of the Caucasian racial type. In this paper, we argue that the invention of the facial line, far from obeying Euro-centric aesthetic bias, grounded Camper’s neutrality with respect to any claim of racial superiority. This can (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  86
    2014 Presidential Address: Peirce's Idea of Ethics as a Normative Science.James Jakób Liszka - 2014 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 50 (4):459.
    In his later years, Peirce proposed the idea of ethics as a normative science. Is such a thing possible? John Dewey asks “whether scientific propositions about the direction of human conduct, about any situation into which the idea of should enters, are possible; and, if so, of what sort they are and the grounds upon which they rest”. If the meaning of ‘science’ here is taken in its contemporary sense—the way in which physics or biology might be understood—then (...) science implies ethical naturalism, the position that normativity is explainable as a natural property, and capable of empirical study. Russ Shafer-Landau defines it precisely in these terms, where moral properties.. (shrink)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Dual Character Concepts in Social Cognition: Commitments and the Normative Dimension of Conceptual Representation.Guillermo Del Pinal & Kevin Https://Orcidorg Reuter - 2017 - Cognitive Science 41 (S3):477–501.
    The concepts expressed by social role terms such as artist and scientist are unique in that they seem to allow two independent criteria for categorization, one of which is inherently normative. This study presents and tests an account of the content and structure of the normative dimension of these “dual character concepts.” Experiment 1 suggests that the normative dimension of a social role concept represents the commitment to fulfill the idealized basic function associated with the role. Background (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  39.  58
    Book Review:Charles S. Peirce on Norms and Ideals. Charles S. Peirce, Vincent G. Potter. [REVIEW]Manley Thompson - 1969 - Ethics 79 (3):244-.
  40.  14
    Charles Peirce and Modern Science.T. L. Short - 2022 - New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
    In this book, T. L. Short places the notorious difficulties of Peirce's important writings in a more productive light, arguing that he wrote philosophy as a scientist, by framing conjectures intended to be refined or superseded in the inquiries they initiate. He argues also that Peirce held that the methods and metaphysics of modern science are amended as inquiry progresses, making metaphysics a branch of empirical knowledge. Additionally, Short shows that Peirce's scientific work expanded empiricism on empirical grounds, grounding his (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  23
    L’épistémologie sociale de Peirce.Jean-Marie Chevalier & Charles Sanders Peirce - 2015 - Cahiers Philosophiques 142 (3):107-120.
    Le philosophe Charles Peirce a accordé un rôle prépondérant à la communauté des enquêteurs, à la fois comme groupe de chercheurs et comme idéal conduisant vers la vérité. Si Peirce parlait pour sa part de « théorie sociale de la réalité », les trois textes qui suivent – inédits en français, et en anglais pour le dernier – justifient d’y voir une véritable épistémologie sociale. Ils montrent dans quelle mesure la connaissance scientifique, et même commune, trouve son fondement dans une (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  40
    Logic as a Normative Science According to Peirce, normative sciences are the “most purely theoretical of purely theoretical sciences”(CP 1.281, c. 1902, A Detailed Classification of the Sciences). At the same time, he takes logic to be a normative science. These two sentences form a highly interesting pair of assertions. Why is. [REVIEW]Based On Rules - 2012 - In Cornelis De Waal & Krzysztof Piotr Skowroński, The normative thought of Charles S. Peirce. New York: Fordham University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  65
    Normative Science?T. L. Short - 2012 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 48 (3):310-334.
    This article revises a paper I read at the SAAP session in honor of my late friend, Richard Robin. The discussion that followed the paper was much better than the paper, and my present effort, I hope, has benefited from that discussion. What I say here is exploratory. I am more confident of my criticisms of other authors than of the alternative I propose. It is the mere sketch of an idea, its many obvious difficulties blithely ignored. I hope in (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44.  38
    Caring Orientations: The Normative Foundations of the Craft of Management.Matt Statler, Donna Ladkin & Steven S. Taylor - 2015 - Journal of Business Ethics 128 (3):575-584.
