Results for 'Tarski’s geometry of solids'

966 found
Order:
  1.  72
    Full development of Tarski's geometry of solids.Rafaŀ Gruszczyński & Andrzej Pietruszczak - 2008 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 14 (4):481-540.
    In this paper we give probably an exhaustive analysis of the geometry of solids which was sketched by Tarski in his short paper [20, 21]. We show that in order to prove theorems stated in [20, 21] one must enrich Tarski's theory with a new postulate asserting that the universe of discourse of the geometry of solids coincides with arbitrary mereological sums of balls, i.e., with solids. We show that once having adopted such a solution (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  2.  20
    A Monadic Second-Order Version of Tarski’s Geometry of Solids.Patrick Barlatier & Richard Dapoigny - forthcoming - Logic and Logical Philosophy:1-45.
    In this paper, we are concerned with the development of a general set theory using the single axiom version of Leśniewski’s mereology. The specification of mereology, and further of Tarski’s geometry of solids will rely on the Calculus of Inductive Constructions (CIC). In the first part, we provide a specification of Leśniewski’s mereology as a model for an atomless Boolean algebra using Clay’s ideas. In the second part, we interpret Leśniewski’s mereology in monadic second-order logic using names (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  15
    On the idea of point-free theories of space based on the example of Tarski’s Geometry of Solids.Grzegorz Sitek - 2022 - Philosophical Discourses 4:157-186.
    The paper presents the main idea of point-free theories of space based on Tarski's system of point-free geometry. First, the general idea of the so-called point-free ontology was discussed, as well as the epistemological and methodological reasons for its adoption. Next, Whitehead's method of extensive abstraction, which is the methodological basis for the construction of point-free theories of space, is presented, and the fundamental concepts of mereology are discussed. The main part of the paper is a discussion of (...) geometry of solids, its postulates and metatheoretical properties. The paper ends with a short description of the contribution of Polish researchers to the development of research on point-free theories of space. (shrink)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. On Tarski's foundations of the geometry of solids.Arianna Betti & Iris Loeb - 2012 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 18 (2):230-260.
    The paper [Tarski: Les fondements de la géométrie des corps, Annales de la Société Polonaise de Mathématiques, pp. 29—34, 1929] is in many ways remarkable. We address three historico-philosophical issues that force themselves upon the reader. First we argue that in this paper Tarski did not live up to his own methodological ideals, but displayed instead a much more pragmatic approach. Second we show that Leśniewski's philosophy and systems do not play the significant role that one may be tempted to (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5. Tarski's system of geometry.Alfred Tarski & Steven Givant - 1999 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 5 (2):175-214.
    This paper is an edited form of a letter written by the two authors (in the name of Tarski) to Wolfram Schwabhäuser around 1978. It contains extended remarks about Tarski's system of foundations for Euclidean geometry, in particular its distinctive features, its historical evolution, the history of specific axioms, the questions of independence of axioms and primitive notions, and versions of the system suitable for the development of 1-dimensional geometry.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  6. Space, points and mereology. On foundations of point-free Euclidean geometry.Rafał Gruszczyński & Andrzej Pietruszczak - 2009 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 18 (2):145-188.
    This article is devoted to the problem of ontological foundations of three-dimensional Euclidean geometry. Starting from Bertrand Russell’s intuitions concerning the sensual world we try to show that it is possible to build a foundation for pure geometry by means of the so called regions of space. It is not our intention to present mathematically developed theory, but rather demonstrate basic assumptions, tools and techniques that are used in construction of systems of point-free geometry and topology by (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  7.  6
    Ernst Mach’s Geometry of Solids.Klaus Robering - 2019 - In Friedrich Stadler (ed.), Ernst Mach – Life, Work, Influence. Springer Verlag.
