Results for 'Aristotle NE 3.5'

951 found
Order:
  1. (1 other version)Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics 3.5, 1113b7-8 and Free Choice.Susanne Bobzien - 2014 - In R. Salles P. Destree (ed.), What is up to us? Studies on Causality and Responsibility in Ancient Philosophy. Academia Verlag.
    ABSTRACT: This is a short companion piece to my ‘Found in Translation – Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics III.5 1113b7-8 and its Reception’ in which I examine in close textual analysis the philosophical question whether these two lines from the Nicomachean Ethics provide any evidence that Aristotle discussed free choice – as is not infrequently assumed. The result is that they do not, and that the claim that they do tends to be based on a mistranslation of the Greek. (There (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  2. Why There Are No Fresh Starts in Metaphysics Epsilon or Nicomachean Ethics III 5.Tim O'Keefe - manuscript
    Metaphysics Epsilon 2-3 and Nicomachean Ethics III 5 (1114b3-25) are often cited in favor of indeterminist interpretations of Aristotle. In Metaphysics Epsilon Aristotle denies that the coincidental has an aitia, and some (e.g., Sorabji) take this as a denial that coincidences have causes. In NE III 5 Aristotle says a person's actions and character must have their origin (archê) in the agent for him to be responsible for them. From this, some conclude that Aristotle thinks a (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Choice and Moral Responsibility in Nichomachean Ethics III 1–5.Susanne Bobzien - 2014 - In Ronald M. Polansky (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics. New York, New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 81-109.
    ABSTRACT: This paper serves two purposes: (i) it can be used by students as an introduction to chapters 1-5 of book iii of the NE; (ii) it suggests an answer to the unresolved question what overall objective this section of the NE has. The paper focuses primarily on Aristotle’s theory of what makes us responsible for our actions and character. After some preliminary observations about praise, blame and responsibility (Section 2), it sets out in detail how all the key (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  4.  73
    Aristotle, De Anima III.3-5.Seth Benardete - 1975 - Review of Metaphysics 28 (4):611 - 622.
    The physicist defines anger in terms of heart, blood, and heat; the dialectician says it is the desire to inflict pain in retaliation. Both give fairly sure signs for its recognition; but neither can show why these signs must go together and in what they can cohere. Aristotelian physics is presumably a way to avoid such a split, and whatever defects his account of perception or intellection suffers from cannot be traced to it. Phantasia, however, seems to be dialectically distinguished (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  5. Found in Translation: Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics 3.5, 1113b7-8 and its Reception.Susanne Bobzien - 2013 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 45:103-148.
    ABSTRACT: This paper is distinctly odd. It demonstrates what happens when an analytical philosopher and historian of philosophy tries their hand at the topic of reception. For a novice to this genre, it seemed advisable to start small. Rather than researching the reception of an author, book, chapter, section or paragraph, the focus of the paper is on one sentence: Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics 3.5, 1113b7-8. This sentence has markedly shaped scholarly and general opinion alike with regard to Aristotle’s (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Aristotle contra Plato on the Voluntariness of Vice: The Arguments of Nicomachean Ethics 3.5.Rachana Kamtekar - 2019 - Phronesis 64 (1):57-83.
  7.  15
    Monism in Aristotle’s Metaphysics I.3–5.Thomas Kjeller Johansen - unknown
    Scholars have often seen Parmenides as entirely opposed to earlier materialistic philosophy. In this paper I argue that what is more striking in Aristotle’s Metaphysics Book I is the degree of continuity that he sees between Parmenides and the material monists. I explore this coupling of Parmenides with the material monists to understand better what he takes to be distinctive and problematic with Parmenides’ monism.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Choice and Virtue in the Nicomachean Ethics.Alfred R. Mele - 1981 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 19 (4):405-423.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content: Choice and Virtue in the Nicomachean Ethics ALFRED R. MELE COM~rNTATORS ON THr Nicomachean Ethics (NE) have long been laboring under the influence of a serious misunderstanding of one of the key terms in Aristotle's moral philosophy and theory of action. This term is prohairesis (choice), the importance of which is indicated by Aristotle's assertions that choice is the proximate efficient cause of action (NE 6. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  9. Aporia 3-5.Frans De Haas - 2009 - In Michel Crubellier & André Laks (eds.), Aristotle's Metaphysics Beta: Symposium Aristotelicum. New York: Oxford University Press UK.
