Results for 'disjunctive syllogism'

952 found
Order:
  1.  19
    Disjunctive Syllogism without Ex falso.Luiz Carlos Pereira, Edward Hermann Haeusler & Victor Nascimento - 2024 - In Thomas Piecha & Kai F. Wehmeier (eds.), Peter Schroeder-Heister on Proof-Theoretic Semantics. Springer. pp. 193-209.
    The relation between ex falso and disjunctive syllogism, or even the justification of ex falso based on disjunctive syllogism, is an old topic in the history of logic. This old topic reappears in contemporary logic since the introduction of minimal logic by Johansson. The disjunctive syllogism seems to be part of our general non-problematic inferential practices and superficially it does not seem to be related to or to depend on our acceptance of the frequently (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  2.  59
    Disjunction and Disjunctive Syllogism.Peter Milne - 1998 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 28 (1):21 - 32.
    The validity of argument by disjunctive syllogism has been denied by proponents of relevant and paraconsistent logic. DS is stigmatised for its role in inferences — most notably C.I. Lewis's derivation of that fallacy of irrelevance ex falso quodlibet — that involve both it and other rules of inference governing disjunction, or, to speak more precisely, other rules of inference taken to apply to the very same disjunction that obeys DS. In avoiding these inferences the road less travelled (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  79
    The disjunctive syllogism and subjunctive conditionals.A. J. Dale - 1984 - Philosophical Quarterly 34 (135):152-156.
  4.  90
    Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion.S. V. Bhave - 1997 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 (3):398-405.
    Disjunctive Syllogism, that is, the inference from 'not-A or B' and 'A', to 'B' can lead from true premises to a false conclusion if each of the sentences 'A' and 'not-A' is a statement of a partial truth such that affirming one of them amounts to denying the other, without each being the contradictory of the other. Such sentences inevitably occur whenever a situation which for its proper precise description needs the use of expressions such as 'most probably (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5. How disjunctive syllogism can be seen as a fallacy of relevance.Richard Routley - 1981 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 10 (4):144-149.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6. Adding the Disjunctive Syllogism to Relevant Logics Including TW Plus the Contraction and Reductio Rules.Jose M. Mendez, Gemma Robles & Francisco Salto - 2011 - Logique Et Analyse 54 (215):343-358.
  7. The Normalization Theorem for the First-Order Classical Natural Deduction with Disjunctive Syllogism.Seungrak Choi - 2021 - Korean Journal of Logic 2 (24):143-168.
    In the present paper, we prove the normalization theorem and the consistency of the first-order classical logic with disjunctive syllogism. First, we propose the natural deduction system SCD for classical propositional logic having rules for conjunction, implication, negation, and disjunction. The rules for disjunctive syllogism are regarded as the rules for disjunction. After we prove the normalization theorem and the consistency of SCD, we extend SCD to the system SPCD for the first-order classical logic with (...) syllogism. It can be shown that SPCD is conservative extension to SCD. Then, the normalization theorem and the consistency of SPCD are given. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. What Is Wrong with Disjunctive Syllogism?Stephen Read - 1980 - Analysis 41 (2):66 - 70.
  9.  22
    The Distinction Between False Dilemma and False Disjunctive Syllogism.Taeda Tomic - 2021 - Informal Logic 41 (4):607-639.
    Since a clear account of the fallacy of false disjunctive syllogism is missing in the literature, the fallacy is defined and its three types are differentiated after some preliminaries. Section 4 further elaborates the differentia specifica for each of the three types by analyzing relevant argument criticism of each, as well as the related profiles of dialogue. After defining false disjunctive syllogisms, it becomes possible to distinguish between a false dilemma and a false disjunctive syllogism: (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  49
    The validity of disjunctive syllogism is not so easily proved.Chris Mortensen - 1983 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 24 (1):35-40.
  11.  76
    (1 other version)A Routley-Meyer type semantics for relevant logics including B r plus the disjunctive syllogism.Gemma Robles & José M. Méndez - 2010 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (2):139-158.