    The present article first places Mach’s consideration about space and geometry into the context of the discussion of these issues in the nineteenth and early twentieth century and then proposes three interpretations of Mach’s thesis, put forward in chapter XXI of his Knowledge and Error, that the problem of measuring the volumes of material bodies is the origin of geometry. According to the first of these interpretations, Mach’s thesis is an assertion about the historical origin of the science (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  19
    Russell's Theories of Events and Instants from the Perspective of Point-Free Ontologies in the Tradition of the Lvov-Warsaw School.Andrzej Pietruszczak - 2024 - History and Philosophy of Logic 45 (2):161-195.
    We classify two of Bertrand Russell's theories of events within the point-free ontology. The first of such approaches was presented informally by Russell in ‘The World of Physics and the World of Sense’ (Lecture IV in Our Knowledge of the External World of 1914). Based on this theory, Russell sketched ways to construct instants as collections of events. This paper formalizes Russell's approach from 1914. We will also show that in such a reconstructed theory, we obtain all axioms of Russell's (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  43
    A constructive version of Tarski's geometry.Michael Beeson - 2015 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 166 (11):1199-1273.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  17
    (1 other version)Z. Piesyk. Uwagi o aksjomatyce geometrii Tarskiego (Remarks on Tarski's system of axioms of geometry). Roczniki Polskiego Towarzystwa Matematycznego, Series I, vol. 9 (1965), pp. 23–33. [REVIEW]L. W. Szczerba - 1970 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 34 (4):648-648.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  48
    Tarski’s Influence on Computer Science.Solomon Feferman - 2018 - In Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska & Ángel Garrido (eds.), The Lvov-Warsaw School. Past and Present. Cham, Switzerland: Springer- Birkhauser,. pp. 391-404.
    Alfred Tarski’s influence on computer science was indirect but significant in a number of directions and was in certain respects fundamental. Here surveyed is Tarski’s work on the decision procedure for algebra and geometry, the method of elimination of quantifiers, the semantics of formal languages, model-theoretic preservation theorems, and algebraic logic; various connections of each with computer science are taken up.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  74
    The completeness of elementary algebra and geometry.Alfred Tarski - 1967 - Paris,: Centre national de la recherche scientifique, Institut Blaise Pascal.
  13. What are logical notions?Alfred Tarski - 1986 - History and Philosophy of Logic 7 (2):143-154.
    In this manuscript, published here for the first time, Tarski explores the concept of logical notion. He draws on Klein's Erlanger Programm to locate the logical notions of ordinary geometry as those invariant under all transformations of space. Generalizing, he explicates the concept of logical notion of an arbitrary discipline.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   231 citations  
  14. The geometry of standard deontic logic.Alessio Moretti - 2009 - Logica Universalis 3 (1):19-57.
    Whereas geometrical oppositions (logical squares and hexagons) have been so far investigated in many fields of modal logic (both abstract and applied), the oppositional geometrical side of “deontic logic” (the logic of “obligatory”, “forbidden”, “permitted”, . . .) has rather been neglected. Besides the classical “deontic square” (the deontic counterpart of Aristotle’s “logical square”), some interesting attempts have nevertheless been made to deepen the geometrical investigation of the deontic oppositions: Kalinowski (La logique des normes, PUF, Paris, 1972) has proposed a (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  15.  53
    Alfred Tarski: Early Work in Poland – Geometry and Teaching.I. Loeb - 2015 - History and Philosophy of Logic 36 (4):397-399.
    According to the editors, Alfred Tarski: Early work in Poland – Geometry and Teaching has three main goals. First, to publish translations so that all of Alfred Tarski's work will be accessi...
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  19
    Legendre’s Revolution (1794): The Definition of Symmetry in Solid Geometry.Bernard R. Goldstein & Giora Hon - 2005 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 59 (2):107-155.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  17.  59
    The critics of paraconsistency and of many-valuedness and the geometry of oppositions.Alessio Moretti - 2010 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 19 (1-2):63-94.