  10.  10
    Aquinas as a Commentator on De Anima 3.5.James Th Martin - 1993 - The Thomist 57 (4):621-640.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:AQUINAS AS A COMMENTATOR ON DE ANIMA 3.5 JAMES T. H. MARTIN St. John's University Jamaica, New York DOES ST. THOMAS AQUINAS in his commentary on De Anima 3.5 provide an acceptable gloss on Aristotle 's cryptic remarks about active mind? That is, can one accept.that what Aquinas says about active mind is what Aristotle meant but for some reason did not say? Many modern commentators, among (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  19
    On Aristotle’s Physics 5. [REVIEW]Leo J. Elders - 1997 - Review of Metaphysics 51 (2):444-445.
    Book 5 stands between the first four books of the Physics and Books 6, 7, and 8, which are traditionally called the treatise On motion. Simplicius, however, attaches it to the first four books on the principles of physical reality, describing it as a supplement to Book 3. David Ross, in his monumental Aristotle’s Physics prefers to consider Books 5, 6, and 8 a coherent group of pragmateiai on motion, while 7 is a comparatively isolated book, a view shared (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  59
    Aristotle on How Pleasure Perfects Activity (Nicomachean Ethics x.5 1175a29-b14): The Optimising-View.David Machek - 2022 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 104 (3):448-467.
    This article offers a new interpretation of Aristotle’s ambiguous and much-discussed claim that pleasure perfects activity. This interpretation provides an alternative to the two main competing readings of this claim in the scholarship: the addition-view, which envisages the perfection conferred by pleasure as an extra perfection beyond the perfection of activity itself; and the identity-view, according to which pleasure just is the perfect activity itself. The proposed interpretation departs from both these views in rejecting their assumption that pleasure cannot (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13.  9
    On Aristotle's "On the Soul 3.1-5". Simplicius & Of Simplicius - 2000 - Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. Edited by H. J. Blumenthal.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Colloquium 5: Aristotle’s Account of Agency in Physics III 3.Ursula Coope - 2004 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 20 (1):201-227.
  15.  70
    PS.-ARISTOTLE, DE MUNDO- J.C. Thom (ed.) Cosmic Order and Divine Power. Pseudo-Aristotle, On the Cosmos. (SAPERE 23.) Pp. x + 230. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2014. Cased, €49. ISBN: 978-3-16-152809-5. [REVIEW]Pavel Gregoric - 2016 - The Classical Review 66 (1):68-70.
  16. Aristotle devotes a significant portion of the Nicomachean Ethics and the Eudemian Ethics to the topic of virtue of character (ethike arete). In each workhe precedes his detailed treatment of the particular virtues of char-acter (courage, temperance, liberality, and so on) with a general account of ethical virtue (NE II–III. 5; EE II; cf. MM I. 5–19). The general account concludes, in both cases, with an extended discussion of voluntariness (to hekousion) and related notions (NE III. 1–5; EE II. 6–11; cf. MM I. 9–19). In order to understand Aristotle's views on voluntariness, we must first understand why he thinks that an account of the voluntary belongs in a treatise on virtue of character. [REVIEW]Susan Sauvé Meyer - 2006 - In Richard Kraut (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  48
    Aristotle on the Cause of Unity: the Argument of Metaphysics H.3–6.Christian Pfeiffer - forthcoming - Phronesis:1-35.
    I argue that Metaphysics H.6 is not an isolated chapter but the conclusion of an argument begun in H.3. This view will provide further and better arguments for the following view about long-standing interpretative debates: first, Aristotle provides a substantive account of the unity of the composite substance (although he also briefly addresses the unity of the form); second, neither Aristotle’s conception of matter nor his account of form changes between H.1–5 and H.6; and third, H does not (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  25
    What can Maimonides' understanding of the shamefulness of touch teach us about Aristotle's NE III.10, 1118b1–3?Mor Segev - 2023 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 31 (3):405-420.