    Routley-Meyer type ternary relational semantics are defined for relevant logics including Routley and Meyer’s basic logic B plus the reductio rule and the disjunctive syllogism. Standard relevant logics such as E and R (plus γ ) and Ackermann’s logics of ‘strenge Implikation’ Π and Π ′ are among the logics considered.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  12.  35
    Entailment, negation and disjunctive syllogism.G. H. Stephenson - 1975 - Philosophical Studies 27 (6):377 - 387.
  13.  35
    Relevance and disjunctive syllogism.Peter Lavers - 1987 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 29 (1):34-44.
  14.  1
    Small but Significant Errata/Typos in the Paper “The Distinction Between False Dilemma and False Disjunctive Syllogism”.Taeda Tomic - 2025 - Informal Logic 44 (4):683.
    In the paper The Distinction Between False Dilemma and False Disjunctive Syllogism, by Taeda Tomić, Informal Logic vol. 41, No 4 (2021), pp. 607-639, there are typos in Figure 12, on page 630.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. On how not to invalidate disjunctive syllogism.John Woods - 1965 - Logique Et Analyse 32:312-320.
  16.  67
    The emergence of reasoning by the disjunctive syllogism in early childhood.Shilpa Mody & Susan Carey - 2016 - Cognition 154 (C):40-48.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  17.  49
    Relevantism, Material Detachment, and the Disjunctive Syllogism Argument.R. Routley - 1984 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 (2):167 - 188.
    Relevantism, as a matter of definition, rejects classical logic as incorrect and adopts instead a relevant logic as encapsulating correct inference. It rejects classical logic on the grounds that the rule of Material Detachment, from A and not A or B to infer B,, sometimes leads from truth to falsity. Relevantism — although promoted by some relevant logicians, and an integral part of ultralogic — has recently encountered heavy, but interesting, criticism from relevance logicians themselves.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  18.  87
    Relevance logic, classical logic, and disjunctive syllogism.John A. Barker - 1975 - Philosophical Studies 27 (6):361 - 376.
  19.  20
    Affirming a Disjunct.Jason Iuliano - 2018-05-09 - In Robert Arp, Steven Barbone & Michael Bruce (eds.), Bad Arguments. Wiley. pp. 35–41.
    This chapter focuses on one of the common fallacies in Western philosophy called 'affirming a disjunct' (AAD). It presents a few examples of fallacies in arguments caused by an ambiguity in the English word or. Because context makes the meaning clear in everyday usage, we might never have thought about this ambiguity before, but we actually use the word or in two very distinct ways. One type of or is known as “inclusive”, and the other type is known as “exclusive”. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  21
    The Logic of Essentialism: An Interpretation of Aristotle’s Modal Syllogistic.Paul Thom - 1996 - Dordrecht, Boston, and London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
    Aristotle's modal syllogistic has been an object of study ever since the time of Theophrastus; but these studies have been somewhat desultory. Remarkably, in the 1990s several new lines of research have appeared, with series of original publications by Fred Johnson, Richard Patterson and Ulrich Nortmann. Johnson presented for the first time a formal semantics adequate to a de re reading of the apodeictic syllogistic; this was based on a simple intuition linking the modal syllogistic to Aristotelian metaphysics. Nortmann developed (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  21.  51
    When can young children reason about an exclusive disjunction? A follow up to Mody and Carey (2016).Shalini Gautam, Thomas Suddendorf & Jonathan Redshaw - 2021 - Cognition 207 (C):104507.
    Mody and Carey (2016) investigated children's capacity to reason by the disjunctive syllogism by hiding stickers within two pairs of cups (i.e., there is one sticker in cup A or B, and one in cup C or D) and then showing one cup to be empty. They found that children as young as 3 years of age chose the most likely cup (i.e., not A, therefore choose B; and disregard C and D) and suggested that these children were (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  22.  55
    Paraconsistent logics included in Lewis’ S4.Gemma Robles & José M. Méndez - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (3):442-466.