    In 1995 Slater argued both against Priest’s paraconsistent system LP (1979) and against paraconsistency in general, invoking the fundamental opposition relations ruling the classical logical square. Around 2002 Béziau constructed a double defence of paraconsistency (logical and philosophical), relying, in its philosophical part, on Sesmat’s (1951) and Blanche’s (1953) “logical hexagon”, a geometrical, conservative extension of the logical square, and proposing a new (tridimensional) “solid of opposition”, meant to shed new light on the point raised by Slater. By using n-opposition (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  18.  76
    Tarski's definition of truth and the correspondence theory.Herbert Keuth - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (3):420-430.
    Tarski's definition of truth has rehabilitated the application of the word "true" to sentences of formalized languages. But a correspondence theory according to which a sentence is true if, And only if, It is related in the peculiar way of correspondence to the facts, Is incompatible with tarski's definition. Actually no theory of truth, Which claims to make proper assertions about sentences when calling them true, Is compatible with tarski's definition. Hence they all have to find their own solution to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  19.  13
    A Solid Mistake: An Early State of Caraglio's Diogenes after Parmigianino.Jamie Gabbarelli - 2017 - Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes 80 (1):231-241.
    This paper begins with an assessment of the differences between two states of Jacopo Caraglio's engraved Diogenes after Parmigianino, and between each of those states and Parmigianino's preparatory drawing of the composition. What follows is an attempt to trace both the textual sources and the creative development of this unusual iconographie subject, culminating in a hypothesis about the chronological sequence of the earliest prints of Parmigianino's Diogenes. It is argued that, originally, the artist devised the composition in collaboration with a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  67
    Tarski's conception of logic.Solomon Feferman - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 126 (1-3):5-13.
    Tarski's general conception of logic placed it at the center of all rational thought, and he took its aim to be the creation of a unified conceptual apparatus. In pursuit of this conviction, from his base at the University of California in Berkeley in the post-war years he campaigned vigorously on behalf of logic, locally, nationally and internationally. Though Tarski was ecumenical in his efforts to establish the importance of logic in these various ways, in his own work—even that part (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  21.  9
    Tarski's Definition of Truth.Scott Soames - 1998 - In Understanding Truth. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press USA.
    This chapter provides a detailed explanation of Tarski's definition of truth for formalized languages. It begins by indicating how he conceived the problem, how his criterion of adequacy guarantees that any definition satisfying it introduces a predicate that applies to all and only object‐language truths, and how he approached the technical problem of formulating a definition that would allow him to derive what he regarded as a “partial definition” of truth for each sentence of the object language. Next, the formal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Aristotle on the subject matter of geometry.Richard Pettigrew - 2009 - Phronesis 54 (3):239-260.
    I offer a new interpretation of Aristotle's philosophy of geometry, which he presents in greatest detail in Metaphysics M 3. On my interpretation, Aristotle holds that the points, lines, planes, and solids of geometry belong to the sensible realm, but not in a straightforward way. Rather, by considering Aristotle's second attempt to solve Zeno's Runner Paradox in Book VIII of the Physics , I explain how such objects exist in the sensibles in a special way. I conclude (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  23.  64
    Tarski Alfred. A decision method for elementary algebra and geometry. U. S. Air Force Project Rand, R-109. Prepared for publication by J. C. C. McKinsey. Litho-printed. The Rand Corporation, Santa Monica, California, 1948, iii + 60 pp. [REVIEW]Leon Henkin - 1949 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 14 (3):188-188.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Tarski's Conception of Meaning.Douglas Patterson - 2008 - In New essays on Tarski and philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 157--191.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25.  21
    The geometry of solids in Hilbert spaces.Theodore F. Sullivan - 1973 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 14 (4):575-580.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  7
    Alfred Tarski: Auxiliary Notes on His Legacy.Jan Zygmunt - 2018 - In Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska & Ángel Garrido (eds.), The Lvov-Warsaw School. Past and Present. Cham, Switzerland: Springer- Birkhauser,. pp. 425-455.
