Results for ' Maximize Presupposition! '

966 found
Order:
  1. Maximize Presupposition! and local contexts.Raj Singh - 2011 - Natural Language Semantics 19 (2):149-168.
    Maximize Presupposition! is an economy condition that adjudicates between contextually equivalent competing structures. Building on data discovered by O. Percus, I will argue that the constraint is checked in the local contexts of embedded constituents. I will argue that this architecture leads to a general solution to the problem of antipresupposition projection, and also allows I. Heim’s ‘Novelty/Familiarity Condition’ to be eliminated as a constraint on operations of context change.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  2. Maximize Presupposition and Gricean reasoning.Philippe Schlenker - 2012 - Natural Language Semantics 20 (4):391-429.
    Recent semantic research has made increasing use of a principle, Maximize Presupposition, which requires that under certain circumstances the strongest possible presupposition be marked. This principle is generally taken to be irreducible to standard Gricean reasoning because the forms that are in competition have the same assertive content. We suggest, however, that Maximize Presupposition might be reducible to the theory of scalar implicatures. (i)First, we consider a special case: the speaker utters a sentence with a presupposition p which (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  3. (1 other version)Maximize presupposition and two types of definite competitors.Luis Alonso-Ovallea - unknown
    Indefinites impose an anti-uniqueness condition on their domain of quantification. The sentence in (1), for instance, cannot be felicitously uttered when it is taken for granted that John has only one friend (Hawkins 1978, 1991, Heim 1991).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4.  22
    Children’s and Adults’ Sensitivity to Gricean Maxims and to the Maximize Presupposition Principle.Francesca Panzeri & Francesca Foppolo - 2021 - Frontiers in Psychology 12.
    Up to age 5, children are known to experience difficulties in the derivation of implicitly conveyed content, sticking to literally true, even if underinformative, interpretation of sentences. The computation of implicated meanings is connected to the (apparent or manifest) violation of Gricean conversational maxims. We present a study that tests unmotivated violations of the maxims of Quantity, Relevance, and Manner and of the Maximize Presupposition principle, with a Truth Value Judgment task with three options of response. We tested pre-schoolers (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  34
    Les apories sur l’existence du temps et du maintenant.Maxime Vachon - 2015 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 71 (1):133-149.
    Maxime Vachon | Résumé : Le but de cet article est de mettre en lumière les apories sur l’existence du temps et sur le maintenant telles que présentées dans la première partie du chapitre IV, 10 de la Physique d’Aristote par une traduction et un commentaire de ce texte. Plus précisément, l’auteur tente de dégager les présupposés philosophiques des apories en question, notamment à partir des occurrences du verbe histanai et de ses composés. |: The aim of this article is (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  8
    The normative turn of perceptual intentionality and its metaphysical consequences (or why Husserl was neither a disjunctivist nor a conjunctivist).Maxime Doyon - 2021 - In Hanne Jacobs, The Husserlian Mind. New Yor, NY: Routledge. pp. 172-183.
    Since its first formulation in the 1980s, the disjunctivist theory has changed the way philosophers think about perception. Fundamentally, the disjunctivist view is a negative metaphysical thesis about the nature of perceptual experience: it is based on a refutation of the so-called “common kind claim,” that is to say, the claim that perceptions, illusions, and hallucinations are conscious experiences of the same fundamental kind. Given the importance granted to perceptual experience in the phenomenological tradition, a few commentators have, in recent (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  38
    Minimal presuppositions and maximal metaphysics.J. W. N. Watkins - 1978 - Mind 87 (346):195-209.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  8.  98
    Reason and Maximization.David Gauthier - 1975 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 4 (3):411 - 433.
    Economic man seeks to maximize utility. The rationality of economic man is assumed, and is identified with the aim of utility-maximization. But may rational activity correctly be identified with maximizing activity? The object of this essay is to explore, and in part to answer, this question.This is not an issue solely, or perhaps even primarily, about the presuppositions of economics. The two great modern schools of moral and political thought in the English-speaking world, the contractarian and the utilitarian, identify (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  9.  63
    Presuppositions and Relevance.Mandy Simons - 2004 - In Zoltan Gendler Szabo, Semantics Versus Pragmatics. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK. pp. 329--255.
