Results for 'Charles Juliet'

961 found
Order:
  1.  25
    Dependence and precarity in the platform economy.Juliet B. Schor, William Attwood-Charles, Mehmet Cansoy, Isak Ladegaard & Robert Wengronowitz - 2020 - Theory and Society 49 (5-6):833-861.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  2.  30
    Ethics of Consumption: The Good Life, Justice, and Global Stewardship.Luis A. Camacho, Colin Campbell, David A. Crocker, Eleonora Curlo, Herman E. Daly, Eliezer Diamond, Robert Goodland, Allen L. Hammond, Nathan Keyfitz, Robert E. Lane, Judith Lichtenberg, David Luban, James A. Nash, Martha C. Nussbaum, ThomasW Pogge, Mark Sagoff, Juliet B. Schor, Michael Schudson, Jerome M. Segal, Amartya Sen, Alan Strudler, Paul L. Wachtel, Paul E. Waggoner, David Wasserman & Charles K. Wilber (eds.) - 1997 - Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
    In this comprehensive collection of essays, most of which appear for the first time, eminent scholars from many disciplines—philosophy, economics, sociology, political science, demography, theology, history, and social psychology—examine the causes, nature, and consequences of present-day consumption patterns in the United States and throughout the world.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  3.  10
    Steiner versus Wittgenstein: Remarks on Differing Views of Mathematical Truth.Charles Sayward - 2010 - Theoria 20 (3):347-352.
    Mark Steiner criticizes some remarks Wittgenstein makes about Gödel. Steiner takes Wittgenstein to be disputing a mathematical result. The paper argues that Wittgenstein does no such thing. The contrast between the realist and the demonstrativist concerning mathematical truth is examined. Wittgenstein is held to side with neither camp. Rather, his point is that a realist argument is inconclusive.
    No categories
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  33
    Steiner versus Wittgenstein: Remarks on Differing Views of Mathematical Truth.Charles Sayward - 2010 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 20 (3):347-352.
    Mark Steiner criticizes some remarks Wittgenstein makes about Gödel. Steiner takes Wittgenstein to be disputing a mathematical result. The paper argues that Wittgenstein does no such thing. The contrast between the realist and the demonstrativist concerning mathematical truth is examined. Wittgenstein is held to side with neither camp. Rather, his point is that a realist argument is inconclusive.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  23
    Editors' Introduction.Peter Atterton & Sean Lawrence - 2022 - Levinas Studies 16 (1):1-6.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Editors’ Introduction“Between the Bible and the Philosophers”: ShakespearePeter Atterton (bio) and Sean Lawrence (bio)It is not clear when Levinas first read Shakespeare, but we do have some clues. The first complete translation of Shakespeare’s works into Russian, Levinas’s mother tongue, appeared between 1865 and 1868. These volumes doubtless graced the shelves of his family’s bookstore in Kovno (now Kaunas), in Lithuania, then part of the Russian empire. Kovno served (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6. Conspiracy Theories, Deplorables, and Defectibility: A Reply to Patrick Stokes.Charles R. Pigden - 2018 - In Matthew R. X. Dentith (ed.), Taking Conspiracy Theories Seriously. Rowman & Littlefield International. pp. 203-215.
    Patrick Stokes has argued that although many conspiracy theories are true, we should reject the policy of particularism (that is, the policy of investigating conspiracy theories if they are plausible and believing them if that is what the evidence suggests) and should instead adopt a policy of principled skepticism, subjecting conspiracy theories – or at least the kinds of theories that are generally derided as such – to much higher epistemic standards than their non-conspiratorial rivals, and believing them only if (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  7. The Question of Ethics: Nietzsche, Foucault, Heidegger.Charles E. SCOTT - 1990 - Indiana University Press.
    "... stimulating and insightful... a thoroughly researched and timely contribution to the secondary literature of ethics... " —Library Journal "His important new work establishes Scott... as one of the foremost interpreters of the Continental philosophical tradition of the US.... Necessary for anyone working in ethics or the Continental tradition." —Choice "... a provocative discourse on the consequences of the ethical in the thought of Nietzsche, Foucault, and Heidegger." —The Journal of Religion Charles E. Scott's challenging book advances the broad (...)
