Results for 'Common belief'

970 found
Order:
  1. Georg Meggle.Common Belief - 2003 - In Matti Sintonen, Petri Ylikoski & Kaarlo Miller (eds.), Realism in Action: Essays in the Philosophy of the Social Sciences. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 321--251.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Common belief with the logic of individual belief.Giacomo Bonanno - 2000 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 46 (1):49-52.
    The logic of common belief does not always reflect that of individual beliefs. In particular, even when the individual belief operators satisfy the KD45 logic, the common belief operator may fail to satisfy axiom 5. That is, it can happen that neither is A commonly believed nor is it common belief that A is not commonly believed. We identify the intersubjective restrictions on individual beliefs that are incorporated in axiom 5 for common (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  3.  13
    Common Beliefs and Common Sense in Educational Policy and Practice.Avi I. Mintz - 2010 - Philosophy of Education 66:177-179.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. On the logic of common belief and common knowledge.Luc Lismont & Philippe Mongin - 1994 - Theory and Decision 37 (1):75-106.
    The paper surveys the currently available axiomatizations of common belief (CB) and common knowledge (CK) by means of modal propositional logics. (Throughout, knowledge- whether individual or common- is defined as true belief.) Section 1 introduces the formal method of axiomatization followed by epistemic logicians, especially the syntax-semantics distinction, and the notion of a soundness and completeness theorem. Section 2 explains the syntactical concepts, while briefly discussing their motivations. Two standard semantic constructions, Kripke structures and neighbourhood (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  5.  72
    Iterative and fixed point common belief.Aviad Heifetz - 1999 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 28 (1):61-79.
    We define infinitary extensions to classical epistemic logic systems, and add also a common belief modality, axiomatized in a finitary, fixed-point manner. In the infinitary K system, common belief turns to be provably equivalent to the conjunction of all the finite levels of mutual belief. In contrast, in the infinitary monotonic system, common belief implies every transfinite level of mutual belief but is never implied by it. We conclude that the fixed-point notion (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  6.  51
    On the Logic of Common Belief.Giacomo Bonanno - 1996 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 42 (1):305-311.
    We investigate an axiomatization of the notion of common belief that makes use of no rules of inference and highlight the property of the set of accessibility relations that characterizes each axiom.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  7. The Topology of Common Belief.Levan Uridia & David Pearce - 2015 - In Emiliano Lorini & Andreas Herzig (eds.), The Cognitive Foundations of Group Attitudes and Social Interaction. Cham: Springer.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  36
    A sound interpretation of minimality properties of common belief in minimal semantics.Vittoriomanuele Ferrante - 1996 - Theory and Decision 41 (2):179-185.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  68
    Strong Completeness Theorems for Weak Logics of Common Belief.Lismont Luc & Mongin Philippe - 2003 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 32 (2):115-137.
    We show that several logics of common belief and common knowledge are not only complete, but also strongly complete, hence compact. These logics involve a weakened monotonicity axiom, and no other restriction on individual belief. The semantics is of the ordinary fixed-point type.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  10.  14
    A non-minimal but very weak axiomatization of common belief.Luc Lismont & Philippe Mongin - 1994 - Artificial Intelligence 70 (1-2):363-374.
  11.  52
    How Much Common Belief is Necessary for Convention?Hyun Song Shin & Timothy Williamson - 1999 - In Cristina Bicchieri, Richard C. Jeffrey & Brian Skyrms (eds.), The logic of strategy. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  49
    When corpus analysis refutes common beliefs: the case of interpolation in European Portuguese dialects.Catarina Magro - 2010 - Corpus 9:115-136.
    Quand l’analyse de corpus réfute des idées reçues : le cas de l’interpolation dans des dialectes du portugais européenCet article analyse l’interpolation (c’est-à-dire la possibilité d’occurrence d’un proclitique séparé du verbe) comme un trait des dialectes du portugais européen (PE) contemporain, tel qu’il est montré par les données fournies par le Syntax-oriented Corpus of Portuguese Dialects – CORDIAL-SIN. Les objectifs de cet étude sont les suivants : (i) décrire les propriétés des constructions d’interpolation dans les dialectes contemporains du PE ; (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Colin oakes/interpretations of intuitionist logic in non-normal modal logics 47–60 Aviad heifetz/iterative and fixed point common belief 61–79 dw mertz/the logic of instance ontology 81–111. [REVIEW]Richard Bradley, Roya Sorensen, Mirror Notation & Philip Kremer - 1999 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 28:661-662.