    Recall Grice’s well-worn example from Logic and Conversation about Smith, his girlfriend, and his trips to New York: (1) A: Smith doesn’t seem to have a girlfriend these days. B: He has been paying a lot of visits to NY recently. Grice says that in this dialogue, B implicates that Smith has, or may have, a girlfriend in New York. But in saying this, Grice under-describes his own example. For this proposition alone does not suffice to satisfy the requirements of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  10. Subclausal Local Contexts.Kyle H. Blumberg & Amir Anvari - forthcoming - Journal of Semantics.
    One of the central topics in semantic theory over the last few decades concerns the nature of local contexts. Recently, theorists have tried to develop general, non-stipulative accounts of local contexts (Schlenker, 2009; Ingason, 2016; Mandelkern & Romoli, 2017a). In this paper, we contribute to this literature by drawing attention to the local contexts of subclausal expressions. More specifically, we focus on the local contexts of quantificational determiners, e.g. `all', `both', etc. Our central tool for probing the local contexts of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11.  89
    The epistemics of presupposition projection.Jan van Eijck & Christina Unger - 2007 - In Dekker Aloni, Proceedings of the Sixteenth Amsterdam Colloquium. pp. 235-240.
    We carry out the Karttunen-Stalnaker pragmatic account of presupposition projection within a state-of-the art version of dynamic epistemic logic. It turns out that the basic projection facts can all be derived from a Gricean maxim ‘be informative’. This sheds light on a recent controversy on the appropriateness of dynamic semantics as a tool for analysing presupposition.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12. Grammatical marking of givenness.Ivona Kučerová - 2012 - Natural Language Semantics 20 (1):1-30.
    Schwarzschild (Nat Lang Semant 7:141–177, 1999)’s account of givenness elaborates a notion of complementarity of givenness and focus in an intricate way: while givenness is semantically interpreted, focus is grammatically marked. It has been noticed, however, that under certain circumstances givenness in English is grammatically marked as well. Movement plays a role in this process. This paper provides further evidence for givenness marking. I present a case study of three Slavic languages (Czech, Russian, and Serbo-Croatian) in which givenness is always (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  29
    Paul Ricœur’s Search for a Just Community. The Phenomenological Presupposition of a Life “with and for others”.Marc De Leeuw - 2018 - Études Ricoeuriennes / Ricoeur Studies 8 (2):46-54.
    The aim of this article is to examine how Ricœur’s critique of Husserl’s and Levinas’s notions of intersubjectivity informs his own alternative conceptualization of the intra- and interpersonal as a complex intertwining of moral selfhood and a just community. My first assumption is that law, as a prescriptive intervention in the social structure of our communal life, presupposes a phenomenology of our “being with others”. My second assumption is that Ricœur’s entire philosophical anthropology, and specifically his ideas on ethics, legality (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Self-interest, autonomy, and the presuppositions of decision theory.Mariam Thalos - 1997 - American Philosophical Quarterly 34 (2):287 - 297.
    the voluntary actions of such beings cannot be covered by causal laws. Decision theorists, accepting the premise of this argument, appeal instead to noncausal laws predicated on principles of success—oriented action, and use these laws to produce substantive and testable predictions about large—scale human behavior. The primary directive of success-oriented action is maximization of some valuable quantity. Many economists and social scientists use the principles of decision theory to explain social and economic phenomena, while many political philosophers use them to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  22
    Modal tense: if and wish.Paul Crowley - 2024 - Linguistics and Philosophy 47 (3):401-443.
    This paper is concerned with uses of certain morphemes, most notably the past, to represent meanings of distance from reality in modal expressions. This class of morphology has been identified with the names subjunctive, fake tense, fake past, modal past and is referred to here as X-marking, after von Fintel and Iatridou (Linguist Philos, 2020). X-marking has been most studied in the context of English conditionals however, it is well-known that the morphology is observed in many non-English languages and can (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  41
    Past time reference in a language with optional tense.M. Ryan Bochnak - 2016 - Linguistics and Philosophy 39 (4):247-294.
    In this paper, I analyze the verbal suffix -uŋil in Washo as an optional past tense. It is optional in the sense that it is not part of a paradigm of tenses, and morphologically tenseless clauses are also compatible with past time reference. Specifically, I claim that -uŋil is the morphological exponent of a tense feature [past], which presupposes that the reference time of the clause, denoted by a temporal pronoun, precedes the evaluation time. Meanwhile, morphologically tenseless clauses lack a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  17.  98
    Beyond the past, present, and future: towards the semantics of ‘graded tense’ in Gĩkũyũ. [REVIEW]Seth Cable - 2013 - Natural Language Semantics 21 (3):219-276.