  8. (3 other versions)Ethics and Language.Charles L. Stevenson - 1945 - Ethics 55 (3):209-215.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   151 citations  
  9.  44
    Elder-Vass's move and Giddens's call.Charles Varela - 2007 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 37 (2):201–210.
    David Elder-Vass's “For Emergence: refining Archer's account of social structure,” is the latest of a number of papers which together constitute a family quarrel in the cognitive space After Postmodernism among realist social scientists. In the case under examination here in “Elder-Vass's Move and Giddens's Call”, the concern is the structure and agency problem in the social sciences. The debate continuing in Elder-Vass's paper represents the proponents of the resurrection of Durkheim's social realism under the auspices of Bhaskar's Transcendental Realism; (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  10.  75
    The semantic paradoxes: Some second thoughts.Charles Chihara - 1984 - Philosophical Studies 45 (2):223 - 229.
  11.  95
    A theorem concerning syntactical treatments of nonidealized belief.Charles B. Cross - 2001 - Synthese 129 (3):335 - 341.
    [IMPORTANT CORRECTION - See end of abstract.] In Syntactical Treatments of Modality, with Corollaries on Reflexion Principles and Finite Axiomatizability, Acta Philosophica Fennica 16 (1963), 153–167, Richard Montague shows that the use of a single syntactic predicate (with a context-independent semantic value) to represent modalities of alethic necessity and idealized knowledge leads to inconsistency. In A Note on Syntactical Treatments of Modality, Synthese 44 (1980), 391–395, Richmond Thomason obtains a similar impossibility result for idealized belief: under a syntactical treatment of (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  12. (1 other version)Actual Causation by Probabilistic Active Paths.Charles R. Twardy & Kevin B. Korb - 2011 - Philosophy of Science 78 (5):900-913.
    We present a probabilistic extension to active path analyses of token causation (Halpern & Pearl 2001, forthcoming; Hitchcock 2001). The extension uses the generalized notion of intervention presented in (Korb et al. 2004): we allow an intervention to set any probability distribution over the intervention variables, not just a single value. The resulting account can handle a wide range of examples. We do not claim the account is complete --- only that it fills an obvious gap in previous active-path approaches. (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  13.  46
    The subject of the scourge: Questioning implications from natural embryo loss.Charles C. Camosy - 2008 - American Journal of Bioethics 8 (7):20 – 21.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  14.  86
    Plato on rhetoric and poetry.Charles Griswold - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  15.  95
    Modality, analogy, and ideal experiments according to C. S. Peirce.Charles G. Morgan - 1979 - Synthese 41 (1):65 - 83.
  16.  89
    (1 other version)Esthetics and the theory of signs.Charles W. Morris - 1939 - Erkenntnis 8 (1):131-150.
  17. Relativising the ideal observer theory.Charles Taliaferro - 1988 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49 (1):123-138.
    THIS PAPER IS A DEFENSE OF AN OBJECTIVIST VERSION OF\nRODERICK FIRTH'S IDEAL OBSERVER THEORY OF ETHICS. IT\nANALYZES AND CRITIQUES A POWERFUL, RELATIVIZED IDEAL\nOBSERVER THEORY ADVANCED BY THOMAS CARSON.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  18.  45
    (2 other versions)The spirit of laws.Charles de Secondat Montesquieu & Jean Le Rond D' Alembert - 1902 - London,: G. Bell and sons. Edited by Jean Le Rond D' Alembert, J. V. Prichard & [From Old Catalog].
    Of laws in general -- Of laws directly derived from the nature of government -- Of the principles of the three kinds of government -- That the laws of education ought to be relative to the principles of government -- That the laws given by the legislator ought to be relative to the nature of government -- Consquences of the principles of different governments, with respect to the simplicity of civil and criminal laws, the form of judgements, and inflicting of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  19.  11
    Narrative prose generation.Charles B. Callaway & James C. Lester - 2002 - Artificial Intelligence 139 (2):213-252.