    The purpose of this article is to highlight a selected few of Alfred Tarski's career achievements. The choice of these achievements is subjective. Section 1 is a general sketch of his life and work, emphasizing his role as researcher, teacher, organizer and founder of a scientific school. Section 2 discusses his contributions to set theory. Section 3 discusses his contributions to the foundations of geometry and to measure theory. Section 4 looks at his metamathematical work, and especially the decision (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. equality and identity.John Corcoran & Anthony Ramnauth - 2013 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 19 (3):255-256.
    Equality and identity. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 19 (2013) 255-6. (Coauthor: Anthony Ramnauth) Also see https://www.academia.edu/s/a6bf02aaab This article uses ‘equals’ [‘is equal to’] and ‘is’ [‘is identical to’, ‘is one and the same as’] as they are used in ordinary exact English. In a logically perfect language the oxymoron ‘the numbers 3 and 2+1 are the same number’ could not be said. Likewise, ‘the number 3 and the number 2+1 are one number’ is just as bad from a logical point (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Thomas Reid’s Geometry of Visibles.James Van Cleve - 2002 - Philosophical Review 111 (3):373-416.
    In a brief but remarkable section of the Inquiry into the Human Mind, Thomas Reid argued that the visual field is governed by principles other than the familiar theorems of Euclid—theorems we would nowadays classify as Riemannian. On the strength of this section, he has been credited by Norman Daniels, R. B. Angell, and others with discovering non-Euclidean geometry over half a century before the mathematicians—sixty years before Lobachevsky and ninety years before Riemann. I believe that Reid does indeed (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  29.  84
    Hypothesis and Convention in Poincaré’s Defense of Galilei Spacetime.Scott Walter - 2009 - In Michael Heidelberger & Gregor Schiemann (eds.), The Significance of the Hypothetical in Natural Science. De Gruyter. pp. 193-220.
    According to the conventionalist doctrine of space elaborated by the French philosopher-scientist Henri Poincaré in the 1890s, the geometry of physical space is a matter of definition, not of fact. Poincaré's Hertz-inspired view of the role of hypothesis in science guided his interpretation of the theory of relativity (1905), which he found to be in violation of the axiom of free mobility of invariable solids. In a quixotic effort to save the Euclidean geometry that relied on this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30.  55
    Hypothesis and Convention in Poincaré’s Defense of Galilei Spacetime.Scott Walter - 2009 - In Michael Heidelberger & Gregor Schiemann (eds.), The Significance of the Hypothetical in Natural Science. De Gruyter. pp. 193-219.
    According to the conventionalist doctrine of space elaborated by the French philosopher-scientist Henri Poincaré in the 1890s, the geometry of physical space is a matter of definition, not of fact. Poincaré’s Hertz-inspired view of the role of hypothesis in science guided his interpretation of the theory of relativity (1905), which he found to be in violation of the axiom of free mobility of invariable solids. In a quixotic effort to save the Euclidean geometry that relied on this (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31.  52
    Tarski's theory of definition.Wilfrid Hodges - 2008 - In Douglas Patterson (ed.), New essays on Tarski and philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 94.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  32.  41
    The Simplest Axiom System for Plane Hyperbolic Geometry Revisited.Victor Pambuccian - 2011 - Studia Logica 97 (3):347 - 349.
    Using the axiom system provided by Carsten Augat in [1], it is shown that the only 6-variable statement among the axioms of the axiom system for plane hyperbolic geometry (in Tarski's language L B =), we had provided in [3], is superfluous. The resulting axiom system is the simplest possible one, in the sense that each axiom is a statement in prenex form about at most 5 points, and there is no axiom system consisting entirely of at most 4-variable (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  33. Spinoza’s Geometry of Power.Valtteri Viljanen - 2011 - Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    This work examines the unique way in which Benedict de Spinoza combines two significant philosophical principles: that real existence requires causal power and that geometrical objects display exceptionally clearly how things have properties in virtue of their essences. Valtteri Viljanen argues that underlying Spinoza's psychology and ethics is a compelling metaphysical theory according to which each and every genuine thing is an entity of power endowed with an internal structure akin to that of geometrical objects. This allows Spinoza to offer (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  34.  56
    (1 other version)Conventionalism In Reid’s ‘geometry Of Visibles’.Edward Slowik - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (3):467-489.
