Results for ' reductio ad absurdum argument'

973 found
Order:
  1. Reductio ad absurdum-argument og filosofisk innsikt.Gunnar Skirbekk - 1966 - [Bergen]:
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  44
    Ryle's reductio ad absurdum argument.R. Routley & V. Routley - 1973 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 51 (2):124 – 138.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  45
    Future‐like‐ours as a metaphysical reductio ad absurdum argument of personal identity.Tomer Jordi Chaffer - 2023 - Bioethics 37 (4):367-373.
    Don Marquis' future‐like‐ours account is regarded as the best secular anti‐abortion position because he frames abortion as a wrongful killing via deprivation of a valuable future. Marquis objects to the reductio ad absurdum of contraception as being immoral because it is too difficult to identify an individual that is deprived of a future. To demonstrate why Marquis’ treatment of the contraception reductio is flawed by his own future‐like‐ours line of reasoning, I offer an argument for why (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  4. Reductio ad absurdum from a dialogical perspective.Catarina Dutilh Novaes - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (10):2605-2628.
    It is well known that reductio ad absurdum arguments raise a number of interesting philosophical questions. What does it mean to assert something with the precise goal of then showing it to be false, i.e. because it leads to absurd conclusions? What kind of absurdity do we obtain? Moreover, in the mathematics education literature number of studies have shown that students find it difficult to truly comprehend the idea of reductio proofs, which indicates the cognitive complexity of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  5. Reductio ad absurdum and slippery slope arguments:: Two sides of the same Coin?Candice Shelby - 2010 - Annales Philosophici 1:77-82.
    Despite the fact that the reductio ad absurdum argument is a valid deductive form, while the slippery slope argument is most often presented as a fallacious form of inductive argument, the two argument types bear some striking similarities. Investigation of these similarities reveals some more universal difficulties in the teaching of informal logic, and, in particular the difference between strong informal arguments and fallacious ones.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  92
    Reductio ad Absurdum Objections and the Dis‐Integration Argument against Merely Instrumental Sex.David Boonin - 2013 - Journal of Social Philosophy 44 (3):233-249.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  84
    Refuting a Standpoint by Appealing to Its Outcomes: Reductio ad Absurdum vs. Argument from Consequences.Henrike Jansen - 2007 - Informal Logic 27 (3):249-266.
    Used informally, the Reductio ad Absurdum (RAA) consists in reasoning appealing to the logically implied, absurd consequences of a hypothetical proposition, in order to refute it. This kind of reasoning resembles the Argument from Consequences, which appeals to causally induced consequences. These types of argument are sometimes confused, since it is not worked out how these different kinds of consequences should be distinguished. In this article it is argued that the logical consequences in RAA-argumentation can take (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  8.  89
    Is Wittgenstein Presenting a Reductio Ad Absurdum Argument in the ‘Private Language’ Sections of Philosophical Investigations §§ 243–315? [REVIEW]Derek A. McDougall - 2017 - Philosophical Quarterly 67 (268):552-570.
    The ‘Private Language’ sections of the Philosophical Investigations §§ 243–315 serve to undermine the idea that our ordinary felt sensations, e.g., of heat, or cold, or pain, together with our experienced impressions of colour or of sound, are ‘private’ or ‘inner’ objects, where an object mirrors in the mental realm what we associate with that of the physical. This paper explores Wittgenstein's method in these sections, together with the work of several of his commentators who agree with his ‘therapeutic’ approach (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  9.  85
    Mathematical Proof and Discovery Reductio ad Absurdum.Dale Jacquette - 2008 - Informal Logic 28 (3):242-261.
    The uses and interpretation of reductio ad absurdum argumentation in mathematical proof and discovery are examined, illustrated with elementary and progressively sophisticated examples, and explained. Against Arthur Schopenhauer’s objections, reductio reasoning is defended as a method of uncovering new mathematical truths, and not merely of confirming independently grasped mathematical intuitions. The application of reductio argument is contrasted with purely mechanical brute algorithmic inferences as an art requiring skill and intelligent intervention in the choice of hypotheses (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  55
    Ibn sīnā on reductio ad absurdum.Wilfrid Hodges - 2017 - Review of Symbolic Logic 10 (3):583-601.
    Ibn Sīnā proposed an analysis of arguments by reductio ad absurdum. His analysis contains, perhaps for the first time, a workable method for handling the making and discharging of assumptions in a formal proof. We translate the relevant text of Ibn Sīnā and put his analysis into the context of his general approach to logic.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  11. A Reductio Ad Absurdum of Divine Temporality.Steven B. Cowan - 1996 - Religious Studies 32 (3):371 - 378.