    In NE III.10, 1118b1–3, Aristotle says that the “most shared of the senses is that according to which intemperance [comes about], and it would seem justifiably to be shameful, because it inheres [in us] not insofar as we are human beings, but insofar as we are animals”. This statement appears to describe the sense of touch as shameful. This may seem like a strange position for Aristotle to hold, since elsewhere he describes human touch as the most accurate (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  26
    Aristotle's Principle of Non-contradiction in Metaphysics Γ. 3.Ivan Stublić - 2007 - Filozofska Istrazivanja 27 (4):777-789.
    U Metafizici Γ. 3 počelo neproturječnosti otkriva se kao počelo mišljenja, ali i počelo svih bića. Prema tome, PN ima svoja dva aspekta – ontički i logički. Ti su aspekti izraženi različitim formulacijama počela neproturječnosti koje nalazimo u Γ. 3. Ne može se govoriti o primatu nekog od aspekata, jer su oni upućeni jedan na drugoga: mišljenje je mišljenje bića, a biće je ono što se u mišljenju misli. PN se ističe time da je najpostojanije počelo jer je ono nužno (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  73
    Hylémorphisme et causalité des intelligibles.Riccardo Chiaradonna - 2008 - Les Etudes Philosophiques 86 (3):379-397.
    Résumé — En Enn., VI, 3 [44], 5, Plotin fait usage de doctrines péripatéticiennes concernant la substance, l’inhérence et la prédication. Ces doctrines correspondent de manière frappante à l’interprétation anti-extensionaliste de la substance physique développée par Alexandre d’Aphrodise contre les thèses des commentateurs plus anciens . Le parallèle entre Plotin et Alexandre ne doit cependant pas conduire à penser que Plotin se borne à suivre les thèses du commentateur, et que leurs doctrines soient donc identiques. Plotin vise plutôt à transposer (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  21.  34
    Colloquium 3 Aristotle on the Voluntariness of Vice.Jay R. Elliott - 2021 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 36 (1):65-88.
    In Nicomachean Ethics III.5, Aristotle argues that virtue and vice are “up to us and voluntary.” Readers have long struggled to make sense of Aristotle’s arguments in this chapter and to explain how they cohere with the rest of his ethical project. Among the most influential lines of complaint is that the argument of III.5 appears to contradict his emphasis elsewhere on the power of upbringing to shape character, beginning in childhood. Scholars have developed two main interpretive approaches (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  25
    From Aristotle to Freud: Terence Cave's Recognitions and the subjective turn Terence Cave, Recognitions: A Study in Poetics . xii + 5 3 0 pp. [REVIEW]Christopher Butler - 1990 - Paragraph 13 (3):326-334.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Aristotle on Blaming Animals: Taking the Hardline Approach on Voluntary Action in the Nicomachean Ethics III.1–5.Paul E. Carron - 2019 - Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 23 (2):381-397.
    This essay offers a reconstruction of Aristotle’s account of the voluntary in the Nicomachean Ethics, arguing that the voluntary grounds one notion of responsibility with two levels, and therefore both rational and non-rational animals are responsible for voluntary actions. Aristotle makes no distinction between causal and moral responsibility in the NE; rather, voluntariness and prohairesis form different bases for responsibility and make possible different levels of responsibility, but both levels of responsibility fall within the ethical sphere and are (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. Aristotle's Two Intellects: A Modest Proposal.Victor Caston - 1999 - Phronesis 44 (3):199-227.
    In "De anima" 3.5, Aristotle argues for the existence of a second intellect, the so-called "Agent Intellect." The logical structure of his argument turns on a distinction between different types of soul, rather than different faculties within a given soul; and the attributes he assigns to the second species make it clear that his concern here -- as at the climax of his other great works, such as the "Metaphysics," the "Nicomachean" and the "Eudemian Ethics" -- is the difference (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  25. Aristotle on Fear's Contributions to the Virtue of Courage.Andrew Culbreth - forthcoming - In Ami Harbin (ed.), The Philosophy of Fear: Historical and Interdisciplinary Approaches. Bloomsbury.
