Results for ' Right intention'

970 found
Order:
  1.  43
    Right Intention and the Ends of War.Duncan Purves & Ryan Jenkins - 2016 - Journal of Military Ethics 15 (1):18-35.
    ABSTRACTThe jus ad bellum criterion of right intention is a central guiding principle of just war theory. It asserts that a country’s resort to war is just only if that country resorts to war for the right reasons. However, there is significant confusion, and little consensus, about how to specify the CRI. We seek to clear up this confusion by evaluating several distinct ways of understanding the criterion. On one understanding, a state’s resort to war is just (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  2.  47
    Right Intention and the Oil Factor in the Second Gulf War.Kenneth W. Kemp - 1994 - Philosophy in the Contemporary World 1 (1):15-20.
    This essay responds to the argument that US interest in Kuwaiti oil made its war against Iraq fail the just-war criterion of right intention. That argument is based on a misunderstanding of the criterion, namely, that right intention requires not merely the presence of a concern for justice but the absence of any other (especially self-interested) motives. Correction of this misunderstanding is important to application of the just-war theory to the general question of intervention in foreign (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  4
    A Return to Right Intention in the Just War.Greg Ray - 2024 - Journal of Military Ethics 23 (2):91-102.
    It has been argued that the criterion of right intention adds nothing in just war theory – that it is subsumed by other conditions on just war. It has also been argued that there is no tenable reading of the criterion at all, and in particular that taking it as a positive requirement on the state's motives is after all incoherent in a way that would make it impossible to satisfy. This article gives an action-theoretic analysis of (one (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  38
    Right Intention: A Reply to Janzen, Purves, and Jenkins.Uwe Steinhoff - 2018 - Journal of Military Ethics 17 (2-3):172-176.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  5. Just Cause and 'Right Intention'.Uwe Steinhoff - 2014 - Journal of Military Ethics 13 (1):32-48.
    I argue that the criterion of just cause is not independent of proportionality and other valid jus ad bellum criteria. One cannot know whether there is a just cause without knowing whether the other (valid) criteria (apart from ‘right intention’) are satisfied. The advantage of this account is that it is applicable to all wars, even to wars where nobody will be killed or where the enemy has not committed a rights violation but can be justifiably warred against (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  6. A Critique of the Right Intention Condition as an Element of Jus ad Bellum.Greg Janzen - 2016 - Journal of Military Ethics 15 (1):36-57.
    According to just war theory, a resort to war is justified only if it satisfies the right intention condition. This article offers a critical examination of this condition, defending the thesis that, despite its venerable history as part of the just war tradition, it ought to be jettisoned. When properly understood, it turns out to be an unnecessary element of jus ad bellum, adding nothing essential to our assessments of the justice of armed conflict.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  7.  9
    A Return to Right Intention in the Just War.Greg Ray - 2024 - Journal of Military Ethics 23 (2):91-102.
    It has been argued that the criterion of right intention adds nothing in just war theory – that it is subsumed by other conditions on just war. It has also been argued that there is no tenable reading of the criterion at all, and in particular that taking it as a positive requirement on the state's motives is after all incoherent in a way that would make it impossible to satisfy. This article gives an action-theoretic analysis of (one (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Joseph C. Kunkel -- right intention, deterrence, and nuclear alternatives.Joseph C. Kunkel - 1984 - Philosophy and Social Criticism 10 (3-4):143-155.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9.  30
    Looking for the right intention: can neuroscience benefit from the law?Davide Rigoni, Luca Sammicheli & Giuseppe Sartori - 2015 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9.
  10.  68
    A Realistic and Effective Constraint on the Resort to Force? Pre-commitment to Jus in Bello and Jus Post Bellum as Part of the Criterion of Right Intention.Annalisa Koeman - 2007 - Journal of Military Ethics 6 (3):198-220.
    This paper explores Brian Orend's contribution to the just war tradition, specifically his proposed jus post bellum criteria and his idea of pre-commitment to jus in bello and jus post bellum as part of an expanded jus ad bellum criterion of right intention. The latter is based on his interpretation of Kant's work: that as part of the original decision to begin a war, a state should commit itself to certain rules of conduct and appropriate war termination, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  11. Deploying Racist Soldiers: A critical take on the `right intention' requirement of Just War Theory.Nathan G. Wood - 2018 - Kriterion - Journal of Philosophy 32 (1):53-74.