    In this paper, I present an argument to show that the doctrine of divine temporality (the view that God is in time, but everlastingly eternal) is incoherent. The doctrine of divine temporality entails that God has traversed an actually infinite series of moments in order to reach the present. But I show that an actually infinite series of moments cannot be traversed. Hence, God could not have traversed his infinite past to reach the present. Therefore, the doctrine of divine (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12. Enhancing the Diagramming Method in Informal Logic.Dale Jacquette - 2011 - Argument: Biannual Philosophical Journal 1 (2):327-360.
    The argument diagramming method developed by Monroe C. Beardsley in his (1950) book Practical Logic, which has since become the gold standard for diagramming arguments in informal logic, makes it possible to map the relation between premises and conclusions of a chain of reasoning in relatively complex ways. The method has since been adapted and developed in a number of directions by many contemporary informal logicians and argumentation theorists. It has proved useful in practical applications and especially pedagogically in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  13. Reductio ad absurdum.Nicholas Rescher - 2002 - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  14.  61
    On the Argumentative Strength of Indirect Inferential Conditionals.Sara Verbrugge & Hans Smessaert - 2010 - Argumentation 24 (3):337-362.
    Inferential or epistemic conditional sentences represent a blueprint of someone’s reasoning process from premise to conclusion. Declerck and Reed (2001) make a distinction between a direct and an indirect type. In the latter type the direction of reasoning goes backwards, from the blatant falsehood of the consequent to the falsehood of the antecedent. We first present a modal reinterpretation in terms of Argumentation Schemes of indirect inferential conditionals (IIC’s) in Declerck and Reed (2001). We furthermore argue for a distinction between (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  47
    Phya pa Chos kyi seng ge on Argumentation by Consequence (thal ʼgyur): The Nature, Function, and Form of Consequence Statements.Pascale Hugon - 2013 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 41 (6):671-702.
    This paper presents the main aspects of the views of the Tibetan logician Phya pa Chos kyi seng ge (1109–1169) on argumentation “by consequence” (thal ʼgyur, Skt. prasaṅga) based on his exposition of the topic in the fifth chapter of his Tshad ma yid kyi mun sel and on a parallel excursus in his commentary on Dharmakīrti’s Pramānaviniścaya. It aims at circumscribing primarily the nature and function of consequences (thal ʼgyur/thal ba) for this author—in particular the distinction between “proving consequences” (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  26
    (1 other version)Wittgenstein's Anti‐Platonist Argument.Thomas McNally - 2015 - Philosophical Investigations 39 (3):281-301.
    Many interpreters have noted that §§138–242 of Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations is dominated by an attack on a platonist or classical realist conception of rules and meaning. In this paper, I address the lack of clarity that still exists concerning the nature and strength of the arguments in those sections. I argue that Wittgenstein's attack is genuinely compelling if viewed as an intricate reductio ad absurdum argument that runs all the way through §§138–201. On my reading, the well-known (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  25
    Mixing and Matching Deductive and Non-deductive Arguments.Spencer K. Wertz - 2024 - Teaching Philosophy 47 (1):95-106.
    This essay is basically divided into two parts. The first deals with the similarities between reductio ad absurdum arguments and slippery slope arguments. The chief example comes from Thomas Hobbes’s Leviathan, which advances an argument for the necessity of government for humane living. The second addresses some pedagogical concerns centered around another pair of arguments: the argument by complete enumeration and the argument by inductive generalization. The illustration for this pair comes from the arts. I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  38
    Reductio ad absurdum” and Łukasiewicz's modalities.S. P. Odintsov - 2003 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 11:149-166.
    The present article contains part of results from my lecture delivered at II Flemish-Polish workshop on Ontological Foundation of Paraconsistency.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19.  26
    Reductio-ad-absurdum: a family feud between Copi and Scherer.Lyman C. D. Kulathungam - 1975 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 16 (2):245-254.
  20. (1 other version)On Reductio ad Absurdum Proofs.J. E. Wiredu - 1976 - International Logic Review 13:90.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  97
    A função do método de análise na constituição do argumento do cogito nas Meditações: uma leitura do cogito através da reductio ad absurdum.Érico Andrade - 2009 - Veritas – Revista de Filosofia da Pucrs 54 (2):155-171.
    Considerando que o cogito possa ser tomado, nas Meditações, como uma conclusão de uma demonstração, pode-se avançar a tese de que essa demonstração está consoante ao método analítico, que Descartes reconhece empreender nesse texto. Esse método teria entre as suas funções nas Meditações aquela de apresentar – sob a forma de uma rede de implicações ontológicas – o raciocínio que conduz à certeza da existência. Como cumpre no referido texto determinar a certeza da existência sem tomar como base nenhuma certeza (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  22.  23
    Some Benefits and Limitations of Modern Argument Map Representation.Charles Rathkopf - 2024 - Argumentation 38 (2):199-224.