    The subject of this investigation is the role of conventions in the formulation of Thomas Reid’s theory of the geometry of vision, which he calls the ‘geometry of visibles’. In particular, we will examine the work of N. Daniels and R. Angell who have alleged that, respectively, Reid’s ‘geometry of visibles’ and the geometry of the visual field are non-Euclidean. As will be demonstrated, however, the construction of any geometry of vision is subject to a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  35.  65
    Thomas Reid’s geometry of visibles and the parallel postulate.Giovanni B. Grandi - 2005 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 36 (1):79-103.
    Thomas Reid (1710–1796) presented a two-dimensional geometry of the visual field in his Inquiry into the human mind (1764), whose axioms are different from those of Euclidean plane geometry. Reid’s ‘geometry of visibles’ is the same as the geometry of the surface of the sphere, described without reference to points and lines outside the surface itself. Interpreters of Reid seem to be divided in evaluating the significance of his geometry of visibles in the history of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  36.  43
    On Magari's concept of general calculus: notes on the history of tarski's methodology of deductive sciences.S. Roberto Arpaia - 2006 - History and Philosophy of Logic 27 (1):9-41.
    This paper is an historical study of Tarski's methodology of deductive sciences (in which a logic S is identified with an operator Cn S, called the consequence operator, on a given set of expressions), from its appearance in 1930 to the end of the 1970s, focusing on the work done in the field by Roberto Magari, Piero Mangani and by some of their pupils between 1965 and 1974, and comparing it with the results achieved by Tarski and the Polish school (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. A calculus of individuals based on "connection".Bowman L. Clarke - 1981 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 22 (3):204-218.
    Although Aristotle (Metaphysics, Book IV, Chapter 2) was perhaps the first person to consider the part-whole relationship to be a proper subject matter for philosophic inquiry, the Polish logician Stanislow Lesniewski [15] is generally given credit for the first formal treatment of the subject matter in his Mereology.1 Woodger [30] and Tarski [24] made use of a specific adaptation of Lesniewski's work as a basis for a formal theory of physical things and their parts. The term 'calculus of individuals' was (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  38. Tarski's Definition of Logical Consequence: Historical and Philosophical Aspects.Mario Gomez Torrente - 1996 - Dissertation, Princeton University
    Among the influential contributions of Alfred Tarski to logic and philosophy, and close in importance to his widely applied and discussed definition of truth, one finds his definition of logical consequence for formal languages. Like his definition of truth, Tarski's definition of logical consequence has been widely and fruitfully applied. Unlike the definition of truth, that of logical consequence has been rarely discussed philosophically. The main aim of this dissertation is to offer a thorough discussion of some philosophical issues arising (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  39. Tarski's Theory of Truth.Hartry Field - 1972 - Journal of Philosophy 69 (13):347.
  40.  86
    Key notions of Tarski's methodology of deductive systems.Janusz Czelakowski & Grzegorz Malinowski - 1985 - Studia Logica 44 (4):321 - 351.
    The aim of the article is to outline the historical background and the present state of the methodology of deductive systems invented by Alfred Tarski in the thirties. Key notions of Tarski's methodology are presented and discussed through, the recent development of the original concepts and ideas.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  41. Tarski's Conception of Truth and Its Application to Natural Language.Andrzej Grzegorczyk - 1996 - Dialogue and Universalism 6 (1-2):73-89.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  63
    Tarski's theory of truth and field's solution to the problem of intentionality.Peter Weatherall - 1993 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (3):291 – 304.
  43.  30
    Should Tarski’s Idea of Consequence Operation be Revised?Ryszard Wójcicki - 1999 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 6:231-242.