    In recent years, our understanding of how tense systems vary across languages has been greatly advanced by formal semantic study of languages exhibiting fewer tense categories than the three commonly found in European languages. However, it has also often been reported that languages can sometimes distinguish more than three tenses. Such languages appear to have ‘graded tense’ systems, where the tense morphology serves to track how far into the past or future a reported event occurs. This paper presents a formal (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  18. The Social Life of Slurs.Geoff Nunberg - 2018 - In Daniel Fogal, Daniel W. Harris & Matt Moss, New Work on Speech Acts. Oxford University Press. pp. 237–295.
    The words we call slurs are just plain vanilla descriptions like ‘cowboy’ and ‘coat hanger’. They don't semantically convey any disparagement of their referents, whether as content, conventional implicature, presupposition, “coloring” or mode of presentation. What distinguishes 'kraut' and 'German' is metadata rather than meaning: the former is the conventional description for Germans among Germanophobes when they are speaking in that capacity, in the same way 'mad' is the conventional expression that some teenagers use as an intensifier when they’re emphasizing (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   93 citations  
  19. The Projection Problem for Predicates of Taste.Dilip Ninan - 2020 - Semantics and Linguistic Theory 30:753-778.
    Utterances of simple sentences containing taste predicates (e.g. "delicious", "fun", "frightening") typically imply that the speaker has had a particular sort of first-hand experience with the object of predication. For example, an utterance of "The carrot cake is delicious" would typically imply that the speaker had actually tasted the cake in question, and is not, for example, merely basing her judgment on the testimony of others. According to one approach, this acquaintance inference is essentially an implicature, one generated by the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  20.  28
    The Semantics-Pragmatics Interface.Philippe Schlenker - 2016 - In Maria Aloni & Paul Dekker, Formal Semantics. Cambridge University Press. pp. 664 - 727.
    The informational content conveyed by utterances has two sources:meaning as it is encoded in words and rules of semantic composition (often called literal or semantic meaning) and further inferences that may be obtained by reasoning on the speaker's motives (the conjunction of these inferences with the literal meaning is often called the strengthened or pragmatic meaning of the sentence). While in simple cases the difference can seem obvious enough, in general this is not so, and the investigation of the semantics–pragmatics (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  21. How To Precisify Quantifiers.Arvid Båve - 2011 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 40 (1):103-111.
    I here argue that Ted Sider's indeterminacy argument against vagueness in quantifiers fails. Sider claims that vagueness entails precisifications, but holds that precisifications of quantifiers cannot be coherently described: they will either deliver the wrong logical form to quantified sentences, or involve a presupposition that contradicts the claim that the quantifier is vague. Assuming (as does Sider) that the “connectedness” of objects can be precisely defined, I present a counter-example to Sider's contention, consisting of a partial, implicit definition of the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  22.  11
    Descriptions in Context.Cleo A. Condoravdi - 1997 - Routledge.
    4.2 Contextually Salient Functions -- 4.3 Negative Contextual Sensitivity -- 4.4 Strong and Weak Novelty and NP Strength -- 4.5 Existential Force and Strong vs. Weak Novelty -- 4.6 Maximality -- 4.7 Consequences of the Existential Presupposition -- 4.7.1 Positive Contextual Sensitivity -- 4.7.2 Dependent Functional Reading -- 5 Conclusion -- Notes -- BIBLIOGRAPHY -- INDEX.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  23. Better vaguely right than precisely wrong in effective altruism: the problem of marginalism.Nicolas Côté & Bastian Steuwer - 2023 - Economics and Philosophy 39 (1):152-169.
    Effective altruism (EA) requires that when we donate to charity, we maximize the beneficial impact of our donations. While we are in broad sympathy with EA, we raise a practical problem for EA, which is that there is a crucial empirical presupposition implicit in its charity assessment methods which is false in many contexts. This is the presupposition that the magnitude of the benefits (or harms) generated by some charity vary continuously in the scale of the intervention performed. We (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Hume e as bases científicas da tese de que não há acaso no mundo.Silvio Seno Chibeni - 2012 - Principia: An International Journal of Epistemology 16 (2):229-254.