    In a recent article Duncan Purves, Ryan Jenkins, and B. J. Strawser argue that in order for a decision in war to be just, or indeed the decision to resort to war to be just, it must be the case that the decision is made for the right reasons. Furthermore, they argue that this requirement holds regardless of how much good is produced by said action. In this essay I argue that their argument is flawed, in that it mistakes (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  34
    The Medical Exception to the Prohibition of Killing: A Matter of the Right Intention?Govert Den Hartogh - 2019 - Ratio Juris 32 (2):157-176.
    It has long been thought that by using morphine to alleviate the pain of a dying patient, a doctor runs the risk of causing his death. In all countries this kind of killing is explicitly or silently permitted by the law. That permission is usually explained by appealing to the doctrine of double effect: If the use of morphine shortens life, that is only an unintended side effect. The paper evaluates this view, finding it flawed beyond repair and proposing an (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  60
    Intentional (Nation‐)States: A Group‐Agency Problem for the State’s Right to Exclude.Matthew R. Joseph - 2021 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 38 (1):73-87.
    Most philosophical defences of the state’s right to exclude immigrants derive their strength from the normative importance of self-determination. If nation-states are taken to be the political institutions of a people, then the state’s right to exclude is the people’s right to exclude – and a denial of this right constitutes an abridgement of self-determination. In this paper, I argue that this view of self-determination does not cohere with a group-agency view of nation-states. On the group-agency (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  14.  63
    Intentions, Rights and Wrongs.Marilyn Fischer - 1984 - Philosophy Research Archives 10:239-247.
    In this paper I argue against Fried’s thesis that a wrong must be intended by the violator in order for a person’s negative rights to be violated. With Fried’s requirement these rights become in a sense derivative from wrongs. This makes the relation between one’s negative rights and one’s moral integrity, upon which Fried wants to base rights, indirect and inappropriately weak. If rights are based on one’s status as a freely choosing, rational, moral personality, then whether one’s rights are (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15.  31
    Intentions and causes, actions and right actions.Robert N. McLaughlin - 2000 - Ratio 13 (1):54–68.
    I argue in this essay that belief/desire explanations are not logically true and not causal, and further that the antecedent of a true belief/desire conditional cannot be strengthened in such a way as to transform it into a true causal statement. I also argue that belief/desire explanations are not dispensable: they are presupposed in our justifications of scientific claims. The proposal is not that psychological determinism is false, but that some at least of our activities are not describable in causal (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. The role of parliamentary intention in adjudication under the human rights act 1998.Kavanagh Aileen - 2006 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 26 (1):179-206.
    This essay gives more detailed content to the widespread view that the Human Rights Act 1998 (HRA) has changed the traditional role of parliamentary intention in statutory interpretation. It begins by outlining the various ways in which legislative intent has featured in traditional (pre-HRA) statutory interpretation. This is followed by an examination of the interpretive principles developed by the senior judiciary under the HRA case-law, focusing on the extent to which they seem to depart from traditional principles. It is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  82
    Beyond Morality: Intentional Action in Hegel's Philosophy of Right.Davide P. Cargnello - 2014 - Mind 123 (491):671-706.
    The paper discusses Hegel’s conception of intentional action. Drawing principally on Hegel’s analysis of the determinations and rights of action in the Morality chapter of the Philosophy of Right, I suggest that Hegel is committed to a corrigibilist view of action, according to which intentions are definitive of action, objective, and publicly accessible, in principle, via ex post facto corrective interpretation. I conclude by commenting briefly on the place of Hegel’s conception of action in the broader action-theoretic landscape.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  18.  66
    War and intention.Darrell Cole - 2011 - Journal of Military Ethics 10 (3):174-191.
    Abstract Right intention is one of the staple criteria of traditional just war theory. In classical terms, right intention is met when a belligerent aims to achieve a just and peaceful order. I will address the problem of determining when a belligerent has satisfied the criterion of right intention. I will argue that right intention is determined by observing a belligerent's acts during and after a conflict. Intention is not merely a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  19.  40
    The rights and wrongs of intentional exposure research: contextualising the Guatemala STD inoculation study.Holly Fernandez Lynch - 2012 - Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (8):513-515.