    Argument maps represent some arguments more effectively than others. The goal of this article is to account for that variability, so that those who wish to use argument maps can do so with more foresight. I begin by identifying four properties of argument maps that make them useful tools for evaluating arguments. Then, I discuss four types of argument that are difficult to map well: reductio ad absurdum arguments, charges of equivocation, logical analogies, and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Abduction as the Mother of All Argumentation.Priyedarshi Jetli - manuscript
    Abduction* is the genus with deduction and induction as species. Modus tollens is backward reasoning as an unknown proposition is inferred from a known proposition. Reductio ad absurdum is abductive because the conclusion is inferred by deriving a contradiction from an assumption. Inductive reasoning from effect to cause is also backward reasoning. But abduction* consists of forward reasoning as well. The generic structure of abductive* argumentation is universal among all cultures, occupations and disciplines.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  50
    An ironic reductio for a 'pro-life' argument:1 Hurlbut's proposal for stem cell research.Kevin Elliott - 2007 - Bioethics 21 (2):98–110.
    ABSTRACT William Hurlbut, a Stanford University bioethicist and member of the President's Council on Bioethics, recently proposed a solution to the current impasse over human embryonic stem cell research in the United States. He suggested that researchers could use genetic engineering and somatic cell nuclear transfer (i.e. cloning) to develop human ‘pseudo‐embryos’ that have no potential to develop fully into human persons. According to Hurlbut, even thinkers who typically ascribe high moral status to human embryos could approve of destroying these (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  25.  70
    A Reductio Ad Absurdum of Restricted, Tribal Criminal Jurisdiction.Clifton Perry - 2004 - International Journal of Applied Philosophy 18 (2):253-262.
    As Federal Indian Law has evolved, many questions have been posed regarding tribal jurisdiction. This paper examines the jurisdiction tribes have over member Indians, non-member Indians, and non-member, non-Indians. It addresses the ethical challenge faced by tribal attorneys who represent non-member Indian clients in a manner that ultimately undermines tribal sovereignty.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Wittgenstein's Reductio.Gilad Nir - 2022 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 10 (3).
    By means of a reductio argument, Wittgenstein’s Tractatus calls into question the very idea that we can represent logical form. My paper addresses three interrelated questions: first, what conception of logical form is at issue in this argument? Second, whose conception of logic is this argument intended to undermine? And third, what could count as an adequate response to it? I show that the argument construes logical form as the universal, underlying correlation of any representation (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. Argument Mariusza Grygiańca za niepoprawnością definicji przedmiotu ogólnego.Wojciech Wciórka - 2005 - Filozofia Nauki 4.
    Mariusz Grygianiec has criticized the so called "proofs of nonexistence of general objects" as based on a wrong definition. In this paper one of his arguments is shown to depend on an unsatisfiable condition (contradictory to some basic ontological intuitions) without which, however, it is inconclusive as a reductio ad absurdum. Furthermore, it is suggested that even if the argument was sound, it could by no means be counted - contrary to the Author's intention - as a (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  20
    Appeal to Ridicule.Gregory L. Bock - 2018-05-09 - In Robert Arp, Steven Barbone & Michael Bruce (eds.), Bad Arguments. Wiley. pp. 118–120.
    This chapter focuses on one of the common fallacies in Western philosophy, appeal to ridicule. An appeal to ridicule is closely related to an ad hominem argument because both attack the person. There is a similarity between an appeal to ridicule and an appeal to emotion in that both attempt to bypass rational assessment of a point of view and elicit an emotional reaction from the audience. An appeal to ridicule may be an attempt to elicit humor at another's (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Rothbard’s and Hoppe’s justifications of libertarianism.Marian Eabrasu - 2013 - Politics, Philosophy and Economics 12 (3):288-307.