  20.  39
    (1 other version)Interpretative Pros Hen Pluralism: from Computer-Mediated Colonization to a Pluralistic Intercultural Digital Ethics.Charles Melvin Ess - 2020 - Philosophy and Technology 33 (4):551-569.
    Intercultural Digital Ethics faces the central challenge of how to develop a global IDE that can endorse and defend some set of universal ethical norms, principles, frameworks, etc. alongside sustaining local, culturally variable identities, traditions, practices, norms, and so on. I explicate interpretive pros hen ethical pluralism ) emerging in the late 1990s and into the twenty-first century in response to this general problem and its correlates, including conflicts generated by “computer-mediated colonization” that imposed homogenous values, communication styles, and so (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  21. On choosing hell.Charles Seymour - 1997 - Religious Studies 33 (3):249-266.
    Most contemporary philosophers who defend the compatibility of hell with the divine goodness do so by arguing that the damned freely choose hell. Thomas Talbott denies that such a choice is possible, on the grounds that God in his goodness would remove any 'ignorance, deception, or bondage to desire' which would motivate a person to choose eternal misery. My strategy is to turn the tables on Talbott and ask why God would not remove the motives we have for any sin (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  22.  60
    Biological structure and embodied human agency: The problem of instinctivism.Charles R. Varela - 2003 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 33 (1):95–122.
    Hebb's conception of instinctive behavior permits the conclusion that it is just not human nature to be instinctive: while the ant brain is built for instinctive behavior, the human brain is built for intelligent behavior. Since drives cannot be instincts, even when a human driver becomes driven, human motives are not instincts either. This understanding allows us to dismiss the determinism of the old instinctivism found in Freud's bio-psychological unconscious, and of the new instinctivism, exemplified by Wilson's sociobiology. The latter (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  23.  18
    Journal of researches.Charles Darwin - 1839 - New York: New York University Press.
    Are they needed? To be sure. The Darwinian industry, industrious though it is, has failed to provide texts of more than a handful of Darwin's books. If you want to know what Darwin said about barnacles (still an essential reference to cirripedists, apart from any historical importance) you are forced to search shelves, or wait while someone does it for you; some have been in print for a century; various reprints have appeared and since vanished." -Eric Korn,Times Literary Supplement (...) Robert Darwin (1880-1882) has been widely recognized since his own time as one of the most influential writers in the history of Western thought. His books were widely read by specialists and the general public, and his influence had been extended by almost continuous public debate over the last 130 years. New York University Press' edition makes it possible for the first time to review Darwin's public literary output as a whole, plus his scientific journal articles, his private notebooks, and his correspondence. This is the first complete edition containing all of Darwin's published books, featuring definitive texts recording original paginations with Darwin's indexes retained. All illustrations and plates are presented, inclucing 82 color plates of birds and mammals and several folding maps and plates. The set also features a general introduction and index, and textural introductions in each volume. (shrink)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  24. Kant and information ethics.Charles Ess & May Thorseth - 2008 - Ethics and Information Technology 10 (4):205-211.
    We begin with our reasons for seeking to bring Kant to bear on contemporary information and computing ethics (ICE). We highlight what each contributor to this special issue draws from Kant and then applies to contemporary matters in ICE. We conclude with a summary of what these chapters individually and collectively tell us about Kant’s continuing relevance to these contemporary matters – specifically, with regard to the issues of building trust online and regulating the Internet; how far discourse contributing to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  25. Plato and Forgiveness.Charles L. Griswold - 2007 - Ancient Philosophy 27 (2):269-287.
  26.  74
    Why we need descriptive psychology.Charles Siewert - 2023 - European Journal of Philosophy 31 (2):341-357.
    This article defends the thesis that in theorizing about the mind we need to accord first-person (“introspective” or “reflective”) judgments about experience a “selective provisional trust.” Such an approach can form part of a descriptive psychology. It is here so employed to evaluate some influential interpretations of research on attention to conclude that—despite what conventional wisdom suggests—an “introspection-positive” policy actually offers us a better critical perspective than its contrary. What supposedly teaches us the worthlessness of introspection actually shows us why (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  41
    The impossibility of which naturalism? A response and a reply.Charles R. Varela - 2002 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 32 (1):105–111.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  28.  11
    Reinhold Niebuhr: His Religious, Social, and Political Thought.Charles W. Kegley & Robert W. Bretall - 1957 - Philosophical Review 66 (3):421.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  29. Arithmetic and the categories.Charles Parsons - 1984 - Topoi 3 (2):109-121.
