Results for 'W. Douglas Seanor'

954 found
Order:
  1.  26
    The influence of the computer upon mathematical notation.W. Douglas Maurer - 1999 - Semiotica 125 (1-3):165-168.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  15
    Analyzing State Autism Private Insurance Mandates for Allied Health Services: A Pilot Study.Henry Carretta, Teal W. Benevides & Megan D. Douglas - 2017 - OTJR: Occupation, Participation and Health 37 (4):218-226.
    Due to the prevalence, severity, and costs associated with autism spectrum disorders, it has become a public health issue. In response, state governments have adopted ASD-specific private insurance mandates requiring coverage of ASD screening, diagnosis, and treatment. Despite rapid uptake of these laws, differences exist in the type and levels of coverage, especially for allied health services including occupational therapy. We piloted a structured legal research methodology to code ASD insurance mandates that impact allied health service provisions. State private insurance (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  35
    The Holy Lake of the Acts of Rāma: An English Translation of Tulasī Dās's RāmacaritamānasaThe Holy Lake of the Acts of Rama: An English Translation of Tulasi Das's Ramacaritamanasa.Norvin Hein, W. Douglas P. Hill, Tulasī Dās & Tulasi Das - 1954 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 74 (1):66.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Criminal Sociology.Enrico Ferri & W. Douglas Morrison - 1896 - International Journal of Ethics 7 (1):110-112.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  16
    The BhagavadgītāThe Bhagavadgita.Ernest Bender & W. Douglas P. Hill - 1969 - Journal of the American Oriental Society 89 (3):666.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  74
    Cases and Commentaries.Louis W. Hodges, Mark Douglas, Rick Kenney, Christine Dellert & Arthur L. Caplan - 2006 - Journal of Mass Media Ethics 21 (2-3):215-228.
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  21
    Repeated isolation experience during the preweanling period: Effects on behavioral ontogeny.Patricia A. Caza, W. Douglas Tynan, Gayle Solheim & Norman E. Spear - 1982 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 20 (2):115-118.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  44
    Hare and critics: essays on moral thinking.Douglas Seanor, N. Fotion & Richard Mervyn Hare (eds.) - 1988 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This collection of thirteen original essays by such well-known philosophers as Thomas Nagel, Peter Singer, J.O. Urmson, David A.J. Richards, James Griffin, R.B. Brandt, John C. Harsanyi, T.M. Scanlon, and others discusses the philosophy of R.M. Hare put forth in his book Moral Thinking, including his thoughts on universalizability, moral psychology, and the role of common-sense moral principles. In addition, Professor Hare responds to his critics with an essay and a detailed, point-by-point criticism.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  9. (1 other version)Hare and Critics: Essays on Moral Thinking.Douglas Seanor & N. Fotion - 1989 - Philosophy 64 (248):269-271.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  10. Hare and its critics.Douglas Seanor & Nicholas Fotion - 1989 - Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 179 (2):267-268.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Rule-Consequentialism and Irrelevant Others: Douglas W. Portmore.Douglas W. Portmore - 2009 - Utilitas 21 (3):368-376.
    In this article, I argue that Brad Hooker's rule-consequentialism implausibly implies that what earthlings are morally required to sacrifice for the sake of helping their less fortunate brethren depends on whether or not other people exist on some distant planet even when these others would be too far away for earthlings to affect.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  12.  32
    Saint John of the Cross and Islam.Miguel Asin Palacios, Howard W. Yoder & Elmer H. Douglas - 1984 - Philosophy East and West 34 (2):232-233.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13. Commonsense Consequentialism: Wherein Morality Meets Rationality.Douglas W. Portmore - 2011 - New York, USA: Oxford University Press USA.