    In its recent review of the US Public Health Service Sexually Transmitted Disease Inoculation Study, conducted in Guatemala from 1946 to 1948, the Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues identified a number of egregious ethical violations, but failed to adequately address issues associated with the intentional exposure research design in particular. As a result, a common public misconception that the study was wrong because researchers purposefully infected their subjects has been left standing. In fact, human subjects have been (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  20. Intentional action in folk psychology: An experimental investigation.Joshua Knobe - 2003 - Philosophical Psychology 16 (2):309-325.
    Four experiments examined people’s folk-psychological concept of intentional action. The chief question was whether or not _evaluative _considerations — considerations of good and bad, right and wrong, praise and blame — played any role in that concept. The results indicated that the moral qualities of a behavior strongly influence people’s judgements as to whether or not that behavior should be considered ‘intentional.’ After eliminating a number of alternative explanations, the author concludes that this effect is best explained by the (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   206 citations  
  21.  11
    Moral Reasoning: An Intentional Approach to Distinguishing Right from Wrong.Michael Jones - unknown
    This book represents a unique contribution to the study of ethics: an introductory textbook that is designed to be very readable while at the same time being deeply philosophical. It leads the reader on an exploration of the major approaches to ethics that have developed in the Western philosophical tradition: Ethical Relativism, Virtue Ethics, Natural Law Ethics, Ethical Egoism, Utilitarianism, Duty Ethics, Social Contract Theory, and Divine Command Theory. It discusses the chief strengths and weaknesses of each and opts for (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  54
    Intention and Moral Enhancement.William Simkulet - 2016 - Bioethics 30 (9):714-720.
    Recently philosophers have proposed a wide variety of interventions referred to as ‘moral enhancements’. Some of these interventions are concerned with helping individuals make more informed decisions; others, however, are designed to compel people to act as the intervener sees fit. Somewhere between these two extremes lie interventions designed to direct an agent's attention either towards morally relevant issues – hat-hanging – or away from temptations to do wrong – hat-hiding. I argue that these interventions fail to constitute genuine moral (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  23. Planning on a Prior Intention.Facundo Alonso - 2020 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 18 (3):229-265.
    Intention plays a central role in coordinating action. It does so, it is commonly thought, by allowing one to plan further actions for the future on the basis of the belief that it will be executed. Doxasticists about intention (Harman, Velleman) conclude from this that accounting for this role of intention requires accepting the thesis that intention involves belief. Conativists (Bratman, Brunero, Mele) reject that conclusion. I argue that Doxasticists are right in calling attention to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24.  94
    Acting intentionally and acting for a reason.Joshua Knobe - 2007 - Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology 27 (1):119-122.
    In earlier work, I relied on a commonly-held view about the relationship between the concept of acting intentionally and the concept of performing a behavior in order to achieve a goal. Eric Wiland responds that it was actually a mistake to rely on this view and that the relationship between these concepts is far more complex than was previously thought. I now think that Wiland may be right to reject my earlier approach, and I therefore provide additional empirical support (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  25.  2
    Human rights education for nursing students: A scoping review.Elisabeth Irene Karlsen Dogan, Laura Terragni & Anne Raustøl - forthcoming - Nursing Ethics.
    Background: Human rights are an important part of nursing care, and nurses deal with human rights matter daily. Despite their relevance and acknowledgement of their importance, human rights issues remain limited in nursing education. Aim: The study’s aim was to describe how human rights education has been addressed in nursing education. Method: A scoping review was conducted according to the Preferred Reporting Items for Scoping reviews (PRISMA-ScR) and Joanna Briggs Institute (JBI) recommendations. The search was conducted in March 2023, with (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Referential Intentions and Communicative Luck.Andrew Peet - 2017 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95 (2):379-384.
    Brian Loar [1976] observed that communicative success with singular terms requires more than correct referent assignment. For communicative success to be achieved, the audience must assign the right referent in the right way. Loar, and others since, took this to motivate Fregean accounts of the semantics of singular terms. Ray Buchanan [2014] has recently responded, maintaining that, although Loar is correct to claim that communicative success with singular terms requires more than correct referent assignment, this is compatible with (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  27.  19
    The right to withdraw from controlled human infection studies: Justifications and avoidance.Holly Fernandez Lynch - 2020 - Bioethics 34 (8):833-848.
