Results for 'Brian Conklin'

964 found
Order:
  1. Anderson, James and Rosenfeld, Edward (eds.), Talking Nets: An Oral History of Neural Networks. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998. Bahn, Paul G., The Cambridge Illustrated History of Prehistoric Art (= Cambridge Illustrated History). New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998. Barondes, Samuel H., Mood Genes: Hunting for Origins of Mania and Depression. New York. [REVIEW]Hugh Beyer, Karen Holtzblatt, D. L. Blank, Brian P. Bloomfield, Rod Coombs, David Knights, Dale Littler, Bob Carpenter & William E. Conklin - 2000 - Semiotica 128 (1/2):195-198.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. William E. Conklin, The Phenomenology of Modern Legal Discourse: The Juridical Production and the Disclosure of Suffering Reviewed by.Brian Hendrix - 2000 - Philosophy in Review 20 (5):329-331.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  50
    Windsor Yearbook of Access to Justice Vols. 1 and 2 William E. Conklin, Peter P. Mercer, Chris J. Wydrazynski, D. Charles James, and Brian M. Mazer, editors Windsor: University of Windsor, 1981 and 1982. Vol. 1, pp. 361; vol. 2, pp. 379. Subscription rate: $25.00 per volume. [REVIEW]Brenda M. Baker - 1984 - Dialogue 23 (4):734-738.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. (1 other version)Evolution of the Social Contract.Brian Skyrms - 1997 - Philosophy 72 (282):604-606.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   248 citations  
  5. .Brian Skyrms - 1980 - In The Role of Causal Factors in Rational Decision. Yale University Press.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   196 citations  
  6. If I Could Just Stop Loving You: Anti-Love Biotechnology and the Ethics of a Chemical Breakup.Brian D. Earp, Olga A. Wudarczyk, Anders Sandberg & Julian Savulescu - 2013 - American Journal of Bioethics 13 (11):3-17.
    “Love hurts”—as the saying goes—and a certain amount of pain and difficulty in intimate relationships is unavoidable. Sometimes it may even be beneficial, since adversity can lead to personal growth, self-discovery, and a range of other components of a life well-lived. But other times, love can be downright dangerous. It may bind a spouse to her domestic abuser, draw an unscrupulous adult toward sexual involvement with a child, put someone under the insidious spell of a cult leader, and even inspire (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  7. A signal detection theoretic approach for estimating metacognitive sensitivity from confidence ratings.Brian Maniscalco & Hakwan Lau - 2012 - Consciousness and Cognition 21 (1):422-430.
    How should we measure metacognitive sensitivity, i.e. the efficacy with which observers’ confidence ratings discriminate between their own correct and incorrect stimulus classifications? We argue that currently available methods are inadequate because they are influenced by factors such as response bias and type 1 sensitivity . Extending the signal detection theory approach of Galvin, Podd, Drga, and Whitmore , we propose a method of measuring type 2 sensitivity that is free from these confounds. We call our measure meta-d′, which reflects (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  8.  52
    The Career of Metaphor.Brian F. Bowdle & Dedre Gentner - 2005 - Psychological Review 112 (1):193-216.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  9. (1 other version)Theories of Justice.Brian Barry - 1991 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 20 (3):264-279.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   115 citations  
  10. Morality, fiction, and possibility.Brian Weatherson - 2004 - Philosophers' Imprint 4:1-27.
    Authors have a lot of leeway with regard to what they can make true in their story. In general, if the author says that p is true in the fiction we’re reading, we believe that p is true in that fiction. And if we’re playing along with the fictional game, we imagine that, along with everything else in the story, p is true. But there are exceptions to these general principles. Many authors, most notably Kendall Walton and Tamar Szabó Gendler, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  11. Repugnant Accuracy.Brian Talbot - 2019 - Noûs 53 (3):540-563.
    Accuracy‐first epistemology is an approach to formal epistemology which takes accuracy to be a measure of epistemic utility and attempts to vindicate norms of epistemic rationality by showing how conformity with them is beneficial. If accuracy‐first epistemology can actually vindicate any epistemic norms, it must adopt a plausible account of epistemic value. Any such account must avoid the epistemic version of Derek Parfit's “repugnant conclusion.” I argue that the only plausible way of doing so is to say that accurate credences (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  12. (1 other version)Intrinsic properties and combinatorial principles.Brian Weatherson - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (2):365-380.
    Three objections have recently been levelled at the analysis of intrinsicness offered by Rae Langton and David Lewis. While these objections do seem telling against the particular theory Langton and Lewis offer, they do not threaten the broader strategy Langton and Lewis adopt: defining intrinsicness in terms of combinatorial features of properties. I show how to amend their theory to overcome the objections without abandoning the strategy.