    Commonsense Consequentialism is a book about morality, rationality, and the interconnections between the two. In it, Douglas W. Portmore defends a version of consequentialism that both comports with our commonsense moral intuitions and shares with other consequentialist theories the same compelling teleological conception of practical reasons. Broadly construed, consequentialism is the view that an act's deontic status is determined by how its outcome ranks relative to those of the available alternatives on some evaluative ranking. Portmore argues that outcomes should (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   156 citations  
  14. Review symposium : Douglas W. hands G. C. Archibald Joseph Agassi on S. J. Latsis, ed. method and appraisal in economics. Cambridge: Cambridge university press, 1976. Pp. VIII + 218. $17.50 the methodology of economic research programmes. [REVIEW]Douglas W. Hands - 1979 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 9 (3):293-303.
  15. Welfare, Achievement, and Self-Sacrifice.Douglas W. Portmore - 2008 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 2 (2):1-29.
    Many philosophers hold that the achievement of one's goals can contribute to one's welfare apart from whatever independent contributions that the objects of those goals or the processes by which they are achieved make. Call this the Achievement View, and call those who accept it achievementists. In this paper, I argue that achievementists should accept both that one factor that affects how much the achievement of a goal contributes to one’s welfare is the amount that one has invested in that (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  16. Opting for the Best: Oughts and Options.Douglas W. Portmore - 2019 - New York, NY, USA: Oxford University Press.
    The book concerns what I take to be the least controversial normative principle concerning action: you ought to perform your best option—best, that is, in terms of whatever ultimately matters. The book sets aside the question of what ultimately matters so as to focus on more basic issues, such as: What are our options? Do I have the option of typing out the cure for cancer if that’s what I would in fact do if I had the right intentions at (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  17. Dual-ranking act-consequentialism.Douglas W. Portmore - 2008 - Philosophical Studies 138 (3):409 - 427.
    Dual-ranking act-consequentialism (DRAC) is a rather peculiar version of act-consequentialism. Unlike more traditional forms of act-consequentialism, DRAC doesn’t take the deontic status of an action to be a function of some evaluative ranking of outcomes. Rather, it takes the deontic status of an action to be a function of some non-evaluative ranking that is in turn a function of two auxiliary rankings that are evaluative. I argue that DRAC is promising in that it can accommodate certain features of commonsense morality (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  18.  27
    Children on the reef.Douglas W. Bird & Rebecca Bliege Bird - 2002 - Human Nature 13 (2):269-297.
    Meriam children are active reef-flat collectors. We demonstrate that while foraging on the reef, children are significantly less selective than adults. This difference and the precise nature of children’s selectivity while reef-flat collecting are consistent with a hypothesis that both children and adults attempt to maximize their rate of return while foraging, but in so doing they face different constraints relative to differences in walking speeds while searching. Implications of these results for general arguments about factors that shape differences between (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  19.  57
    Introduction to Kantsequentialism: A Morality of Ends.Douglas W. Portmore - manuscript
    This is the introduction to my book Kantsequentialism: A Morality of Ends.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  62
    Kantsequentialism and Agent-Centered Options.Douglas W. Portmore - manuscript
    In this, the sixth chapter of _Kantsequentialism: A Morality of Ends_, I argue that the duty of beneficence is best understood as a duty both (a) to adopt helping the needy as a serious, major, continually relevant, life-shaping end and (b) to refrain from acting in a way that would manifest one’s failure to do so. What’s more, I argue that Kantsequentialism offers us the best account of whether an act manifests a failure to have adopted helping the needy as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Desire fulfillment and posthumous harm.Douglas W. Portmore - 2007 - American Philosophical Quarterly 44 (1):27 - 38.