    The right to withdraw from research without penalty is well established around the world. However, it has been challenged in some corners of bioethics based on concerns about various harms—to participants, to scientific integrity, and to research bystanders—that may stem from withdrawal. These concerns have become particularly salient in emerging debates about the ethics of controlled human infection (CHI) studies in which participants are intentionally infected with pathogens, often in inpatient settings with extensive follow‐up. In this article, I provide (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  28.  20
    Human Rights and Public Policy Frameworks A Kantian Perspective.Shashi Motilal & Divya Raj Juyal - 2016 - Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research 33 (2):241-251.
    PurposeThis paper presumes that a public policy document must aim at protecting human rights. The question being raised is- what kind of moral reasoning or grounding can we afford to the idea that human rights are important for the whole framework of public policy. The paper aims at looking at the moral and political philosophy of Immanuel Kant as we find it in his Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals and the Metaphysics of Morals for providing this background.MethodThe paper provides (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  36
    Intentions at the End of Life: Continuous Deep Sedation and France’s Claeys-Leonetti law.Steven Farrelly-Jackson - 2024 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 49 (1):43-57.
    In 2016, France passed a major law that is unique in giving terminally ill and suffering patients the right to the controversial procedure of continuous deep sedation until death (CDS). In so doing, the law identifies CDS as a sui generis clinical practice, distinct from other forms of palliative sedation therapy, as well as from euthanasia. As such, it reconfigures the ethical debate over CDS in interesting ways. This paper addresses one aspect of this reconfiguration and its implications for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30.  18
    Actions, Intentions, and Awareness and Causal Deviancy.Kevin Magill - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 26:38-52.
    In Davidson's example of causal deviancy, a climber knows that he can save himself from plummeting to his death by letting go of a rope connecting him to a companion who has lost his footing, but the thought of the contemplated act so upsets him that he lets go unintentionally. Causation of behavior by intentional states that rationalize it is not enough for it to count as acting. Therefore, the behavior must be caused in 'the right way' or by (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  24
    The Nature of Agreements: A Solution to Some Puzzles about Claim-Rights and Joint Intention.Margaret Gilbert - 2014 - In Manuel Vargas & Gideon Yaffe (eds.), Rational and Social Agency: The Philosophy of Michael Bratman. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. pp. 215-255.
  32. Neuro rights, the new human rights.Deepa Kansra - 2021 - Rights Compass.
    The human mind has been a subject matter of study in psychology, law, science, philosophy and other disciplines. By definition, its potential is power, abilities and capacities including perception, knowledge, sensation, memory, belief, imagination, emotion, mood, appetite, intention, and action (Pardo, Patterson). In terms of role, it creates and shapes societal morality, culture, peace and democracy. Today, a rapidly advancing science–technology–artificial intelligence (AI) landscape is able to reach into the inner realms of the human mind. Technology, particularly neurotechnology enables (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  19
    Chapouthier, G. and Nouët, J.-C. (eds.): 1998, The Universal Declaration of Animal Rights. Comments and Intentions.Jan Vorstenbosch - 1999 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 2 (2):209-210.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  41
    Intentions in critical clinical settings: a study of medical students' perceptions.N. Juth, T. Tillberg & N. Lynoe - 2011 - Journal of Medical Ethics 37 (8):483-486.
    The aim of this pilot study was to develop a realistic clinical case for identifying Knobe's asymmetric effect, ie, the tendency to ascribe intentions to a larger extent when an act is considered wrong, as well as to compare medical students at the beginning and end of their curriculum. A vignette about a critically ill 72-year-old patient in need of an operation was used, with two different outcomes: the patient dies or the patient recovers. Approximately half of the students received (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35.  67
    Unravelling intention: Distal intentions increase the subjective sense of agency.Mikkel C. Vinding, Michael N. Pedersen & Morten Overgaard - 2013 - Consciousness and Cognition 22 (3):810-815.
    Experimental studies investigating the contribution of conscious intention to the generation of a sense of agency for one’s own actions tend to rely upon a narrow definition of intention. Often it is operationalized as the conscious sensation of wanting to move right before movement. Existing results and discussion are therefore missing crucial aspects of intentions, namely intention as the conscious sensation of wanting to move in advance of the movement. In the present experiment we used an (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  36.  11
    Right living: lessons in ethics for schools.Susan H. Wixon - 1903 - New York [etc.]: Thompson-Brown.