    Murray N. Rothbard and Hans-Hermann Hoppe build their libertarian theory of justice on two axioms concerning self-ownership and homesteading, which are bolstered by two key arguments: reductio ad absurdum and performative contradiction. Each of these arguments is designed to demonstrate that libertarianism is the only theory of justice that can be justified. If either of these arguments were valid, it would prove the libertarian claim that the state is an unjust political arrangement. Giving due weight to the importance (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30.  13
    The principle of reductio ad absurdum as an ontological problem.A. M. Anisov - 2018 - RUDN Journal of Philosophy 22 (2):149-157.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Difficoltà della «reductio ad absurdum» e apparenti deroghe alla logica classica nelle argomentazioni giudiziali.A. Custanzo - 1990 - Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia Del Diritto 67 (4):576-617.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  97
    Hume's Argument for the Temporal Priority of Causes.Todd Ryan - 2003 - Hume Studies 29 (1):29-41.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Studies Volume 29, Number 1, April 2003, pp. 29-41 Hume's Argument for the Temporal Priority of Causes TODD RYAN In a section entitled "Of Probability; and of the idea of cause and effect," Hume embarks on a search for the conceptual components of our idea of causation. Rejecting the possibility of analyzing the idea in terms of the qualities of objects, Hume claims to discover two constituent (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  33.  58
    The form of reductio ad absurdum.Paul Foulkes - 1973 - Mind 82 (328):579-580.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34. Contraception is not a reductio of Marquis.Bruce P. Blackshaw - 2023 - Bioethics 37 (5):508-510.
    Don Marquis’ future-like-ours account argues that abortion is seriously immoral because itdeprives the embryo or fetus of a valuable future much like our own. Marquis was mindful ofcontraception being reductio ad absurdum of his reasoning, and argued that prior tofertilisation, there is not an identifiable subject of harm. Contra Marquis, Tomer Chaffercontends that the ovum is a plausible subject of harm, and therefore contraception deprives theovum of a future-like-ours. In response, I argue that being an identifiable subject of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  15
    Following Sextus: Demonstrative Argument in Gorgias’ Peri tou mē ontos.Stefania Giombini - 2018 - Peitho 9 (1):13-29.
    The two extant versions of Gorgias’ Peri tou mē ontos have been preserved by an anonymous author and by Sextus Empiricus. Both versions have been differently interpreted by scholars who examine either the doctrine or the rhetorical-communicational dimen­sion. When comparing the PTMO with the rest of Gorgias’ works, the present paper aims to demonstrate that S.E. offers a more precise account of Gorgias’ modus argumentandi. Thus, S.E. shows the following, typical features of Gorgias’ demonstra­tive reasoning: 1) application of demonstrandum and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Meaning in time: on temporal externalism and Kripkenstein’s skeptical challenge.Jaakko Reinikainen - 2022 - Synthese 200 (288):1-27.
    The main question of metasemantics, or foundational semantics, is why an expression token has the meaning (semantic value) that it in fact has. In his reading of Ludwig Wittgenstein’s later work, Saul Kripke presented a skeptical challenge that threatened to make the foundational question unanswerable. My first contention in this paper is that the skeptical challenge indeed poses an insoluble paradox, but only for a certain kind of metasemantic theory, against which the challenge effectively works as a reductio ad (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  37.  40
    Scherer on reductio ad absurdum.Charles H. Lambros - 1973 - Mind 82 (328):581-585.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  40
    Quine’s proxy-function argument for the indeterminacy of reference and frege’s caesar problem.Dirk Greimann - 2020 - Manuscrito 44 (3):70-108.
    In his logical foundation of arithmetic, Frege faced the problem that the semantic interpretation of his system does not determine the reference of the abstract terms completely. The contextual definition of number, for instance, does not decide whether the number 5 is identical to Julius Caesar. In a late writing, Quine claimed that the indeterminacy of reference established by Frege’s Caesar problem is a special case of the indeterminacy established by his proxy-function argument. The present paper aims to show (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  60
    Utilitarianism and the reductio ad absurdum.LindaA Bell - 1978 - Metaphilosophy 9 (3-4):233-241.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  41
    Ghazālī and Metaphorical Predication in the Third Discussion of the Tahāfut al-Falāsifa.M. V. Dougherty - 2008 - American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 82 (3):391-409.
    Ghazālī’s The Incoherence of the Philosophers is an unusual philosophical work for a number of reasons, not the least of which is the author’s explicit disavowalof any of the conclusions contained within it. The present essay examines some of the hermeneutical challenges that face readers of the work and offers anexegetical account of the much-neglected Third Discussion, which examines a key point of Neoplatonic metaphysics. The paper argues that Ghazālī’s maintaining of the incompatibility of metaphysical creationism and Neoplatonic emanationism should (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41.  29
    Irony and Reductio ad Absurdum as a Methodological Strategy in Plato’s Meno.Luis Guerrero Martínez - 2021 - Revista de Filosofía (México) 49 (143):127-154.