    This paper argues that the standard account of posthumous harm is untenable. The standard account presupposes the desire-fulfillment theory of welfare, but I argue that no plausible version of this theory can allow for the possibility of posthumous harm. I argue that there are, at least, two problems with the standard account from the perspective of a desire-fulfillment theorist. First, as most desire-fulfillment theorists acknowledge, the theory must be restricted in such a way that only those desires that pertain to (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  22. (1 other version)Consequentializing.Douglas W. Portmore - forthcoming - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    This is an encyclopedia entry on consequentializing. It explains what consequentializing is, what makes it possible, why someone might be motivated to consequentialize, and how to consequentialize a non-consequentialist theory.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  23.  53
    Kantsequentialism and Agent-Centered Restrictions.Douglas W. Portmore - manuscript
    There are two alternative approaches to accommodating an agent-centered restriction against, say, φ-ing. One approach is to prohibit agents from ever φ-ing. For instance, there could be an absolute prohibition against breaking a promise. The other approach is to require agents both to adopt an end that can be achieved only by their not φ-ing and to give this end priority over that of minimizing overall instances of φ-ing. For instance, each agent could be required both to adopt the end (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Kantsequentialism.Douglas W. Portmore - manuscript
    This is a draft of Chapter Three of the book I'm working on entitled: Kantsequentialism: A Morality of Ends. This chapter outlines my favored moral theory: Kantian consequentialism or Kantsequentialism, for short. This theory takes what's best from both utilitarianism and Kantianism while leaving behind the problems associated with each.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Consequentializing moral theories.Douglas W. Portmore - 2007 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88 (1):39–73.
    To consequentialize a non-consequentialist theory, take whatever considerations that the non-consequentialist theory holds to be relevant to determining the deontic statuses of actions and insist that those considerations are relevant to determining the proper ranking of outcomes. In this way, the consequentialist can produce an ordering of outcomes that when combined with her criterion of rightness yields the same set of deontic verdicts that the non-consequentialist theory yields. In this paper, I argue that any plausible non-consequentialist theory can be consequentialized. (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  26. A Comprehensive Account of Blame: Self-Blame, Non-Moral Blame, and Blame for the Non-Voluntary.Douglas W. Portmore - 2022 - In Andreas Brekke Carlsson (ed.), Self-Blame and Moral Responsibility. New York, USA: Cambridge University Press.
    Blame is multifarious. It can be passionate or dispassionate. It can be expressed or kept private. We blame both the living and the dead. And we blame ourselves as well as others. What’s more, we blame ourselves, not only for our moral failings, but also for our non-moral failings: for our aesthetic bad taste, gustatory self-indulgence, or poor athletic performance. And we blame ourselves both for things over which we exerted agential control (e.g., our voluntary acts) and for things over (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  27. Kantianism versus Utilitarianism.Douglas W. Portmore - manuscript
    I argue that Kantianism and utilitarianism have the opposite strengths and weaknesses. Whereas Kantianism but not utilitarianism accords with our commonsense views about morality, utilitarianism but not Kantianism accords with our commonsense views about action and reasons for action.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Introduction.Douglas W. Portmore - 2020 - In The Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism. New York, USA: Oup Usa. pp. 1-21.
  29.  50
    Goffman, Garfinkel, and games.Douglas W. Maynard - 1991 - Sociological Theory 9 (2):277-279.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  30. Teleological Reasons.Douglas W. Portmore - 2018 - In Daniel Star (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity. New York, NY, United States of America: Oxford University Press.
    I explain what teleological reasons are, distinguish between direct and indirect teleological reasons, and discuss both whether all practical reasons are teleological and whether all teleological reasons are direct.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31.  38
    Basic Speech Acts.Nick Fotion & Douglas Seanor - 2003 - Philosophical Inquiry 25 (1-2):229-243.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  75
    Avoiding Twisted Pixels: Ethical Guidelines for the Appropriate Use and Manipulation of Scientific Digital Images.Douglas W. Cromey - 2010 - Science and Engineering Ethics 16 (4):639-667.
    Digital imaging has provided scientists with new opportunities to acquire and manipulate data using techniques that were difficult or impossible to employ in the past. Because digital images are easier to manipulate than film images, new problems have emerged. One growing concern in the scientific community is that digital images are not being handled with sufficient care. The problem is twofold: (1) the very small, yet troubling, number of intentional falsifications that have been identified, and (2) the more common unintentional, (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  33. Agent-Relative vs. Agent-Neutral.Douglas W. Portmore - 2021 - In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.