    Excerpt from Right Living: Lessons in Ethics for Schools Human experience has shown the value of right living, also, the disaster that follows wrong living. It has been clearly demonstrated, again and again, that the basis of symmetrical life is character, first, last, and always, and good character comes only from a right use of life, and a correct understanding of its duties. Emerson says Character is the most valuable pos session and acquisition of life. Higher than (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  54
    Conscientious objection to intentional killing: an argument for toleration.Bjørn K. Myskja & Morten Magelssen - 2018 - BMC Medical Ethics 19 (1):82.
    In the debate on conscientious objection in healthcare, proponents of conscience rights often point to the imperative to protect the health professional’s moral integrity. Their opponents hold that the moral integrity argument alone can at most justify accommodation of conscientious objectors as a “moral courtesy”, as the argument is insufficient to establish a general moral right to accommodation, let alone a legal right. This text draws on political philosophy in order to argue for a legal right to (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  38. Intention and sexual consent.Hallie Liberto - 2017 - Philosophical Explorations 20 (sup2):127-141.
    In this paper I first argue that we do not need to intend all the features of X in order to consent to X. I will present cases in which agents intend to consent to gambles, and intend to consent to have sex with people under certain descriptions, de re, rather than de dicto. Next, I argue that deception – even deception about features of a sexual act that qualify as “deal-breakers” for a participant – might not always have the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  39.  31
    Mal-Intentioned Illiteracy, Willful Ignorance, and Fetal Protection Laws: Is There a Lexicologist in the House?Mary Faith Marshall - 1999 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 27 (4):343-346.
    We should not investigate facts by the light of arguments, but arguments by the light of facts.Myson of Chen, one of the Seven Sages ca. 600 B.C.To settle scores as well as problems, to shake things up, to make people think about what they said and wrote, to be provocative without being unjust...Kingsley AmisIn their critique of Wisconsin's revised child protection Statute, Kenneth De Ville and Loretta Kopelman argue rightly that “words matter.” Word mongering infects most political dialogue and is (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  15
    Rights to Punish for Libertarians.Jordan Howard Sobel - 1995 - Dialogue 34 (4):675-.
    Thomas Hurka derives rights to punish from what I will term the Libertarian Rights Principle, which is “that there is really only one natural right, namely the equal right of all persons to the most extensive liberty compatible with a like liberty for other persons, and that all other natural rights are species or instances of the right to liberty.” These rights to punish, he says, extend only to punishing violators of rights, never to “punishing” the innocent; (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  20
    Social Integration and Right-Wing Populist Voting in Germany: How Subjective Social Marginalization Affects Support for the AfD.Patrick Sachweh - 2020 - Analyse & Kritik 42 (2):369-398.
    Electoral support for right-wing populist parties is typically explained either by economic deprivation or cultural grievances. Attempting to bring economic and cultural explanations together, recent approaches have suggested to conceptualize right-wing populist support as a problem of social integration. Applying this perspective to the German case, this article investigates whether weak subjective social integration-or subjective social marginalization, respectively-is associated with the intention to vote for the AfD. Furthermore, it asks whether the strength of this association varies across (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  54
    Kamm on Intention and Proportionality in War.Thomas Hurka - 2014 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 11 (4):411-427.
    This paper discusses the novel versions of the right intention and proportionality conditions in the ius ad bellum proposed in Chapter 3 of Frances Kamm’s Ethics for Enemies. It argues that Kamm is right to weaken the right intention condition to require, not positively intending a war’s just cause, but only having that cause’s presence be a necessary condition for war, but wrong to place no limits on why one makes a just cause necessary. It (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43.  16
    Intentional Parenthood and the Nuclear Family.Liezl Zyl - 2002 - Journal of Medical Humanities 23 (2):107-118.