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   42 citations  
  13. The Demandingness of Morality: Toward a Reflective Equilibrium.Brian Berkey - 2016 - Philosophical Studies 173 (11):3015-3035.
    It is common for philosophers to reject otherwise plausible moral theories on the ground that they are objectionably demanding, and to endorse “Moderate” alternatives. I argue that while support can be found within the method of reflective equilibrium for Moderate moral principles of the kind that are often advocated, it is much more difficult than Moderates have supposed to provide support for the view that morality’s demands in circumstances like ours are also Moderate. Once we draw a clear distinction between (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  14. Luminous margins.Brian Weatherson - 2004 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82 (3):373 – 383.
    Timothy Williamson has recently argued that few mental states are luminous , meaning that to be in that state is to be in a position to know that you are in the state. His argument rests on the plausible principle that beliefs only count as knowledge if they are safely true. That is, any belief that could easily have been false is not a piece of knowledge. I argue that the form of the safety rule Williamson uses is inappropriate, and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  15. Indicative and subjunctive conditionals.Brian Weatherson - 2001 - Philosophical Quarterly 51 (203):200-216.
    This paper presents a new theory of the truth conditions for indicative conditionals. The theory allows us to give a fairly unified account of the semantics for indicative and subjunctive conditionals, though there remains a distinction between the two classes. Put simply, the idea behind the theory is that the distinction between the indicative and the subjunctive parallels the distinction between the necessary and the a priori. Since that distinction is best understood formally using the resources of two-dimensional modal logic, (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  16. Perceptual illusionism.Brian Cutter - 2021 - Analytic Philosophy 62 (4):396-417.
    Perceptual illusionism is the view that perceptual experience is, in general, radically illusory. That is, perceptual experience presents objects as having certain sensible properties and standing in certain sensible relations, but nothing in the subject’s environment has those properties or stands in those relations. This paper makes the case for perceptual illusionism by showing how a broad set of philosophical and scientific considerations converge to support illusionism about the full range of sensible properties and relations. After clarifying the illusionist thesis, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  17. Is God an abstract object?Brian Leftow - 1990 - Noûs 24 (4):581-598.
    Before Duns Scotus, most philosophers agreed that God is identical with His necessary intrinsic attributes--omnipotence, omniscience, etc. This Identity Thesis was a component of widely held doctrines of divine simplicity, which stated that God exemplifies no metaphysical distinctions, including that between subject and attribute. The Identity Thesis seems to render God an attribute, an abstract object. This paper shows that the Identity Thesis follows from a basic theistic belief and does not render God abstract. If also discusses how one might (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  18. The biological function of consciousness.Brian Earl - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5:69428.
    This research is an investigation of whether consciousness—one's ongoing experience—influences one's behavior and, if so, how. Analysis of the components, structure, properties, and temporal sequences of consciousness has established that, (1) contrary to one's intuitive understanding, consciousness does not have an active, executive role in determining behavior; (2) consciousness does have a biological function; and (3) consciousness is solely information in various forms. Consciousness is associated with a flexible response mechanism (FRM) for decision-making, planning, and generally responding in nonautomatic ways. (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  19. Molyneux’s Question and the History of Philosophy.Brian Glenney & Gabriele Ferretti (eds.) - 2020 - New York, USA: Routledge.
    In 1688 the Irish scientist and politician William Molyneux sent a letter to the philosopher John Locke. In it, he asked him a question: could someone who was born blind, and able to distinguish a globe and a cube by touch, be able to immediately distinguish and name these shapes by sight if given the ability to see? -/- The philosophical puzzle offered in Molyneux’s letter fascinated not only Locke, but major thinkers such as Leibniz, Berkeley, Diderot, Reid, and numerous (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  20.  35
    Knowledges in Context.Brian Wynne - 1991 - Science, Technology and Human Values 16 (1):111-121.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   36 citations  
  21.  92
    Collective Obligations and Demandingness Complaints.Brian Berkey - 2019 - Moral Philosophy and Politics 6 (1):113-132.
    It has been suggested that understanding our obligations to address large-scale moral problems such as global poverty and the threat of severe climate change as fundamentally collective can allow us to insist that a great deal must be done about these problems while denying that there are very demanding obligations, applying to either individuals or collectives, to contribute to addressing them. I argue that this strategy for limiting demandingness fails because those who endorse collective obligations to address large-scale moral problems (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  22.  35
    The owl and the electric encyclopedia.Brian Cantwell Smith - 1991 - Artificial Intelligence 47 (1-3):251-288.