    Aristotle characterizes the courageous person as someone who “will fear” frightening things in the right way, and someone who “will endure” terrifying things for the sake of the noble (NE III 7, 1115b11-13). Aristotle’s claims that the courageous person experiences fear have puzzled commentators for at least two reasons: first, Aristotle’s contention about the courageous person’s fear appears to be inconsistent with his claims, elsewhere in the ethical treatises, that the courageous person is fearless; second, if courageous (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Aristotle on Co-causes of One’s Dispositions.Filip Grgić - 2017 - Elenchos 38 (1-2):107-126.
    In this paper I offer a close reading of Aristotle’s argument in the Nicomachean Ethics 3.5.1114a31–b25 and try to show that despite considerable interpretive difficulties, some clear structure can nevertheless be discerned. While Aristotle’s main concern in this passage is to refute the so-called asymmetry thesis – the thesis that virtue is voluntary, but vice is not – there is much more in it than just a dialectical encounter. Aristotle wants to respond to a more general objection, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. The Nicomachean Ethics is framed by a beginning (NEI. 1–3) and an ending (NE X. 9) which, in rather different ways, communicate a single message: politics is the activity and branch of study that deals with the subject matter of the work. For us, ethics and politics signify two distinct, if overlapping, spheres. For Aristotle, there is just one sphere–politics–conceived in ethical terms. This startling truth is generally downplayed (if not totally ignored) in many presenta-tions of the Nicomachean ... [REVIEW]Malcolm Schofield - 2006 - In Richard Kraut (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 305.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  7
    “If There Were an Eye on the Back of the Heaven…” (Plotinus, Ennead 4.5,3 and 8).Andrei Cornea - 2007 - Laval Théologique et Philosophique 63 (3):459-472.
    Notre article analyse deux passages curieux du traité Sur les difficultés relatives à l’âme III. De la vision (Enn. IV.5,3 et 8), dans lesquels Plotin paraît concevoir la possibilité d’un autre univers, situé en dehors du nôtre. Or, cet autre univers doit rester inconnu pour nous à jamais, quand bien même il y aurait un « oeil placé sur le dos du Ciel » qui voudrait le voir. En outre, nous ne saurons même pas décider si cet univers existe ou (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  12
    Aristote et la question du monde: essai sur le contexte cosmologique et anthropologique de l'ontologie.Rémi Brague - 1988 - Paris: Presses Universitaires de France - PUF.
    Plusieurs aspects de la métaphysique, de la physique, de l'éthique et de la psychologie d’Aristote peuvent s'interpréter comme des affleurements d'un concept non-thématisé, celui d'être-dans-le-monde (l'in-der-welt-sein de heidegger). L’ensemble de la pensée grecque classique, même si elle était fascinée par l'ordre du cosmos, ne s'est guère demande ce que signifiait "être-dans-le-monde". L’expérience de la facticité, qui est un des traits fondamentaux de celle-ci, est ce qui permet à Aristote dans le protreptique, de justifier la vie philosophique ; mais il conçoit (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  79
    Aristotle on Circular Proof.Marko Malink - 2013 - Phronesis 58 (3):215-248.
    In Posterior Analytics 1.3, Aristotle advances three arguments against circular proof. The third argument relies on his discussion of circular proof in Prior Analytics 2.5. This is problematic because the two chapters seem to deal with two rather disparate conceptions of circular proof. In Posterior Analytics 1.3, Aristotle gives a purely propositional account of circular proof, whereas in Prior Analytics 2.5 he gives a more complex, syllogistic account. My aim is to show that these problems can be solved, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  31.  25
    Aristotle on the Sources of the Ethical Life by Sylvia Berryman.Elizabeth C. Shaw & Staff - 2020 - Review of Metaphysics 74 (2):381-383.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Aristotle on the Sources of the Ethical Life by Sylvia BerrymanElizabeth C. Shaw and Staff*BERRYMAN, Sylvia. Aristotle on the Sources of the Ethical Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019. vii + 220 pp. Cloth, $70.00—Berryman’s goals in Aristotle on the Sources of the Ethical Life are threefold: to establish that Aristotle practiced what contemporary philosophers call metaethics; to refute the idea that Aristotle (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  35
    Aristotle on Virtue as Mean State.Steven C. Skultety - 2022 - Ancient Philosophy 42 (2):493-508.
    Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Mean is often interpreted as a map of how character virtues are constituted. Taken in this way, critics argue that the Doctrine fails to describe accurately the specific virtues analyzed in books 3 to 5 of the Nicomachean Ethics. I argue that Aristotle does not offer the Doctrine as a map, but rather as a legend in terms of which any explication of a character virtue should be given. This interpretation resolves a number of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Nous in Aristotle's De Anima.Caleb Murray Cohoe - 2014 - Philosophy Compass 9 (9):594-604.
    I lay out and examine two sharply conflicting interpretations of Aristotle's claims about nous in the De Anima (DA). On the human separability approach, Aristotle is taken to have identified reasons for thinking that the intellect can, in some way, exist on its own. On the naturalist approach, the soul, including intellectual soul, is inseparable from the body of which it is the form. I discuss how proponents of each approach deal with the key texts from the DA, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  34.  65
    Passive Potentiality in the Physical Realm: Plotinus' Critique of Aristotle in Enneads II 5 [25].Cinzia Arruzza - 2011 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 93 (1):24-57.
    This article analyzes the status of passive potentiality of prime matter and sensible objects in Plotinus' Enneads. In particular, it will focus on Enneads II 5 [25] and confront it with other treatises, specifically Enneads III 6 [26]; II 6 [17]; VI 2 [43] and VI 3 [44]. It aims at offering a new interpretation of treatise 25 and at proposing a reconstruction of Plotinus' notion of change in the sensible realm that illustrates both his critique of Aristotle's notion (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  9
    The Voluntariness of Vice - Aristotle’s Anti-Socratic Argument -. 송유레 - 2019 - Cheolhak-Korean Journal of Philosophy 141:1-26.
    본 논문의 목적은 아리스토텔레스가 『니코마코스 윤리학』 3권 5장에서 초반부에 제시한 악덕의 자발성 논증을 고찰하는 것이다. 이 논증은 성격과 행동을 개념적으로 혼동했을 뿐만 아니라, 다른 곳에서 제시된 아리스토텔레스의 입장과 상충한다는 비판을 받았다. 이 논증에 선행하는 덕의 자발성 논증 또한 덕행의 자발성을 입증할 뿐인데 덕의 자발성을 결론으로 도출했다는 비판을 받았다. 우리는 이러한 비판에 맞서 우선 선행 논증에서 일종의 생략추론(enthymeme)이 사용되었고, 논증에서 생략된 전제는 3권 5장의 후속 논의에서 완전히 몰지각한 사람 외에 누구나 아는 것으로 간주된 것이라는 해석을 제안한다. 다음으로 우리는 악덕의 자발성 논증을 (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Aristotle’s Critique of Timaean Psychology.Jason W. Carter - 2017 - Rhizomata 5 (1):51-78.
    Of all the criticisms that Aristotle gives of his predecessors’ theories of soul in De anima I.3–5, none seems more unmotivated than the ones directed against the world soul of Plato’s Timaeus. Against the current scholarly consensus, I claim that the status of Aristotle’s criticisms is philosophical rather than eristical, and that they provide important philosophical reasons, independent of Phys. VIII.10 and Metaph. Λ.6, for believing that νοῦς is without spatial extension, and that its thinking is not a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37.  88
    “Listening to Reason”: The Role of Persuasion in Aristotle’s Account of Praise, Blame, and the Voluntary.Allen Speight - 2005 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 38 (3):213-225.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:“Listening to Reason”:The Role of Persuasion in Aristotle’s Account of Praise, Blame, and the VoluntaryAllen SpeightAristotle connects praise and blame closely to the voluntary, but the question of how his discussion of these terms should be construed more broadly in the context of a theory of responsibility has been much disputed. There are some well-known difficulties with the coherence of Aristotle's views in this regard: animals and (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38. Aristotle on Actions from Lack of Control.Jozef Müller - 2015 - Philosophers' Imprint 15.