    Both in the Treatise of Human Nature and in the Enquiry concerning Human Understanding, Hume defends that “there is no chance in the world”, and that “what the vulgar call chance is nothing but a secret and conceal’d cause”. This view plays a crucial role in Hume’s influential analysis of free will and moral responsibility. It functions also as a central presupposition in his discussion of miracles. However, Hume himself argued convincingly that the “maxim of causality”, according to which “whatever (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  14
    Natural Law, Impartialism, and Others’ Good.Mark C. Murphy - 1996 - The Thomist 60 (1):53-80.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:NATURAL LAW, IMPARTIALISM, AND OTHERS' GOOD* MARK C. MURPHY Georgetown University Washington, D.C. The title of a recent article by Henry Veatch and Joseph Rautenberg asks "Does the Grisez-Finnis-Boyle Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?'"; the answer that the text of that article produces is, unsurprisingly, "Yes." Veatch and Rautenberg argue that despite superficial similarities between the moral theory defended by Germain Grisez, John Finnis, and Joseph Boyle and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  62
    Intentional action and pure causality: A critical discussion of some central conceptual distinctions in the work of Jon Elster.Tore Sandven - 1995 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 25 (3):286-317.
    This article discusses fundamental problems in "rational choice theory," as outlined by Jon Elster. Elster's discussion of why institutions may not be said to act shows his fundamental presupposition that only "monolithic," unitary entities are capable of action. This is, for him, a reason why only individual human beings may be said to act. Furthermore, human beings may be said to act only insofar as they "maximize" (their "utility") on the basis of a unitary, complete, consistent "preference structure." All (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  27.  14
    Insecurity, Conformity and Community: James Coleman's Latent Theoretical Model of Action.Gad Yair - 2008 - European Journal of Social Theory 11 (1):51-70.
    James S. Coleman was the major proponent of rational choice theory. This article challenges the traditional reading of his work by showing that under the explicit theory of rational choice lay a latent non-rational theory of action. The article shows that instead of rationality, Coleman's psychological starting point was existential insecurity; that instead of the alleged mechanism of the maximization of utility, actors choose to conform to peer values and norms in order to alleviate insecurity; and that the optimal setting (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. The Rule of the Mathematical: Wittgenstein's Later Discussions.Juliet H. Floyd - 1990 - Dissertation, Harvard University
    If we consider Wittgenstein's career as a whole, it appears that he wrote more on the philosophy of logic and mathematics than any other subject. Yet his writings on these subjects have exerted little influence. Indeed, the tide of response to Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, which contains the bulk of his latest views of mathematics, has been for the most part overwhelmingly negative. Given his later emphasis on the context-bound character of language, mathematics and logic--where language apparently operates (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  33
    On the scalar antonymy of only and even.Yael Greenberg - 2022 - Natural Language Semantics 30 (4):415-452.
    An old observation about the focus sensitive particles _only_ and _even_ is that they are in some sense scalar antonyms. We examine three schematic proposals raised in the literature to capture this observation, namely that _only_ vs. _even_ presuppose that the proposition denoted by their prejacent, _p_, is lower vs. higher, respectively _(A)_ than _what is EXPECTED/the default STANDARD_ ( the ‘mirative/evaluative antonymy’ view ), _(B)_ than _SOME (salient) alternative_ in the set of contextually relevant focus alternatives, C, ( the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Insufficient Reason: An Interpretation and Critique of Kant's Categorical Imperative.Andrew Burkitt Johnson - 2001 - Dissertation, The University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill
    Kant's moral theory, along with Utilitarianism and Virtue Ethics, is one of the three leading moral theories in contemporary Western moral philosophy. I argue in this dissertation, however, that Kant's moral theory suffers from deeper flaws than its proponents have acknowledged---flaws that render it untenable. But a great deal of interpretative argument must be done before this critique can be compelling, since every critique rests on interpretative presuppositions that are liable to be questioned. Hence the dissertation also spends significant time (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  55
    The first formalized proof of the indestructibility of a subsistent form.Edward Nieznański - 2013 - Studies in East European Thought 65 (1-2):65-73.