  14.  64
    Beliefs and Testimony as Social Evidence: Epistemic Egoism, Epistemic Universalism, and Common Consent Arguments.Joshua Rollins - 2015 - Philosophy Compass 10 (1):78-90.
    Until recently, epistemology was largely caught in the grips of an epistemically unrealistic radical epistemological individualism on which the beliefs and testimony of others were of virtually no epistemic significance. Thankfully, epistemologists have bucked the individualist trend, acknowledging that one person's belief or testimony that P might offer another person prima facie epistemic reasons – or social evidence as I call it – to believe P. In this paper, I discuss the possibility and conditions under which beliefs and testimony (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  29
    Belief formation in a signaling game without common prior: an experiment.Alex Possajennikov - 2018 - Theory and Decision 84 (3):483-505.
    Using belief elicitation, the paper investigates the process of belief formation and evolution in a signaling game in which a common prior is not induced. Both prior and posterior beliefs of Receivers about Senders’ types are elicited, as well as beliefs of Senders about Receivers’ strategies. In the experiment, subjects often start with diffuse uniform beliefs and update them in view of observations. However, the speed of updating is influenced by the strength of initial beliefs. An interesting (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16.  46
    Belief and delusion: Their common origin but different course of development.Hermann Lenz - 1983 - Zygon 18 (2):117-137.
    Comparing the experiences of mystics and victims of delusion we find very similar states of conditions: an experience of abnormal significance, pseudohallucinations, the sense of mission, the suspension of time, extremes of mood, and the sudden and passive appearance. Only the subsequent course of life of those having the experiences makes it possible to distinguish between belief and delusion. The criteria are simple: we find hope and doubt only in relation to mystical experience whereas in delusion we find a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17.  25
    Common Core/Diversity Dilemma, Agatheism and the Epistemology of Religious Belief.Thomas D. Senor - 2016 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 8 (4):213--226.
    The essay “The Common-Core/Diversity Dilemma: Revisions of Humean Thought, New Empirical Research, and the Limits of Rational Religious Belief‘ is a bold argument for the irrationality of “first-order‘ religious belief. However, unlike those associated with “New Atheism,‘ the paper’s authors Branden Thornhill-Miller and Peter Millican claim both that there are prospects for rational “second-order‘ religious belief and that religious belief and practice can play a positive role in human life. In response to Thornhill-Miller and Millican, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  13
    Common Sense and Basic Beliefs: from Certainty to Happiness.Herman Parret - 1983 - In On Believing. De la Croyance. Epistemological and Semiotic Approaches. De Gruyter. pp. 216-228.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Common Consent Arguments for Belief in God.Marcus Hunt - 2022 - Dialogue: A Journal of Philosophy and Religion (58):17-22.
    A popular introduction to common consent arguments for belief in God.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  63
    Between reason and common sense. On the very idea of necessary (though unwarranted) belief.Daniel A. Kaufman - 2005 - Philosophical Investigations 28 (2):134–158.
    This essay is intended as a companion‐piece to my article, “Reality in Common Sense: Reflections on Realism and Anti‐Realism from a ‘Common Sense Naturalist’ Perspective.” (Philosophical Investigations, Vol. 25, No. 4 (October 2002). It explores the epistemological dimension of the Common Sense Naturalism that I developed in that earlier, predominantly metaphysical essay; a position that combines the views of David Hume, Thomas Reid, and the Wittgenstein of On Certainty. My ultimate aim is to produce a comprehensive philosophy (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  24
    Intuitionistic common knowledge or belief.Gerhard Jäger & Michel Marti - 2016 - Journal of Applied Logic 18:150-163.
  22.  32
    Critical Reflection and Common-Sense Beliefs.Francesco Poggiani - 2017 - European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 9 (2).
    I explore the connection between pragmatism and common sense by reflecting upon two seemingly contrasting Peircean remarks about the pragmatic method: (a) its “basis on the doctrine of common sense” and (b) the recommendation that a proposition p be explicated in light of critical, deliberate, or “self-controlled” conduct ensuing from a belief that p. I show that Peirce’s focus on phenomena of self-control is situated within his broader interest in the nature of reasoning. The “secret of rational (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Simulation constraints, afterlife beliefs, and common-sense dualism.V. Antony Michael - 2006 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (5):462-463.