  23. Tendency.Brian Pinkstone & Mervyn Hartwig - 2007 - In Mervyn Hartwig (ed.), Dictionary of critical realism. New York: Routledge. pp. 458--60.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  24. From Moral Realism to Axiarchism.Brian Cutter - 2023 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 47:73-101.
    Moral realism faces a well known genealogical debunking challenge. I argue that the moral realist’s best response may involve abandoning metaphysical naturalism in favor of some form of axiarchism—the view, very roughly, that the natural world is “ordered to the good.” Axiarchism comes in both theistic and non-theistic forms, but all forms agree that the natural world exists and has certain basic features because it is good for it to exist and have those features. I argue that theistic and non-theistic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  39
    Strange Weather, Again.Brian Wynne - 2010 - Theory, Culture and Society 27 (2-3):289-305.
    For a long time before the ‘climategate’ emails scandal of late 2009 which cast doubt on the propriety of science underpinning the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC), attention to climate change science and policy has focused solely upon the truth or falsity of the proposition that human behaviour is responsible for serious global risks from anthropogenic climate change. This article places such propositional concerns in the perspective of a different understanding of the relationships between scientific knowledge and public policy (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  26.  23
    Heart to Heart: A Relation-Alignment Approach to Emotion’s Social Effects.Brian Parkinson - 2021 - Emotion Review 13 (2):78-89.
    This article integrates arguments and evidence from my 2019 monograph Heart to Heart: How Your Emotions Affect Other People. The central claim is that emotions operate as processes of relation alignment that produce convergence, complementarity, or conflict between two or more people’s orientations to objects. In some cases, relation alignment involves strategic presentation of emotional information for the purpose of regulating other people’s behaviour. In other cases, emotions consolidate from socially distributed reciprocal adjustments of cues, signals, and emerging actions without (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  27. (1 other version)Nietzsche and the morality critics.Brian Leiter - 1997 - Ethics 107 (2):250-285.
  28. The asymmetric magnets problem.Brian Weatherson - 2006 - Philosophical Perspectives 20 (1):479–492.
    There are many controversial theses about intrinsicness and duplication. The first aim of this paper is to introduce a puzzle that shows that two of the uncontroversial sounding ones can’t both be true. The second aim is to suggest that the best way out of the puzzle requires sharpening some distinctions that are too frequently blurred, and adopting a fairly radical reconception of the ways things are.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  29. Against the Middle Ground: Why Russellian Monism is Unstable.Brian Cutter - 2019 - Analytic Philosophy 60 (2):109-129.
  30. Propositions and Multiple Indexing.Brian Rabern - 2012 - Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 1 (2):116-124.
    It is argued that propositions cannot be the compositional semantic values of sentences (in context) simply due to issues stemming from the compositional semantics of modal operators (or modal quantifiers). In particular, the fact that the arguments for double indexing generalize to multiple indexing exposes a fundamental tension in the default philosophical conception of semantic theory. This provides further motivation for making a distinction between two sentential semantic contents—what (Dummett 1973) called “ingredient sense” and “assertoric content”.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  31. Public Reason—Honesty, Not Sincerity.Brian Carey - 2017 - Journal of Political Philosophy 26 (1):47-64.
  32. Epistemicism, parasites, and vague names.Brian Weatherson - 2003 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (2):276 – 279.
    John Burgess has recently argued that Timothy Williamson’s attempts to avoid the objection that his theory of vagueness is based on an untenable metaphysics of content are unsuccessful. Burgess’s arguments are important, and largely correct, but there is a mistake in the discussion of one of the key examples. In this note I provide some alternative examples and use them to repair the mistaken section of the argument.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  33.  96
    Why Marxism Still Does Not Need Normative Theory.Brian Leiter - 2015 - Analyse & Kritik 37 (1-2):23-50.
    Marx did not have a normative theory, that is, a theory that purported to justify, discursively and systematically, his normative opinions, to show them to be rationally obligatory or objectively valid. In this regard, Marx was obviously not alone: almost everyone, including those who lead what are widely regarded as exemplary ‘moral’ lives, decide and act on the basis of normative intuitions and inclinations that fall far short of a theory. Yet self-proclaimed Marxists like G. A. Cohen and Jurgen Habermas (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  34. Pain and representation.Brian Cutter - 2017 - In Jennifer Corns (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Pain. New York: Routledge. pp. 290-39.