    The article presents a formalization of Thomas Aquinas proof for the indestructibility of the human soul. The author of the formalization—the first of its kind in the history of philosophy—is Father Joseph Maria Bocheński. The presentation involves no more than updating the logical symbolism used and accompanies the logical formulae with ordinary language paraphrases in order to ease the reader’s understanding of the formulae. “The fundamental idea of the Thomist proof is of utmost simplicity: things which are destructible are destructible (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  22
    Additivity, scalarity and Mandarin Universal wh’s.Mingming Liu - 2023 - Natural Language Semantics 31 (2):179-218.
    This paper offers a compositional analysis of Mandarin universal _wh_’s in construction with an additive/scalar adverb _ye_ ‘also/even’. In the analysis, universal force is derived from exhaustification of the subdomain alternatives activated by _wh_-items under stress, and the tendency of _wh_-_ye_ to appear in negative sentences is explained by the interaction between _ye_ and domain widening. Specifically, the _ye_ in _wh_-_ye_ is argued to be a scalar _ye_ imposing a total order presupposition on its associated set of alternatives. In _wh_-_ye_ (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. A New Negentropic Subject: Reviewing Michel Serres' Biogea.A. Staley Groves - 2012 - Continent 2 (2):155-158.
    continent. 2.2 (2012): 155–158 Michel Serres. Biogea . Trans. Randolph Burks. Minneapolis: Univocal Publishing. 2012. 200 pp. | ISBN 9781937561086 | $22.95 Conveying to potential readers the significance of a book puts me at risk of glad handing. It’s not in my interest to laud the undeserving, especially on the pages of this journal. This is not a sales pitch, but rather an affirmation of a necessary work on very troubled terms: human, earth, nature, and the problematic world we made. (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  84
    Counterparts and Qualities.Manfred Kupffer - unknown
    David Lewis proposed to deal with the semantics of sentences that state what is possible for an individual in terms of possible individuals that are in ways the first individual might have been, so called counterparts of the individual. In this book, I defend counterpart semantics as an approach to the semantics of modality and natural language semantics in particular. Counterpart semantics has a rival, the standard Kripkean semantics that deals with the same sentences in terms of an accessibility relation (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35. "We sing our law, is that still TEK?": Traditional ecological knowledge and can the west come to know?John J. Bradley & Stephen Johnson - unknown
    Throughout history, anthropologists have confronted a number of uncomfortable truths around the supposed nature of reality. The anthropological maxim, "through the study of others we learn more about ourselves" has been sorely tested en route. Arguably, this challenge reached culmination during the 1970s and 80s, with several prominent social commentators from Geertz to Clifford suggesting that anthropologists had, in both past and present, been much more concerned with the study of 'others' than of 'ourselves'. In essence, this reflexive critique suggested (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  77
    Two Dialogues: Introductions to Philosophy and Libertarianism.J. C. Lester - 2016 - Buckingham, England: The University of Buckingham Press.
    Why learn about philosophy? Because it is the master subject; more fundamental than all of the others: it critically examines their fundamental assumptions and presuppositions. And without some grasp of philosophy one cannot be fully educated or even intellectually autonomous: one is the meme-marionette of unexamined traditions, fashions, and commonsense assumptions. *** -/- Why learn about libertarianism? Because politics causes or exacerbates the very problems that it purports to solve, or it misperceives voluntary behaviour and free markets as problems. Liberty (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  45
    The Empirical Author: Salman Rushdie's The Satanic Verses.Anthony Close - 1990 - Philosophy and Literature 14 (2):248-267.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Anthony Close THE EMPIRICAL AUTHOR: SALMAN RUSHDIE'S THE SATANIC VERSES HOBBES, comparing the author ofan action to the owner ofgoods, asserts, "And as the right of possession, is called dominion; so the right of doing any action, is called authority" (Leviathan, Book I, chap. 16). My purpose in this essay is to apply this Hobbesian maxim to the relation Author/Text, expanding somewhat Hobbes's notion of authority. I presuppose that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  58
    On a homework problem of Larry horn's.Francis Jeffry Pelletier - unknown
    Larry Horn is justifiably famous for his work on the semantics of the English conjunction or and both its relationship to the formal logic truth functions ∨ and @ (“inclusive” and “exclusive” disjunction respectively1) and its relationship to the ways people employ or in natural discourse. These interests have been present since his 1972 dissertation, where he argued for a “scalar implicature-based” account of many of these relationships as opposed to a presuppositional account. They have surfaced in his “Greek Grice” (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  18
    On a super large fixed-point of common information in multi-agent signalling games.Anton Benz - 2012 - Logic Journal of the IGPL 20 (1):94-120.