    El Menón es un buen ejemplo del uso de la ironía socrática como forma de refutación. Específicamente, la forma lógica de reducción al absurdo constituye un dispositivo muy relacionado con la ironía socrática. En este artículo, se examinan analíticamente los cuatro elementos de la ironía que se presentan en el diálogo: 1. el conocimiento falso como una posición inicial asumida por los interlocutores de Sócrates; 2. la igno­ rancia socrática; 3. la reducción al absurdo del falso saber inicial; y 4. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  24
    David Hume & Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Common Approach to Common Sense?Derek McDougall - 2021 - Wittgenstein-Studien 12 (1):111-120.
    With characteristic candour, David Hume is prepared to admit that in ordinary life, but certainly not when reflecting on the nature of perceptual experience, he has no option but to ‘believe in the existence of body’ despite his philosophical reasonings to the contrary. In this instance, his commitment to ‘Common Sense’ has become, as it was not to become for his contemporary Thomas Reid, a direct consequence of participating in a day-to-day existence if nevertheless one which he has no option (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  66
    The form of Reductio ad Absurdum.J. M. Lee - 1973 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 14 (3):381-386.
  44. Hare'a-Horgana-Timmonsa argument przeciwko deskryptywizmowi.Krzysztof Saja - 2005 - Diametros 3:56-74.
    In recent years, with the appearance of a new wave of realism and non-descriptivism, the old dispute in meta-ethics between cognitivism and non-cognitivism has resurfaced. At present one of the most intensely discussed arguments among meta-ethicists is the so-called Moral Twin Earth argument of Terrence Horgan and Mark Timmons. It was presented in a series of articles published at the beginning of the nineties. However, a similar argument was put forth much earlier by Richard Hare, though the participants (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  38
    Transformative Pacifism in Theory and Practice: Gandhi, Buber, and the Dream of a Great and Lasting Peace.Andrew Fiala - 2016 - Dialogue and Universalism 26 (4):133-148.
    Pacifists imagine a “great peace,” to borrow a phrase from Martin Buber. This great peace will uphold justice and respect for humanity. It will not efface difference or negate liberty and identity. The great peace will be a space in which genuine dialogue can flourish—in which we can encounter one another as persons, listen to one another, embrace our common humanity, and acknowledge our differences. The great peace is much more than the absence of war. It is holistic, organic, dialogical, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  55
    The form of reductio ad absurdum.Donald Scherer - 1971 - Mind 80 (318):247-252.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47. Sceptical Paradoxes of Rule Following.Tomoji Shogenji - 1991 - Dissertation, University of Southern California
    In this dissertation I examine the sceptical problem of rule following presented by Saul Kripke in his interpretation of Ludwig Wittgenstein's later works: Do any facts determine what rule we were following in our apparently rule-following activities such as the use of language? I distinguish three ways of understanding this question--modest scepticism, radical scepticism, and metascepticism--and address them in Parts 1, 2 and 3 of the dissertation, respectively. ;Part 1 discusses modest scepticism, which asserts that no finite facts about humans (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  78
    Comment on Desmond Clarke, "teleology and mechanism: M. Grene's absurdity argument".Marjorie Grene - 1979 - Philosophy of Science 46 (2):326-327.
    Desmond Clarke's remarks on “my” absurdity argument are puzzling. i) Although I do indeed still believe it to be a valid argument, I certainly would not claim credit for it. I believe that “Reducibility: Another Side Issue?” put the general problem of the reducibility of mind into a somewhat unorthodox context, but the particular claim Clarke is attacking forms only one very unoriginal step in the general argument of that essay. ii) Some points that Clarke makes I (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  49
    A Reply to Haze’s Argument Against Arbitrary Reference.Sofía Meléndez Gutiérrez - 2023 - Philosophia 51 (3):1445-1448.
    This paper is a response to Haze’s brief argument for the falsity of the theory that instantial terms refer arbitrarily, proposed by Breckenridge and Magidor in 2012. In this paper, I characterise instantial terms and outline the theory of arbitrary reference; then I reconstruct Haze’s argument and contend that it fails in its purpose. Haze’s argument is supposed to be a _reductio ad absurdum:_ according to Haze, it proves that a contradiction follows from the most basic (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  57
    Do we need two notions of natural kind to account for the history of “jade”?Françoise Longy - 2018 - Synthese 195 (4):1459-1486.
    We need to distinguish two sorts of natural kinds, scientific and common NKs, because the notion of NK, which has to satisfy demands at three different levels—ontological, semantic and epistemological—, is subject to two incompatible sets of constraints. In order to prove this, I focus on the much-discussed case of jade. In the first part of the paper, I show that the current accounts are unsatisfactory because they are inconsistent. In the process, I explain why LaPorte’s analysis of “jade” as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
1 — 50 / 973