    Simulation constraints cannot help in explaining afterlife beliefs in general because belief in an afterlife is a precondition for running a simulation. Instead, an explanation may be found by examining more deeply our common-sense dualistic conception of the mind or soul.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  24. The Common-Core/Diversity Dilemma: Revisions of Humean thought, New Empirical Research, and the Limits of Rational Religious Belief.Branden Thornhill-Miller & Peter Millican - 2015 - European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 7 (1):1--49.
    This paper is the product of an interdisciplinary, interreligious dialogue aiming to outline some of the possibilities and rational limits of supernatural religious belief, in the light of a critique of David Hume’s familiar sceptical arguments -- including a rejection of his famous Maxim on miracles -- combined with a range of striking recent empirical research. The Humean nexus leads us to the formulation of a new ”Common-Core/Diversity Dilemma’, which suggests that the contradictions between different religious belief (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25. Hume natural beliefs and Reid principles of common-sense.E. Griffincollart - 1976 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 30 (115):126-142.
  26.  40
    Common Sense Beliefs about the Central Self, Moral Character, and the Brain.Diego Fernandez-Duque & Barry Schwartz - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
  27. The Inadequacy of Certain Common Grounds of Belief.J. E. M'taggart - 1905 - Hibbert Journal 4:116.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  15
    Common sense.Lynd Forguson - 1989 - New York: Routledge.
    This accessible study presents a new investigation into the philosophical foundations and psychological origins of our common sense beliefs - that intricate network of shared ideas which guides our everyday behaviour.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  29. Approximate common knowledge and co-ordination: Recent lessons from game theory. [REVIEW]Stephen Morris & Hyun Shin - 1997 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 6 (2):171-90.
    The importance of the notion of common knowledge in sustaining cooperative outcomes in strategic situations is well appreciated. However, the systematic analysis of the extent to which small departures from common knowledge affect equilibrium in games has only recently been attempted.We review the main themes in this literature, in particular, the notion of common p-belief. We outline both the analytical issues raised, and the potential applicability of such ideas to game theory, computer science and the philosophy (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  30. How can belief be akratic?Eugene Chislenko - 2021 - Synthese 199 (5-6):13925-13948.
    Akratic belief, or belief one believes one should not have, has often been thought to be impossible. I argue that the possibility of akratic belief should be accepted as a pre-theoretical datum. I distinguish intuitive, defensive, systematic, and diagnostic ways of arguing for this view, and offer an argument that combines them. After offering intuitive examples of akratic belief, I defend those examples against a common argument against the possibility of akratic belief, which I (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  31. Essentialist Beliefs About Bodily Transplants in the United States and India.Meredith Meyer, Sarah-Jane Leslie, Susan A. Gelman & Sarah M. Stilwell - 2013 - Cognitive Science 37 (1):668-710.
    Psychological essentialism is the belief that some internal, unseen essence or force determines the common outward appearances and behaviors of category members. We investigated whether reasoning about transplants of bodily elements showed evidence of essentialist thinking. Both Americans and Indians endorsed the possibility of transplants conferring donors' personality, behavior, and luck on recipients, consistent with essentialism. Respondents also endorsed essentialist effects even when denying that transplants would change a recipient's category membership (e.g., predicting that a recipient of a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  32.  38
    The belief in innate talent and its implications for distributive justice.Mark C. Vopat - 2021 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 53 (8):819-832.
    Although the commonly accepted view is that there are such things as natural talents, more than 20 years of research suggests the opposite. What passes for talented is attributable to a combination of social and environmental factors. If the current research on this topic holds true, then there are implications not only for various theories of distributive justice, but there are also serious implication for real world distributions. In this article I will argue that talent is not innate and that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  77
    Toward formalizing common-sense psychology: an analysis of the false-belief task.Konstantine Arkoudas & Selmer Bringsjord - 2008 - In Tu-Bao Ho & Zhi-Hua Zhou (eds.), PRICAI 2008: Trends in Artificial Intelligence. Springer. pp. 17--29.