    As is known, a logic S is paraconsistent if the rule ECQ (E contradictione quodlibet) is not a rule of S. Not less well known is the fact that Lewis’ modal logics are not paraconsistent. Actually, Lewis vindicates the validity of ECQ in a famous proof currently known as the “Lewis’ proof” or “Lewis’ argument.” This proof essentially leans on the Disjunctive Syllogism as a rule of inference. The aim of this paper is to define a series of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  23.  27
    The Status of Conditional Syllogism in Syllogistics.Moussa Fatahine & Yagoubi Mahmmoud - 2020 - Studia Humana 9 (1):12-18.
    The form of the conditional syllogism resembles that of the categorical syllogism, while its subject matter is at least a conditional premise, but its conclusion is always conditional conjunctive or disjunctive. This mixed structure to which we apply the rules of the categorical syllogism, is a structure of which Aristotle did not have an idea, and which the Stoics did not conceive, and which the non-Arabian logicians did not know until in modern times. But what we (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. (1 other version)Denying conditionals: Abaelard and the failure of Boethius' account of the hypothetical syllogism.Christopher Martin - 2007 - Vivarium 45 (s 2-3):153-168.
    Boethius' treatise De Hypotheticis Syllogismis provided twelfth-century philosophers with an introduction to the logic of conditional and disjunctive sentences but this work is the only part of the logica vetus which is no longer studied in the twelfth century. In this paper I investigate why interest in Boethius acount of hypothetical syllogisms fell off so quickly. I argue that Boethius' account of compound sentences is not an account of propositions and once a proper notion of propositionality is available the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  14
    “Logical Lantern”: Analogue of the Square of Opposition for Propositions in V.I. Markin’s Universal Language for Traditional Positive Syllogistic Theories.Oksana Cherkashina - 2024 - Logica Universalis 18 (1):35-47.
    In this paper is constructed an analogue of the square of opposition for propositions about relations between two non-empty sets. Unlike the classical square of opposition, the proposed scheme uses all logically possible syllogistic constants, formulated in V.I. Markin’s universal language for traditional positive syllogistic theories. This scheme can be called “Logical lantern”. The basic constants of this language are representing the five basic relations between two non-empty sets: equity, strict inclusion, reversed strict inclusion, intersection and exclusion (considered are only (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  26. Scepticism and animal rationality: the fortune of Chrysippus' dog in the history of western thought.Luciano Floridi - 1997 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 79 (1):27-57.
    This paper employs the metaphor of hunting to discuss intellectual investigation. Drawing on the example of Chrysippus’ dog, an animal whose behaviour supposedly reflects disjunctive syllogistic reasoning, the article traces the history of thought. It concludes by summarizing the contribution of Chrysippus’ dog to the fields of literature, philosophy and the visual arts. -/- .
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  27.  4
    Is False Dilemma Really a Formal Fallacy?Taeda Tomic - 2025 - Informal Logic 44 (4):543-572.
    We argue that Conces’ and Walters’ tool FM2.0 is valuable but does not show that false dilemma is a formal fallacy. The FM2.0 assumes an ambiguous use of the term ‘formal fallacy’, different from how the term is used in logic, and may show that any argument is a formal fallacy. Moreover, the FM2.0 is developed by using one type of false disjunctive syllogism. However, the adequate application of FM2.0 on false dilemma does not lead to an invalid (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Chrysippus' dog as a case study in non-linguistic cognition.Michael Rescorla - 2009 - In Robert W. Lurz (ed.), The Philosophy of Animal Minds. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 52--71.
    I critique an ancient argument for the possibility of non-linguistic deductive inference. The argument, attributed to Chrysippus, describes a dog whose behavior supposedly reflects disjunctive syllogistic reasoning. Drawing on contemporary robotics, I urge that we can equally well explain the dog's behavior by citing probabilistic reasoning over cognitive maps. I then critique various experimentally-based arguments from scientific psychology that echo Chrysippus's anecdotal presentation.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  29.  14
    (1 other version)Relevance Logic.Edwin D. Mares - 2002 - In Dale Jacquette (ed.), A Companion to Philosophical Logic. Malden, MA, USA: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 607–627.