    This is a general introduction to the agent-relative/agent-neutral distinction.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  34.  74
    Going to School with Friedrich Nietzsche: The Self in Service of Noble Culture.Douglas W. Yacek - 2013 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 33 (4):391-411.
    To understand Nietzsche’s pedagogy of self-overcoming and to determine its true import for contemporary education, it is necessary to understand Nietzsche’s view of the self that is to be overcome. Nevertheless, previous interpretations of self-overcoming in the journals of the philosophy of education have lacked serious engagement with the Nietzschean self. I devote the first part of this paper to redressing this neglect and arguing for a view of the Nietzschean self as an assemblage of ontologically basic affects which have (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35. Commitment in Dialogue: Basic Concepts of Interpersonal Reasoning.Douglas Neil Walton & Erik C. W. Krabbe - 1995 - Albany, NY, USA: State University of New York Press.
    Develops a logical analysis of dialogue in which two or more parties attempt to advance their own interests. It includes a classification of the major types of dialogues and a discussion of several important informal fallacies.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   408 citations  
  36.  42
    Offering and soliciting collaboration in multi-party disputes among children (and other humans).Douglas W. Maynard - 1986 - Human Studies 9 (2-3):261 - 285.
    This paper has aimed to remedy a neglect of multi-party disputes by addressing how those involved in a two-party argument may collaborate with others who are co-present. Collaboration is a complex phenomenon. In the first place, we have seen that disputes, although initially produced by two parties, do not consist simply of two sides. Rather, given one party's displayed position, stance, or claim, another party can produce opposition by simply aligning against that position or by aligning with a counterposition. This (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  37. Consequentializing agent‐centered restrictions: A Kantsequentialist approach.Douglas W. Portmore - 2023 - Analytic Philosophy 64 (4):443-467.
    There is, on a given moral view, an agent-centered restriction against performing acts of a certain type if that view prohibits agents from performing an instance of that act-type even to prevent two or more others from each performing a morally comparable instance of that act-type. The fact that commonsense morality includes many such agent-centered restrictions has been seen by several philosophers as a decisive objection against consequentialism. Despite this, I argue that agent-centered restrictions are more plausibly accommodated within a (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  38. (1 other version)7 Consequentialism.Douglas W. Portmore - 2011 - In Christian Miller (ed.), Continuum Companion to Ethics. Continuum. pp. 143.
  39. (1 other version)Latitude, Supererogation, and Imperfect Duties.Douglas W. Portmore - 2023 - In David Heyd (ed.), Springer Handbook of Supererogation. Springer.
  40.  18
    Assessing the Dangers of the Next Reductionist Fantasy.Douglas W. Heinrichs - 2022 - Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 29 (1):43-45.
    In this thought-provoking article, a number of very valid and serious ethical concerns are raised about the potential application of research in neuro-circuitry to future treatment devices in clinical psychiatry. Rainey elaborates the basis for his concerns within the framework of a hypothetico-deductive notion of science,, and in his characterization.) From this perspective, the critical source of problems derives from an interposed step C in which “techniques are applied to extract relevant signals from the complicated raw signal.” The resulting characteristics (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Commonsense morality and not being required to maximize the overall good.Douglas W. Portmore - 2000 - Philosophical Studies 100 (2):193-213.
    On commonsense morality, there are two types of situations where an agent is not required to maximize the impersonal good. First, there are those situations where the agent is prohibited from doing so--constraints. Second, there are those situations where the agent is permitted to do so but also has the option of doing something else--options. I argue that there are three possible explanations for the absence of a moral requirement to maximize the impersonal good and that the commonsense moralist must (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  42.  72
    On the sociology of justice: Theoretical notes from an actual jury deliberation.Douglas W. Maynard & John F. Manzo - 1993 - Sociological Theory 11 (2):171-193.