  34. Beliefs: Our Map of the World.Avijit Lahiri - manuscript
    In this essay we focus on our vast web of beliefs that serves us as a rough and ready map of reality, generated more to give us comfort and confidence in an intimidating world than to be accurate. Maps of reality can never be accurate in any ultimate sense since reality itself is a convoluted entity that can only be accessed in never- ending layers. Our repertoire of beliefs, generated compulsively in the mind, span a huge spectrum in respect of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  35
    Elementary Belief Revision Operators.Jake Chandler & Richard Booth - 2023 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 52 (1):267-311.
    Discussions of the issue of iterated belief revision are commonly accompanied by the presentation of three “concrete” operators: natural, restrained and lexicographic. This raises a natural question: What is so distinctive about these three particular methods? Indeed, the common axiomatic ground for work on iterated revision, the AGM and Darwiche-Pearl postulates, leaves open a whole range of alternative proposals. In this paper, we show that it is satisfaction of an additional principle of “Independence of Irrelevant Alternatives”, inspired by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36. Beliefs do not come in degrees.Andrew Moon - 2017 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 47 (6):760-778.
    Philosophers commonly say that beliefs come in degrees. Drawing from the literature, I make precise three arguments for this claim: an argument from degrees of confidence, an argument from degrees of firmness, and an argument from natural language. I show that they all fail. I also advance three arguments that beliefs do not come in degrees: an argument from natural language, an argument from intuition, and an argument from the metaphysics of degrees. On the basis of these arguments, I conclude (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  37. Delusions and Other Irrational Beliefs.Lisa Bortolotti - 2009 - Oxford University Press. Edited by K. W. M. Fulford, John Sadler, Stanghellini Z., Morris Giovanni, Bortolotti Katherine, Broome Lisa & Matthew.
    Delusions are a common symptom of schizophrenia and dementia. Though most English dictionaries define a delusion as a false opinion or belief, there is currently a lively debate about whether delusions are really beliefs and indeed, whether they are even irrational. The book is an interdisciplinary exploration of the nature of delusions. It brings together the psychological literature on the aetiology and the behavioural manifestations of delusions, and the philosophical literature on belief ascription and rationality. The thesis (...)
  38. Belief's own metaethics? A case against epistemic normativity.Charles Cote-Bouchard - 2017 - Dissertation, King's College London
    Epistemology is widely seen as a normative discipline like ethics. Just like moral facts, epistemic facts – i.e. facts about our beliefs’ epistemic justification, rationality, reasonableness, correctness, warrant, and the like – are standardly viewed as normative facts. Yet, whereas many philosophers have rejected the existence of moral facts, few have raised similar doubts about the existence of epistemic facts. In recent years however, several metaethicists and epistemologists have rejected this Janus-faced or dual stance towards the existence of moral and (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  39.  26
    Belief and desire under the Elms.Consuelo Preti - 2000 - ProtoSociology 14:270-284.
    This paper begins with an exposition the apparent tension between externalist theories of content and common-sense belief/desire psychology, with a view to resolving the conflict between these two views. The second part of the paper is a criticism of Fodor’s reformulation of Twin Earth type cases.I argue that this attempt to mitigate the damage such cases do to the tenability of folk psychological explanation cannot work, because Twin Earth cases pose a metaphysical problem for content and explanation, not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  44
    Doxasticism: Belief and the information-responsiveness of mind.Robert Audi - 2020 - Episteme 17 (4):542-562.
    ABSTRACTThis paper concerns a problem that has received insufficient analysis in the philosophical literature so far: the conditions under which an information-bearing state – say a perception or recollection – yields belief. The paper distinguishes between belief and a psychological property easily conflated with belief, illustrates the tendency of philosophers to overlook this distinction, and offers a positive conception of the mind's information-responsiveness that requires far less belief-formation – and far less formation of other propositional attitudes (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  41. Rational Belief in the Impossible.Sharon Ryan - 1991 - Dissertation, The University of Rochester
    It is commonly assumed that if one's beliefs are epistemically rational, then those beliefs must at least be consistent with one another. I argue that this assumption is false. I argue that it can be epistemically rational for a person to believe an inconsistent set of statements. I argue further that while one can rationally believe an inconsistent set of statements, one cannot rationally believe a set of statements that she or he knows to be inconsistent. ;In opposition, versions of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  68
    Belief As a Disposition to Act: Variations on a Pragmatist Theme.Pascal Engel - unknown
    In this paper I want to show that, although it is a common thread of many pragmatist or pragmatist-inspired doctrines, the belief-as-disposition-to-act theme is played on very different tunes by the various philosophical performers. A whole book could be devoted to the topic. I shall limit myself here to the views of Peirce, James, Ramsey, contemporary functionalists, and Isaac Levi. Depending on how they interpret this theme, the pragmatist philosophers can emphasise more or less the role of theory (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  43. Being realistic about common knowledge: a Lewisian approach.Cedric Paternotte - 2011 - Synthese 183 (2):249-276.