    Tarski’s papers, in which he examines the idea of a consequence operation Cn,divide into two groups. One of them is formed by the papers that offer an analysis of the general idea of the consequence operation. Resorting to fundamental ideas of logical semantics, Tarski explains what, in his view, it means to say that a formula a of a language L is a logical consequence Cn of a set of formulas X of that language. Under the definition he proposed (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  38
    Tarski’s Theory of the Formal Correctness of Definitions.David Hitchcock - 2024 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 53 (1):181-221.
    In his 1933 monograph on the concept of truth, Alfred Tarski claimed that his definition of truth satisfied “the usual conditions of methodological correctness”, which in a 1935 article he identified as consistency and back-translatability. Following the rules of defining for an axiomatized theory was supposed to ensure satisfaction of the two conditions. But Tarski neither explained the two conditions nor supplied rules of defining for any axiomatized theory. We can make explicit what Tarski understood by consistency and back-translatability, with (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  27
    Tarski and Wittgenstein on Semantics of Geometrical Figures.Ladislav Kvasz - 1999 - Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 6:179-191.
    The aim of this paper is to compare two approaches to semantics, namely the standard Tarskian theory and Wittgenstein’s picture theory of meaning. I will compare them with respect to an unusual subject matter, namely to geometrical pictures. The choice of geometry rather than arithmetic or set theory as the basis, on which this comparison will be made has two reasons. One reason is related to Wittgenstein’s picture theory of meaning. This theory was developed more or less as a (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  50
    On Tarski’s Axiomatization of Mereology.Neil Tennant - 2019 - Studia Logica 107 (6):1089-1102.
    It is shown how Tarski’s 1929 axiomatization of mereology secures the reflexivity of the ‘part of’ relation. This is done with a fusion-abstraction principle that is constructively weaker than that of Tarski; and by means of constructive and relevant reasoning throughout. We place a premium on complete formal rigor of proof. Every step of reasoning is an application of a primitive rule; and the natural deductions themselves can be checked effectively for formal correctness.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  57
    Axiomatizing Changing Conceptions of the Geometric Continuum II: Archimedes-Descartes-Hilbert-Tarski†.John T. Baldwin - 2019 - Philosophia Mathematica 27 (1):33-60.
    In Part I of this paper we argued that the first-order systems HP5 and EG are modest complete descriptive axiomatization of most of Euclidean geometry. In this paper we discuss two further modest complete descriptive axiomatizations: Tarksi’s for Cartesian geometry and new systems for adding $$\pi$$. In contrast we find Hilbert’s full second-order system immodest for geometrical purposes but appropriate as a foundation for mathematical analysis.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48.  49
    Tarski's theory of definability: common themes in descriptive set theory, recursive function theory, classical pure logic, and finite-universe logic.J. W. Addison - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 126 (1-3):77-92.
    Although the theory of definability had many important antecedents—such as the descriptive set theory initiated by the French semi-intuitionists in the early 1900s—the main ideas were first laid out in precise mathematical terms by Alfred Tarski beginning in 1929. We review here the basic notions of languages, explicit definability, and grammatical complexity, and emphasize common themes in the theories of definability for four important languages underlying, respectively, descriptive set theory, recursive function theory, classical pure logic, and finite-universe logic. We review (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  19
    Spinoza’s Geometry of Affective Relations, the Body Politic, and the Social Grammar of Intolerance: A Minimalist Theory of Toleration.Elainy Costa Da Silva & Nythamar de Oliveira - 2022 - Roczniki Filozoficzne 70 (4):237-269.
    In this paper, we set out to show that the relationships between individuals, including the intersubjectivity inherent to the body politic, are also affective relationships, so as to reconstruct Spinoza’s minimalist theory of tolerance. According to Spinoza’s concept of affectivity and bodily life, affection refers to a state of the affected body and implies the presence of the affecting body, while affect refers to the transition from one state to another, taking into account the correlative variation of affective bodies, that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. On Tarski's Theory of Truth.Luis Fernâandez Moreno - 2021 - In Piotr Stalmaszczyk & Mieszko Tałasiewicz (eds.), The Lvov-Warsaw School and Contemporary Philosophy of Language. Boston: BRILL.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 966