    The paper defends three claims about Aristotle’s theory of uncontrolled actions (akrasia) in NE 7.3. First, I argue that the first part of NE 7.3 contains the description of the overall state of mind of the agent while she acts without control. Aristotle’s solution to the problem of uncontrolled action lies in the analogy between the uncontrolled agent and people who are drunk, mad, or asleep. This analogy is interpreted as meaning that the uncontrolled agent, while acting without (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  39.  48
    Dunaton as ‘Capable’ versus ‘Possible’ in Aristotle’s Metaphysics ix 3-4.Francisco Gonzalez - 2022 - Ancient Philosophy 42 (2):453-470.
    While Aristotle’s explicit focus in Metaphysics Theta 1-5 is dunamis in the sense of the ‘capability’ a thing has to originate change in something else or in itself qua other, practically all translators, when they arrive at chapter four, switch to ‘possible’ and ‘impossible’ as translations of dunaton and adunaton. Such a switch is neither defensible nor necessary and the relevance of Theta 4 is understood only without it.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40. Competing ways of life and ring-composition in NE x 6-8.Thornton Lockwood - 2014 - In Ronald M. Polansky (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics. New York, New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 350-369.
    The closing chapters of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics x are regularly described as “puzzling,” “extremely abrupt,” “awkward,” or “surprising” to readers. Whereas the previous nine books described—sometimes in lavish detail—the multifold ethical virtues of an embodied person situated within communities of family, friends, and fellow-citizens, NE x 6-8 extol the rarified, god-like and solitary existence of a sophos or sage (1179a32). The ethical virtues that take up approximately the first half of the Ethics describe moral exempla who experience fear fighting (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41. Nicomachean Revision in the Common Books: the Case of NE 6. (≈EE 5.) 2.Samuel H. Baker - 2024 - Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 63:193-236.
    We have good reason to believe that Nicomachean Ethics VI. 2 is a Nicomachean revision of an originally Eudemian text. Aristotle seems to have inserted lines 1139a31-b11 by means of a marginal note, which the first editor then mistakenly added in the wrong place, and I propose that we move these lines so that they follow the word κοινωνεῖν at 1139a20. The suggested note appears to be Nicomachean for several reasons but most importantly because it contains a desire-based account (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  1
    Aristotle’s Earliest Extant Manuscripts. New Doubts and Perspectives.Silvia Fazzo - 2024 - Aristotelica 6:93.
    This paper follows up on two previous contributions in Aristotelica (3 and 5) that focused on the early transmission of Phys. 250b13 as a case study. Here, the discussion broadens to general questions about the scribal hands behind Aristotle’s earliest manuscripts J (ms. Vindobonensis Phil. gr. 100) and E (ms. Parisinus gr. 1853), their roles in textual history, and their connections to the earliest reconstructable archetype. Current scholarship holds that while the sources of J and E overlap for the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Aristotle on the common sense.Pavel Gregoric - 2007 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    I. The framework. 1, Aristotle's project and methods. 2, The perceptual capacity of the soul. 3, The sensory apparatus. 4, The common sense and the related capacities -- II. The terminology. 1, Overlooked occurrences of the phrase 'common sense'. 2, De anima III.1 425a27. 3, De partibus animalium IV.10 686a31. 4, De memoria et reminiscentia 1 450a10. 5, De anima III.7 431b5. 6, Conclusions on the terminology -- III. Functions of the common sense. 1, Simultaneous perception and cross-modal binding. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  44. Pt. 1. ancient philosophy and faith, from athens to jerusalem: Lecture 1. introductIon to the problems and scope of philosophy ; lecture 2. the old testament, guest lecture / by Robert Oden ; lecture 3. the gospels of mark and Matthew, guest lecture / by Elizabeth mcnamer ; lecture 4. Paul, his world, guest lecture / by Elizabeth mcnamer ; lecture 5. presocratics, Ionian speculaton and eleatic metaphysics ; lecture 6. republic I, justice, power, and knowledge ; lecture 7. republic II-v, Paul and city ; lecture 8. republic VI-x, the architecture of reality ; lecture 9. Aristotle's metaphysical views ; lecture 10. Aristotle's politics, the golden mean and just rule, guest lecture. [REVIEW]Dennis Dalton, the Stoic Ideal Lecture 11Marcus Aurelius' Meditations & Lecture 12Augustine'S. City Of God - 2000 - In Darren Staloff, Louis Markos, Jeremy duQuesnay Adams, Phillip Cary, Dennis Dalton, Alan Charles Kors, Jeremy Shearmur, Robert C. Solomon, Robert Kane, Kathleen Marie Higgins, Mark W. Risjord & Douglas Kellner (eds.), Great Minds of the Western Intellectual Tradition, 3rd edition. Washington DC: The Great Courses.