  30. Man on His Nature.Charles Sherrington - 1956 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 7 (27):268-269.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  31.  13
    The approximate number system represents magnitude and precision.Charles R. Gallistel - 2021 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 44.
    Numbers are symbols manipulated in accord with the axioms of arithmetic. They sometimes represent discrete and continuous quantities, but they are often simply names. Brains, including insect brains, represent the rational numbers with a fixed-point data type, consisting of a significand and an exponent, thereby conveying both magnitude and precision.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  32. Quine on the Philosophy of Mathematics.Charles Parsons - 1986 - In Lewis Edwin Hahn & Paul Arthur Schilpp (eds.), The Philosophy of W.V. Quine. Chicago: Open Court. pp. 369-395.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  33. Scepticism.Charles Larmore - 1998 - In Daniel Garber & Michael Ayers (eds.), The Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 2--145.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  34. Ephesians and Colossians.Charles H. Talbert - 2007
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  35.  33
    The future of ethics and education: philosophy in a time of existential crises.Charles C. Verharen - 2020 - Ethics and Education 15 (3):371-389.
    Philosophy confronts two existential crises: the threats to its existence from scientists like Stephen Hawking who claim that philosophy is dead; and the threat to life itself from catastrophic climate change. The essay’s first theoretical part critiques Nietzsche’s claim that philosophy’s primary function is to guarantee the future of life. The essay’s second practical part claims that philosophy must meet the challenge of life’s extinction through a revised model for ethics in education. Taking its start from recent conceptualizations of philosophy (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36. The Word Before The Powers: An Ethic of Preaching.Charles L. Campbell - 2002
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  37. The afterlife myth in Plato's gorgias.Charles B. Daniels - 1992 - Journal of Value Inquiry 26 (2):271-279.
  38. Metaphorical semeiotic referents: Dyadic objects.Carl R. Hausman - 2007 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 43 (2):276-287.
    : When language is expressed metaphorically, metaphors seem to "say" something that has never seen said before. Some of them seem to express insights. What then are the constraints on their interpretations? Charles Peirce's semeiotic suggests a way to answer the question. Crucial to the answer is Peirce's account of semeiotic objects as two-fold, one side, the dynamic or "real" object to be interpreted, the other side, the immediate object, which is the dynamic object that has been interpreted. The (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  42
    Felicitometry: Measuring the 'quality' in quality of life.Charles Kowalski, Steven Pennell & Amiram Vinokur - 2008 - Bioethics 22 (6):307–313.
    Following Bernheim,1 we examine aspects of 'felicitometrics,'2 the measurement of the 'quality' term in Quality of Life (QOL). Bernheim argued that overall QOL is best captured as the Gestalt3 of a global self-assessment and suggested that the Anamnestic Comparative Self Assessment (ACSA) approach, in which subjects' memories of the best and worst times of their lives are used to anchor a Visual Analog Scale (VAS), provided a serious answer to the serious question, 'How have you been?' Bernheim compares and contrasts (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40. Quasi-orderings and population ethics.Charles Blackorby, Walter Bossert & David Donaldson - 1996 - Social Choice and Welfare 13 (2):129--150.
    Population ethics contains several principles that avoid the repugnant conclusion. These rules rank all possible alternatives, leaving no room for moral ambiguity. Building on a suggestion of Parfit, this paper characterizes principles that provide incomplete but ethically attractive rankings of alternatives with different population sizes. All of them rank same-number alternatives with generalized utilitarianism.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  41. Does the law of excluded middle require bivalence?Charles Sayward - 1989 - Erkenntnis 31 (1):129 - 137.