    In view of the ethical crises that have proliferated over the last decade, scholars have reflected critically on the ideal of management as a value-neutral, objective science. The alternative conceptualization of management as a craft has been introduced but not yet sufficiently elaborated. In particular, although authors such as Mintzberg and MacIntyre suggest craft as an appropriate alternative to science, neither of them systematically describes what “craft” is, and thus how it could inform an ethical managerial orientation. In this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45.  65
    Peirce's conception of logic as a normative science.Arthur W. Burks - 1943 - Philosophical Review 52 (2):187-193.
  46.  20
    The Problem with Conservative Art: A Critique of Russell Kirk’s Metaphysical Conservatism.Seth Vannatta - 2023 - Philosophies 8 (2):26.
    In this paper I measure the progressive potentiality of art against Russell Kirk’s notion of “normative art”. Kirk argues that good literature cultivates virtue according to a transcendent norm, a law of nature. I interrogate the extent to which this art can be conservative according to Kirk’s own meaning of conservatism and read his own conservatism against itself in an effort to show which of its tenets detrimentally supersede and contradict its others. The criticism of Kirk’s discussion of (...) art makes use of Charles Sanders Peirce’s more sophisticated epistemology, metaphysics, and normative science of aesthetics. Ultimately, Kirk’s conservatism and his position on normative art rely on metaphysical dualism and the gratuitous capacity of intuition. This ends in an unjustified discounting of his principles of variety, imperfectability, prescription, and continuity and their subordination to his principle of transcendence. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  26
    Security as Completeness.Matteo Santarelli - 2017 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 9 (1).
    Peirce’s anti-psychologism hinges on two main assumptions. First, logic and psychology belong to two separate disciplines – respectively, the normative sciences and the experimental sciences. Second, externalism must be understood as a crucial and inescapable epistemological criterion. The introspectionist illusion, according to which individuals have direct and epistemologically flawless access to their own internal states, should be dismissed. As Colapietro (2003) and Calcaterra (2006) observe, Peirce’s standpoint is far different from the Kantian classical account of anti-psychologism. This original take (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  39
    Integrating the parts of the biopsychosocial model.Michael A. Westerman - 2007 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 14 (4):pp. 321-326.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Integrating the Parts of the Biopsychosocial ModelMichael A. Westerman (bio)Keywordsbiopsychosocial approach, pragmatism, participatory framework, functionalist accounts, mind-body-behavior integrationEngel’s (1977, 1980) call for replacing the biomedical model with his biopsychosocial approach pointed in the right direction. Bradley Lewis recognizes this, but argues that Engel’s framework does not provide us with everything we need to develop the biopsychosocial approach. Lewis attempts to add what is missing by reinterpreting Engel as a (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  49. Sellars and Peirce on Truth and the End of Inquiry.Catherine Legg - 2024 - In Carl Sachs, Interpreting Sellars: Critical Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    Despite some notable similarities between the scientific realisms of Sellars and Peirce (such as both being anti-representationalist, and future-directed), in his mature work Science and Metaphysics Sellars explicitly critiqued Peirce’s account of truth, as lacking “an intelligible foundation” (Sellars 1968: vii). In this paper, I explore Sellars’ proposed remedy to Peirce’s purported lack, in his complex and enigmatic account of picturing – a non-discursive ‘mapping’ of the world. I argue that although Sellars’ development of this idea is largely sound, much (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50. Same-tracking real kinds in the social sciences.Theodore Bach - 2022 - Synthese 200 (2):1-26.
    The kinds of real or natural kinds that support explanation and prediction in the social sciences are difficult to identify and track because they change through time, intersect with one another, and they do not always exhibit their properties when one encounters them. As a result, conceptual practices directed at these kinds will often refer in ways that are partial, equivocal, or redundant. To improve this epistemic situation, it is important to employ open-ended classificatory concepts, to understand when different research (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
1 — 50 / 967