    Reproductive techniques and practices, ranging from ordinary birth-control measures and artificial insemination to embryo transfer and surrogate motherhood, have greatly enhanced our range of reproductive choices. As a consequence, they pose a number of difficult moral and legal questions with regard to the formation of a family and our conception of parenthood. A view that is becoming increasingly common is that parental rights and responsibilities should not be based on genetic relationships but should instead be seen as arising from agreements (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44.  50
    “Benefit to the World” and “Heaven’s Intent”: The Prospective and Retrospective Aspects of the Mohist Criterion for Rightness.Bradford Jean-Hyuk Kim - 2024 - Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 23 (2).
    “Benefit to the world” and “Heaven’s intent” are not, as is often assumed, separate criteria for action in Mozi’s 墨子 ethics; they are the same in extension but not intension. When Mozi speaks in terms of “Heaven’s intent,” it is to highlight the criterion’s retrospective orientation and its scope; taking a cue from Heaven’s reactions to past deeds, agents specify the scope of “the world” by reference to the past performance of persons regarding benefit to the world. This diverges from (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  43
    Information rights: trust and human dignity in e-Government.Toni Carbo - 2007 - International Review of Information Ethics 7 (9):1-7.
    The words ―Rights,‖ ―Trust,‖ ―Human Dignity,‖ and even ―Government‖ have widely varying meanings and connotations, differing across time, languages and cultures. Concepts of rights, trust, and human dignity have been examined for centuries in great depth by ethicists and other philosophers and by religious think-ers, and more recently by social scientists and, especially as related to information, by information scientists. Similarly, discussions of government are well documented in writings back to Plato and Aristotle, with investi-gations of electronic government dating back (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  65
    Human rights and distributive justice in health care delivery.R. L. Shelton - 1978 - Journal of Medical Ethics 4 (4):165-171.
    This paper was first presented at the Annual Meeting of the American Society of Christian Ethics, Toronto School of Theology, Toronto, Ontario in January 1977. Robert Shelton aims to focus on the concept of 'right to health care,' its related principle, 'distributive justice' in an attempt to suggest 'where we are' at present and where we perhaps ought to be heading. The paper is divided into three parts, which in their turn explore the moral grounds, the US general public's (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  47.  31
    Human Rights and Socio-economic Transformation in South Africa.Carol Chi Ngang - 2021 - Human Rights Review 22 (3):349-370.
    In this article, I revisit the question of socio-economic transformation in South Africa to illustrate how it connects with human rights, essentially because, as I argue, transformation is unattainable without a comprehensive understanding of the central role of human rights in activating that process. I state the claim that the progressive human rights culture on the basis of which South Africa launched itself from the demise of apartheid into one of the most treasured constitutional democracies globally is noticeably disintegrating, displaying (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  97
    How Reasons Bear on Intentions.Graham Hubbs - 2013 - Ethics 124 (1):84-100.
    This paper is a critical response to Mark Schroeder’s recent “The Ubiquity of State-Given Reasons.” In this essay, Schroeder claims that it is possible for a right-kind reason to bear on an intention without that reason bearing on the object of the intention. I examine Schroeder’s central argument for this claim and conclude that it does not deliver the result Schroeder desires. My critique turns on explicating and extending some of G. E. M. Anscombe’s remarks in (...) on the structure of practical reasoning. (shrink)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  49.  20
    Rights, Indirect Harms and the Non‐Identity Problem.Justinpatrick Mcbrayer - 2008 - Bioethics 22 (6):299-306.
    The non‐identity problem is the problem of grounding moral wrongdoing in cases in which an action affects who will exist in the future. Consider a woman who intentionally conceives while on medication that is harmful for a fetus. If the resulting child is disabled as a result of the medication, what makes the woman's action morally wrong? I argue that an explanation in terms of harmful rights violations fails, and I focus on Peter Markie's recent rights‐based defense. Markie's analysis rests (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  83
    (1 other version)Equality, Right, and Identity: Rethinking the Contract through Hobbes and Marx.Rahul Govind - 2011 - Telos: Critical Theory of the Contemporary 2011 (154):75-98.
    ExcerptThe following essay is an investigation into the nature of the contract, the way in which the contract indexes “right” and equality, and the textual and historical expressions—as well as echoes—that this has taken from Thomas Hobbes to Karl Marx.1 The opening set of conceptual remarks will lead to a reading of Hobbes's Leviathan and Marx's On the Jewish Question, with the intent of arguing that both texts were concerned with theoretically explicating the relationship between right and equality, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 970