    This chapter contains sections titled: Non‐Sequiturs are Bad The Real Use of Premises Implication From Proof Theory to Semantics Adding Conjunction The Problem of Disjunction Routley and Meyer's Ternary Relation Rules for Disjunction The Semantics of Negation Rules for Negation Disjunctive Syllogism Logics Stronger than R Logics Weaker than R Relevant Logics and Natural Language Conditionals Theory of Properties Summary.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  30.  28
    Paul Ramsey and the Rule of Double Effect.Sanford S. Levy - 1987 - Journal of Religious Ethics 15 (1):59 - 71.
    Paul Ramsey has argued that the rule of double effect is morally significant because of the existence of indeterminate choices between incommensurable values. I interpret his argument as the following disjunctive syllogism. There are two sorts of principles we can appeal to in dealing with indeterminate choices: the rule of double effect and a commensurate reason principle. The second does not work, so we are left with the first. I respond, first, that this argument commits the fallacy of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  31.  35
    Non-Boolean classical relevant logics I.Tore Fjetland Øgaard - 2019 - Synthese (8):1-32.
    Relevant logics have traditionally been viewed as paraconsistent. This paper shows that this view of relevant logics is wrong. It does so by showing forth a logic which extends classical logic, yet satisfies the Entailment Theorem as well as the variable sharing property. In addition it has the same S4-type modal feature as the original relevant logic E as well as the same enthymematical deduction theorem. The variable sharing property was only ever regarded as a necessary property for a logic (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  32. What is Wrong with Cantor's Diagonal Argument?R. T. Brady & P. A. Rush - 2008 - Logique Et Analyse 51 (1):185-219..
    We first consider the entailment logic MC, based on meaning containment, which contains neither the Law of Excluded Middle (LEM) nor the Disjunctive Syllogism (DS). We then argue that the DS may be assumed at least on a similar basis as the assumption of the LEM, which is then justified over a finite domain or for a recursive property over an infinite domain. In the latter case, use is made of Mathematical Induction. We then show that an instance (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  33. The Justification of the Basic Laws of Logic.Gillian Russell - 2015 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 44 (6):793-803.
    Take a correct sequent of formal logic, perhaps a simple logical truth, like the law of excluded middle, or something with premises, like disjunctive syllogism, but basically a claim of the form \.Γ can be empty. If you don’t like my examples, feel free to choose your own, everything I have to say should apply to those as well. Such a sequent attributes the properties of logical truth or logical consequence to a schematic sentence or argument. This paper (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  34.  72
    Boyle, Bentley and Clarke on God, necessity, frigorifick atoms and the void.J. J. MacIntosh - 2001 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 15 (1):33 – 50.
    In this paper I look at two connections between natural philosophy and theology in the late 17th century. In the last quarter of the century there was an interesting development of an argument, earlier but sketchier versions of which can be found in classical philosophers and in Descartes. The manoeuvre in question goes like this: first, prove that there must, necessarily, be a being which is, in some sense of "greater", greater than humans. Second, sketch a proof that such a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  21
    From Explosion to Implosion: A New Justification for the Ex Falso Quodlibet Rule.Ivo Pezlar - forthcoming - Erkenntnis.
    In this paper, we consider the ex falso quodlibet rule (EFQ) as a derived rule and propose a new justification for it based on a rule we call the collapse rule. The collapse rule is a mix between EFQ and disjunctive syllogism (DS). Informally, it says that a choice between a proposition A and ⊥, which is understood as nullary disjunction, is no choice at all and it defaults to A. Thus, we can regard it as capturing the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  28
    Some False Laws of Logic.Valerie Plumwood - 2023 - Australasian Journal of Logic 20 (2):97-137.