    In this article, we compare two fixed-point constructions of common knowledge in sequential coordination problems. The first one corresponds to the standard maximal fixed-point construction of common knowledge in a possible worlds framework; the second construction provides an even larger fixed-point and involves iterated epistemic updates. We call the first fixed-point the maximal fixed-point, and the second the update fixed-point. Both fixed-points define a set of sequential actions that solve the coordination problem such that success is mutually guaranteed. The main (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. (1 other version)Nietzsche's Will to Power as Naturalist Critical Ontology.Donovan Miyasaki - 2013 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 30 (3):251-69.
    In this paper, I argue that Nietzsche’s published works contain a substantial, although implicit, argument for the will to power as ontology—a critical and descriptive, rather than positive and explanatory, theory of reality. Further, I suggest this ontology is entirely consistent with a naturalist methodology. The will to power ontology follows directly from Nietzsche’s naturalist rejection of three metaphysical presuppositions: substance, efficient causality, and final causality. I show that a number of interpretations, including those of Clark, Schacht, Reginster, and Richardson, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  50
    The historical connection between the golden rule and the second greatest love command.Keith D. Stanglin - 2005 - Journal of Religious Ethics 33 (2):357-371.
    The golden rule, perhaps the most recognizable moral maxim in Western culture, is an inadequate basis for morality. In light of its flaws as a precept and its apparent lack of moral content, it is initially perplexing that the historic Judeo-Christian tradition has often linked the golden rule with the second greatest command to love one's neighbor as oneself. However, after examining the presuppositions behind this link and investigating the biblical context of these sayings, it is clear that the Judeo-Christian (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  31
    Unveiling the Other - the Pragmatics of Infosuasion.Monika Kopytowska - 2010 - Lodz Papers in Pragmatics 6 (2):249-282.
    Unveiling the Other - the Pragmatics of Infosuasion The present paper, starting from the assumption that television news is "the main source" and a key player in the democratic process explores the media-politics interface, along with the ideological conditioning and cultural embedding of the news discourse, understood both as a process and as a product. The objective behind it is threefold. Firstly, it is to examine the media mechanisms accounting for the process of ‘infosuasion’, i.e. persuading the viewers under the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  20
    Perspective pragmatique sur l’anaphore.Jean Albrespit - 2022 - Corela. Cognition, Représentation, Langage.
    La pragmatique linguistique a pour objet le calcul du sens dans les inférences et les implicatures, l’étude des effets des actes de langage, des présuppositions. Un des domaines qui a retenu l’attention des chercheurs en pragmatique est celui de l’anaphore et de la déixis. Le corpus examiné fournit des occurrences intéressantes d’anaphore pour un traitement pragmatique : le conférencier doit convaincre et garder son public attentif. Il cherche à établir une connivence avec son public en faisant référence à un « (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  8
    Course d'Apobate.Maxime Collignon - 1883 - Bulletin de Correspondance Hellénique 7 (1):458-462.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. (1 other version)Islam and Capitalism.Maxime Rodinson & Brian Pearce - 1976 - Science and Society 40 (1):88-91.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46. Descartes.Maxime Leroy, G. Friedmann, J. Luc, Lucie Prenant, P. Labérenne & N. Gutermann - 1938 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 45 (3):18-18.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  27
    Language structure and the structure of consciousness: Can one find a 'common denominator' between them?Maxim I. Stamenov - 2001 - In Paavo Pylkkänen & Tere Vadén, Dimensions of Conscious Experience. John Benjamins. pp. 37--45.
  48.  24
    La vision interne et l'enveloppement visuel.Maxime Vincent - 1933 - Paris,: Fischbacher.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  8
    Kritik der mythischen Ökonomie.Maxim Asjoma - 2015 - Berlin: Duncker Und Humblot.
  50. La force du droit.Maxime Chauvet, Gustavo Fernandes Meireles & Emmanuele Nef (eds.) - 2023 - Paris: Éditions Mare & Martin.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 966