    Despite the venerable place that "justice" occupies in social scientific theory and research, little effort has been made to see how members of society themselves define and use the concept when confronted with determining "what has happened" in some social arena, theorizing about why it happened, and deciding what should ensue. We take an ethnomethodological approach to justice, attempting to recover it as a feature of practical activity or a "phenomenon of order." Our analysis involves an actual videotaped jury deliberation. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43.  84
    Kantian Telicism: Our Legitimate Ends and Their Moral Significance.Douglas W. Portmore - manuscript
    This chapter explains a key tenet of the moral theory that I call Kantsequentialism. That tenet is Kantian Telicism: the view that a subject’s will along with the value of things determine their legitimate ends, which include all their discretionary ends (say, mastering kung fu or traveling the world) as well as the following four obligatory ends: (a) never manifesting a lack of recognition respect for a person, (b) the well-being of every other existing sentient being, (c) the maximization of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. Moral reasons, overridingness, and supererogation.Douglas W. Portmore - manuscript
    In this paper, I present an argument that poses the following dilemma for moral theorists: either (a) reject at least one of three of our most firmly held moral convictions or (b) reject the view that moral reasons are morally overriding, that is, reject the view that moral reasons override non-moral reasons such that even the weakest moral reason defeats the strongest non-moral reason in determining an act’s moral status (e.g., morally permissible). I then argue that we should opt for (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  8
    Cognition on the ground.Douglas W. Maynard - 2006 - Discourse Studies 8 (1):105-115.
    Suggesting that much of social science is still wedded to the ‘dogma of the ghost in the machine,’ I discuss my ethnomethodological and conversation analytic approach to the assembly of cognitive objects. It is important to reverse the usual social psychological metalanguage of mind causing behavior, and see how practices in interaction operate to display cognitive states of participants. Two examples are given: one in regard to the assembly of gestalts, including social actions in talk, and the other concerning the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46. Perform Your Best Option.Douglas W. Portmore - 2013 - Journal of Philosophy 110 (8):436-459.
    We ought to perform our best option—that is, the option that we have most reason, all things considered, to perform. This is perhaps the most fundamental and least controversial of all normative principles concerning action. Yet, it is not, I believe, well understood. For even setting aside questions about what our options are and what our reasons are, there are prior questions concerning how best to formulate the principle. In this paper, I address these questions. One of the more interesting (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  47. Exclusion, still not tracted.Douglas Keaton & Thomas W. Polger - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 171 (1):135-148.
    Karen Bennett has recently articulated and defended a “compatibilist” solution to the causal exclusion problem. Bennett’s solution works by rejecting the exclusion principle on the grounds that even though physical realizers are distinct from the mental states or properties that they realize, they necessarily co-occur such that they fail to satisfy standard accounts of causal over-determination. This is the case, Bennett argues, because the causal background conditions for core realizers being sufficient causes of their effects are identical to the “surround” (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  48. Combining teleological ethics with evaluator relativism: A promising result.Douglas W. Portmore - 2005 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86 (1):95–113.
    Consequentialism is an agent-neutral teleological theory, and deontology is an agent-relative non-teleological theory. I argue that a certain hybrid of the two—namely, non-egoistic agent-relative teleological ethics (NATE)—is quite promising. This hybrid takes what is best from both consequentialism and deontology while leaving behind the problems associated with each. Like consequentialism and unlike deontology, NATE can accommodate the compelling idea that it is always permissible to bring about the best available state of affairs. Yet unlike consequentialism and like deontology, NATE accords (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  49. Agent-Neutral and Agent-Relative.Douglas W. Portmore - 2013 - In J. E. Crimmins & D. C. Long (eds.), Encyclopedia of Utilitarianism. Bloomsbury Academic.
    This is an introduction to the agent-relative/agent-neutral distinction as it pertains to utilitarianism.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Transitivity, Moral Latitude, and Supererogation.Douglas W. Portmore - 2017 - Utilitas 29 (3):286-298.
    On what I take to be the standard account of supererogation, an act is supererogatory if and only if it is morally optional and there is more moral reason to perform it than to perform some permissible alternative. And, on this account, an agent has more moral reason to perform one act than to perform another if and only if she morally ought to prefer how things would be if she were to perform the one to how things would be (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
1 — 50 / 954