    This chapter focuses specifically on the case of pain. Despite traditional opposition to the representational thesis, the latter has won widespread assent. The most important early proponents of the representational thesis were David Armstrong and George Pitcher, both of whom held that pain is a form of perception. Following Armstrong and Pitcher, intentionalists have traditionally held that the experience of pain has a content with roughly the following form: there is a disturbance with such-and-such features at location L. Since the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  35.  13
    Introduction.Brian Davies - 2021 - New Blackfriars 102 (1101):601-606.
    New Blackfriars, Volume 102, Issue 1101, Page 601-606, September 2021.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36. Philosophy and disagreement.Brian Ribeiro - 2011 - Critica 43 (127):3-25.
    Disagreement as we find it in both the history and the contemporary practice of philosophy is an inadequately understood phenomenon. In this paper I outline and motivate the problem of disagreement, arguing that "hard cases" of disagreement confront us with an unresolved, and seemingly unresolvable, challenge to the rationality of philosophical discourse, thereby raising the specter of a worri-some form of metaphilosophical skepticism. A variety of responses and attempted evasions are considered, though none are found to be particularly satisfying: Thus, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  37. Reference from the first person perspective.Brian Loar - 1995 - Philosophical Issues 6:53-72.
  38. The Oxford handbook of Aquinas.Brian Davies & Eleonore Stump (eds.) - 2011 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    This Handbook is therefore meant to be useful to someone wanting to learn about Aquinas's philosophy and theology while also looking for help in philosophical ...
  39.  18
    Gesture, speech, and computational stages: A reply to McNeill.Brian Butterworth & Uri Hadar - 1989 - Psychological Review 96 (1):168-174.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  40.  10
    Becoming beside ourselves: the alphabet, ghosts, and distributed human being.Brian Rotman - 2008 - Durham: Duke University Press.
    Lettered selves and beyond -- The alphabetic body -- Gesture and non-alphabetic writing -- Technologized mathematics -- Parallel selves -- Ghost effects.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  41.  56
    Right and Wrong: Assessing Scalar Consequentialism.Brian McElwee - 2024 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 27 (5):707-724.
    Demoralising ethical theory involves eschewing the deontic categories of moral obligation, moral permissibility, and moral impermissibility from our ethical thought. In this paper, I evaluate the case made in Alastair Norcross’s recent book, _Morality By Degrees_ (2020), for a consequentialist version of such demoralisation. Norcross defends scalar consequentialism, a radical variant of consequentialism which restricts fundamental normative verdicts to a scalar ranking of available actions, ordered according to the goodness of the consequences they produce. Following an introductory Sect. 1, I (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  68
    Circumcision, Autonomy and Public Health.Brian D. Earp & Robert Darby - 2019 - Public Health Ethics 12 (1):64-81.
    Male circumcision—partial or total removal of the penile prepuce—has been proposed as a public health measure in Sub-Saharan Africa, based on the results of three randomized control trials showing a relative risk reduction of approximately 60 per cent for voluntary, adult male circumcision against female-to-male human immunodeficiency virus transmission in that context. More recently, long-time advocates of infant male circumcision have argued that these findings justify involuntary circumcision of babies and children in dissimilar public health environments, such as the USA, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43. Systematicity redux.Brian P. McLaughlin - 2009 - Synthese 170 (2):251-274.
    One of the main challenges that Jerry Fodor and Zenon Pylyshyn (Cognition 28:3–71, 1988) posed for any connectionist theory of cognitive architecture is to explain the systematicity of thought without implementing a Language of Thought (LOT) architecture. The systematicity challenge presents a dilemma: if connectionism cannot explain the systematicity of thought, then it fails to offer an adequate theory of cognitive architecture; and if it explains the systematicity of thought by implementing a LOT architecture, then it fails to offer an (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  44. Real freedom and basic income.Brian Barry - 1996 - Journal of Political Philosophy 4 (3):242–276.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  45.  49
    Justice, Caring, and Animal Liberation.Brian Luke - unknown
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  46.  24
    Serial retrieval processes in the recovery of order information.Brian McElree & Barbara A. Dosher - 1993 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 122 (3):291.
  47.  51
    Cybernetic Muse: Hannah Arendt on Automation, 1951–1958.Brian Simbirski - 2016 - Journal of the History of Ideas 77 (4):589-613.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  48.  40
    Speech Genres and Other Late Essays. [REVIEW]Brian Shaffer - 1988 - Substance 57:58–60.
  49. Universal and differential forces.Brian Ellis - 1963 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 14 (55):177-194.
  50.  29
    A field ion microscope study of some tungsten-rhenium alloys.Brian Ralph & D. G. Brandon - 1963 - Philosophical Magazine 8 (90):919-934.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
1 — 50 / 964