    This paper argues that some widely used laws of implication are false, and arguments based upon them invalid. These laws are Exportation, Commutation, (as well as various restricted forms of these), Exported Syllogism and Disjunctive Syllogism. All these laws are false for the same reason – that they license the suppression or replacement in some position of some class of propositions which cannot legitimately be suppressed or replaced. These laws fail to preserve the property of sufficiency of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  37.  65
    The A Priori Meaningfulness Measure and Resolution Theorem Proving.Joseph S. Fulda & Kevin De Fontes - 1989 - Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 1 (3):227-230.
    Demonstrates the validity of the measure presented in "Estimating Semantic Content" on textbook examples using (binary) resolution [a generalization of disjunctive syllogism] theorem proving; the measure is based on logical probability and is the mirror image of logical form; it dates to Popper.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  49
    Begging the question, circularity and epistemic propriety.Dilip K. Basu - 1994 - Argumentation 8 (3):217-226.
    In this paper we shall try to understand what it is to beg the question, and since begging the question is generally believed to be linked with circularity, we shall also explore this relationship. Finally, we shall consider whether certain forms of valid argument can go through smoothly in anepistemio context without begging the question. We shall consider, especially, the claims of the disjunctive syllogism in this regard.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  75
    (1 other version)The Orthologic of Epistemic Modals.Wesley H. Holliday & Matthew Mandelkern - 2024 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 53 (4):831-907.
    Epistemic modals have peculiar logical features that are challenging to account for in a broadly classical framework. For instance, while a sentence of the form $$p\wedge \Diamond \lnot p$$ (‘p, but it might be that not p’) appears to be a contradiction, $$\Diamond \lnot p$$ does not entail $$\lnot p$$, which would follow in classical logic. Likewise, the classical laws of distributivity and disjunctive syllogism fail for epistemic modals. Existing attempts to account for these facts generally either under- (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  40. A plea for KR.Alison Duncan Kerr - 2019 - Synthese 198 (4):3047-3071.
    There is a strong case to be made for thinking that an obscure logic, KR, is better than classical logic and better than any relevant logic. The argument for KR over relevant logics is that KR counts disjunctive syllogism valid, and this is the biggest complaint about relevant logics. The argument for KR over classical logic depends on the normativity of logic and the paradoxes of implication. The paradoxes of implication are taken by relevant logicians to justify relevant (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41.  70
    Non-Boolean classical relevant logics II: Classicality through truth-constants.Tore Fjetland Øgaard - 2021 - Synthese (3-4):1-33.
    This paper gives an account of Anderson and Belnap’s selection criteria for an adequate theory of entailment. The criteria are grouped into three categories: criteria pertaining to modality, those pertaining to relevance, and those related to expressive strength. The leitmotif of both this paper and its prequel is the relevant legitimacy of disjunctive syllogism. Relevant logics are commonly held to be paraconsistent logics. It is shown in this paper, however, that both E and R can be extended to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  74
    What Follows from the Impossible: Everything or Nothing? (An Interpretation of the ‘Avranches Text’ and the Ars Meliduna).Wolfgang Lenzen - 2021 - History and Philosophy of Logic 43 (4):309-331.
    One of the main controversies of the Logic Schools of the 12th century centered on the question: What follows from the impossible? In this paper arguments for two diametrically opposed positions are examined. The author of the ‘Avranches Text’ who probably belonged to the school of the Parvipontani defended the view that from an impossible proposition everything follows (‘Ex impossibili quodlibet’). In particular he developed a proof to show that by means of so-called ‘disjunctive syllogism’ any arbitrary proposition (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43. Logic for dogs.Andrew Aberdein - 2008 - In Steven D. Hales (ed.), What Philosophy Can Tell You about Your Dog. Open Court. pp. 167-181.