    Determining whether the law of excluded middle requires bivalence depends upon whether we are talking about sentences or propositions. If we are talking about sentences, neither side has a decisive case. If we are talking of propositions, there is a strong argument on the side of those who say the excluded middle does require bivalence. I argue that all challenges to this argument can be met.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  42.  31
    Determinism and the recovery of human agency: The embodying of persons.Charles Varela - 1999 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 29 (4):385–402.
    Intending the recovery of human agency with the aid of theories of human socio-cultural life, Turner and Harre do so however in terms of conflicting conceptions of the embodying of persons. Consequently, their theories share the problem of determinism and embodied human agency. This is the problem of the proper location of agency with regard to the person, the body, and society. These theories then are in fundamental conflict on exactly this issue of the proper location of agency. Turner's thesis (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  41
    Brandt's questions about emotive ethics.Charles L. Stevenson - 1950 - Philosophical Review 59 (4):528-534.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  28
    Doctors should be morally common: a reply to Rosamond Rhodes.Charles Foster - 2019 - Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (12):784-785.
    ​Rosamond Rhodes contends, by reference to seven examples, that medical ethics is distinctly different from non-medical ethics. Each of those examples, on proper examination, illustrates precisely the opposite contention. It is clear not only that medical ethics relies on the same principles as non-medical (and indeed non-professional) ethics, but that it should so rely. A distinctively medical ethics would be dangerous: it would divorce ethical medical decision-making from the patients whom medicine exists to serve.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  45.  38
    Meaning, metaphysics, and mystics: Thaddeus Metz’s God, Soul and the Meaning of Life.Charles Taliaferro - 2021 - International Journal of Philosophy and Theology 82 (4-5):361-365.
    ABSTRACT Thaddeus Metz is probably the leading expert on the meaning of life. His latest book admirably displays his intellectual agility and fairness: arguments, counter-arguments, examples and counter-examples come in wave after wave that may compel most of us to slow down the pace of reading. If you have ever had the delight of interacting with Professor Metz at a conference, you know his irrepressible energy and love for debate. In this brief essay, I challenge some of Metz’s terminology, raise (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  16
    Uses of equipoise in discussions of the ethics of randomized controlled trials of COVID-19 therapies.Charles Weijer & Hayden P. Nix - 2021 - BMC Medical Ethics 22 (1):1-8.
    BackgroundEarly in the COVID-19 pandemic, the urgent need to discover effective therapies for COVID-19 prompted questions about the ethical problem of randomization along with its widely accepted solution: equipoise. In this scoping review, uses of equipoise in discussions of randomized controlled trials of COVID-19 therapies are evaluated to answer three questions. First, how has equipoise been applied to COVID-19 research? Second, has equipoise been employed accurately? And third, do concerns about equipoise pose a barrier to the ethical conduct of COVID-19 (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  24
    A Stoic Ethics for Attention.Charles Brittain - 2021 - Rhizomata 9 (2):224-246.
    Seneca’s Letters sketch a theory of attentive action according to which distraction is caused by inconsistent beliefs about values, such that the degree of an agent’s attention to an endorsed action is proportionate to the consistency of her beliefs about value, i. e. her proximity to virtue. The agent’s activity of attentive action is co-ordinated with a state of alertness to her interests, which accordingly triggers switches in attention that sustain the endorsed action in single-minded agents or cause distraction if (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48. On Hartshorne's formulation of the ontological argument: A rejoinder.Charles Hartshorne - 1945 - Philosophical Review 54 (1):63 - 65.
  49.  6
    Personalised revision of `failed' questions.Charles Antaki - 2002 - Discourse Studies 4 (4):411-428.
    In interviews, it may happen that a respondent gives an answer which seems well formatted, but is not receipted as acceptable by the interviewer. In this article I examine one way in which interviewers display their diagnosis of the problem and act to bring about its solution. In the cases I describe, the interviewers defer revision of the question until they have established a new, more personalized basis for it, informed by their knowledge of the respondents' circumstances. There are three (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  50.  27
    Henry of Harclay on Knowing Many Things at Once.Charles Bolyard - 2014 - Recherches de Theologie Et Philosophie Medievales 81 (1):75-93.
1 — 50 / 961