    Defined and formalized several decades ago, widely used in philosophy and game theory, the concept of common knowledge is still considered as problematic, although not always for the right reasons. I suggest that the epistemic status of a group of human agents in a state of common knowledge has not been thoroughly analyzed. In particular, every existing account of common knowledge, whether formal or not, is either too strong to fit cognitively limited individuals, or too weak to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  44.  16
    (1 other version)Faith, Belief and Fictionalism.Michael Scott & Finlay Malcolm - 2016 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 98 (2):257-274.
    Is propositional religious faith constituted by belief? Recent debate has focussed on whether faith may be constituted by a positive non‐doxastic cognitive state, which can stand in place of belief. This article sets out and defends the doxastic theory. We consider and reject three arguments commonly used in favour of non‐doxastic theories of faith: (1) the argument from religious doubt; (2) the use of ‘faith’ in linguistic utterances; and (3) the possibility of pragmatic faith. We argue that (...) is required to maintain a distinction between genuine faith, pretend faith, and fictionalist faith. (shrink)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  45.  10
    A philosophy of common sense: the modern discovery of the epistemic foundations of science and belief.Antonio Livi - 2013 - Aurora, Colorado: Davies Group, Publishers.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Group Belief: Defending a minimal version of summativism.Domingos Faria - 2021 - Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 58 (1):82-93.
    Beliefs are commonly attributed to groups or collective entities. But what is the nature of group belief? Summativism and nonsummativism are two main rival views regarding the nature of group belief. On the one hand, summativism holds that, necessarily, a group g has a belief B only if at least one individual i is both a member of g and has B. On the other hand, non-summativism holds that it is possible for a group g to have (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  47.  56
    Belief Revision and Computational Argumentation: A Critical Comparison.Pietro Baroni, Eduardo Fermé, Massimiliano Giacomin & Guillermo Ricardo Simari - 2022 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 31 (4):555-589.
    This paper aims at comparing and relating belief revision and argumentation as approaches to model reasoning processes. Referring to some prominent literature references in both fields, we will discuss their (implicit or explicit) assumptions on the modeled processes and hence commonalities and differences in the forms of reasoning they are suitable to deal with. The intended contribution is on one hand assessing the (not fully explored yet) relationships between two lively research fields in the broad area of defeasible reasoning (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48. Evidence and Belief, Common Sense, and the Science of Mind in the Philosophy of Thomas Reid.Alan Wade Davenport - 1987 - Dissertation, The American University
    This dissertation attempts to expose the influence of Francis Bacon on the philosophy of Thomas Reid. Reid was a self-professed Baconian who viewed the human mind as a subject which was amenable to scientific investigation. Reid attempts to develop his own theory of mind according to the method of induction and experiment and general philosophy of science of Bacon. Further, Reid's use of the Baconian idols in his attack on the theory of ideas is explored. In addition, it is argued (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  8
    The origin and nature of religion: tracing the common origin and nature of religion behind the multiplicity of beliefs and practices.Augustine Perumalil - 2001 - Delhi: ISPCK.
  50.  84
    Self-Knowledge of Belief Requires Understanding of Propositions.Lukas Schwengerer - forthcoming - Erkenntnis:1-14.
    I show that from common views about propositions as sets of possible worlds and knowledge requiring a sufficiently strong safety condition one can derive a condition stating that self-knowledge of belief is only possible if the content of that belief is fully understood. I show this by a reductio. If a subject S lacks full understanding of a proposition p, then S’s belief about believing that p cannot amount to knowledge. Even though my argument is based (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 970