  45.  36
    Aristotle on Thought and Feeling by Paula Gottlieb (review).Corinne Gartner - 2023 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 61 (4):703-705.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Aristotle on Thought and Feeling by Paula GottliebCorinne GartnerPaula Gottlieb. Aristotle on Thought and Feeling. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2021. Pp. 173. Hardback, $99.99.Paula Gottlieb's recent book is an illuminating, synoptic study of Aristotle's theory of human motivation, according to which his innovative notion of prohairesis (choice)—specifically, the virtuous agent's prohairesis—is the cornerstone. She argues against both Kantian-flavored readings, which prioritize reason's role in motivating (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  62
    Aristotle's Theory of Substance: The Categories and Metaphysics Zeta (review).Gareth B. Matthews - 2001 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 39 (3):437-438.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Journal of the History of Philosophy 39.3 (2001) 437-438 [Access article in PDF] Michael V. Wedin. Aristotle's Theory of Substance: The Categories and Metaphysics Zeta. Oxford Aristotle Studies. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000. Pp. xiii + 482. Cloth, $55.00. Michael Wedin has written the equivalent for Aristotle of what biblical scholars would call a "harmony of the gospels." It is a wonderfully rich and argumentatively (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  12
    Latin Aristotle commentaries.Charles H. Lohr - 1900 - Firenze: L.S. Olschki.
    Multi-volume work with 4 of the 5 volumes published. -/- -- 1. Medieval Authors (in two books) -- 2. Renaissance authors -- 3. Index initorum-index finium -- 5. Bibliography of secondary literature.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  6
    l'état pluriculturel et les droits aux différences: colloque organisé à Nouméa du 3 au 5 juillet 2002.Paul de Deckker & Jean Yves Faberon (eds.) - 2003 - Bruxelles: Bruylant.
    L'État pluriculturel est devenu un concept majeur du début du XXIe siècle, tant au Nord qu'au Sud de la planète. La plupart des États sont confrontés à l'éveil ou à l'affirmation des différentes cultures des différentes communautés en leur sein. Pour nos sociétés plurielles, voici venu le temps des droits aux différences. En réalité, devant ce phénomène universel, les positions de l'État varient : il aménage la coexistence des communautés culturelles ; ou il ne veut pas les connaître. Entre ces (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  59
    Does Aristotle's political theory rest on a 'blunder'?Joseph Chan - 1992 - History of Political Thought 13 (2):189-202.
    We may sum up the five roles which human beings might play in the existence of the polis in the following way: (1) Human nature plays the role of the inner principle of change which explains the type of human relation a polis takes (the polis as a type); (2) General patterns of human behaviours, together with patterns of societal conditions, play the role of material conditions which explain the variety of forms of polis; (3) Statesmen or politicians play the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  50.  33
    Substantial City: Reflections On Aristotle’s Politics.David Roochnik - 2010 - Polis 27 (2):275-291.
    Minimally, Aristotle’s account of the ‘city’ is isomorphic with his metaphysical doctrine of substance and teleological conception of nature. Maximally, his political theory depends on it. Part I explains what this means. Part II discusses the significant consequences the notion of a ‘substantial city’ has for Aristotle’s political theory. Part III suggests how this notion can be deployed to address the notorious question of whether the Politics forms a unified whole, or whether Books 4, 5 and 6 — (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 951