    Imagine a dog tracing a scent to a crossroads, sniffing all but one of the exits, and then proceeding down the last without further examination. According to Sextus Empiricus, Chrysippus argued that the dog effectively employs disjunctive syllogism, concluding that since the quarry left no trace on the other paths, it must have taken the last. The story has been retold many times, with at least four different morals: (1) dogs use logic, so they are as clever as (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44.  48
    The Fallacy of Begging the Question: A Reply to Barker.David H. Sanford - 1977 - Dialogue 16 (3):485-498.
    According to John A Barker, whether an argument begs the question is purely a matter of logical form. According to me, it is also a matter of epistemic conditions; some arguments which beg the question in some contexts need not beg the question in every context. I point out difficulties in Barker's treatment and defend my own views against some of his criticisms. In the concluding section, "Alleged difficulties with disjunctive syllogism," I defend the validity of disjunctive (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  45.  42
    A non-transitive relevant implication corresponding to classical logic consequence.Peter Verdée, Inge De Bal & Aleksandra Samonek - 2019 - Australasian Journal of Logic 16 (2):10-40.
    In this paper we first develop a logic independent account of relevant implication. We propose a stipulative denition of what it means for a multiset of premises to relevantly L-imply a multiset of conclusions, where L is a Tarskian consequence relation: the premises relevantly imply the conclusions iff there is an abstraction of the pair such that the abstracted premises L-imply the abstracted conclusions and none of the abstracted premises or the abstracted conclusions can be omitted while still maintaining valid (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  73
    On permutation in simplified semantics.Greg Restall & Tony Roy - 2009 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 38 (3):333 - 341.
    This note explains an error in Restall’s ‘Simplified Semantics for Relevant Logics (and some of their rivals)’ (Restall, J Philos Logic 22(5):481–511, 1993 ) concerning the modelling conditions for the axioms of assertion A → (( A → B ) → B ) (there called c 6) and permutation ( A → ( B → C )) → ( B → ( A → C )) (there called c 7). We show that the modelling conditions for assertion and permutation proposed (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  47.  57
    Do nonlinguistic creatures deploy mental symbols for logical connectives in reasoning?Susan Carey - 2023 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 46:e267.
    Some nonlinguistic systems of representation display some of the six features of a language-of-thought (LoT) delineated by Quilty-Dunn et al. But they conjecture something stronger: That all six features cooccur homeostatically in nonlinguistic thought. Here I argue that there is no good evidence for nonlinguistic deductive reasoning involving the disjunctive syllogism. Animals and prelinguistic children probably do not make logical inferences.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48. Minimal inconsistency-tolerant logics: a quantitative approach.Christian Strasser & Sanderson Molick - forthcoming - Australasian Journal of Logic.
    In order to reason in a non-trivializing way with contradictions, para- consistent logics reject some classically valid inferences. As a way of re- covering some of these inferences, Graham Priest ([Priest, 1991]) proposed to nonmonotonically strengthen the Logic of Paradox by allowing the se- lection of “less inconsistent” models via a comparison of their respective inconsistent parts. This move recaptures a good portion of classical logic in that it does not block, e.g., disjunctive syllogism, unless it is applied (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  12
    Relevance in Reasoning.Neil Tennant - 2005 - In Stewart Shapiro (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
    This chapter explains an approach to relevantization of logical reasoning that seeks to maximize epistemic gain. It does so by retaining Disjunctive Syllogism and making admissible only a restricted rule of Cut. The virtue of this approach is that one can show that the resulting relevant logic is adequate for mathematics and science. In the course of explaining this kind of relevant logic, we compare and contrast our approach with the Anderson-Belnap tradition.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  50. A Routley-Meyer semantics for Ackermann's logics of “strenge implication”.José M. Méndez - 2009 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 18 (3-4):191-219.
    The aim of this paper is to provide a Routley-Meyer semantics for Ackermann’s logics of “strenge Implikation” Π ′ and Π ′′ . Besides the Disjunctive Syllogism, this semantics validates the rules Necessitation and Assertion. Strong completeness theorems for Π ′ and Π ′′ are proved. A brief discussion on Π ′ , Π ′′ and paraconsistency is included.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 952