Results for 'Jerry Law'

957 found
Order:
  1. Freud's Critique of Religion and the Viability of Faith.Jerry Law - 2000 - Telos: Critical Theory of the Contemporary 2000 (118):143-155.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Commonsense Metaphysics and Lexical Semantics.Jerry R. Hobbs, William Croft, Todd Davies, Douglas Edwards & Kenneth Laws - 1987 - Computational Linguistics 13 (3&4):241-250.
    In the TACITUS project for using commonsense knowledge in the understanding of texts about mechanical devices and their failures, we have been developing various commonsense theories that are needed to mediate between the way we talk about the behavior of such devices and causal models of their operation. Of central importance in this effort is the axiomatization of what might be called commonsense metaphysics. This includes a number of areas that figure in virtually every domain of discourse, such as granularity, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  3.  17
    Catholic Social Teaching and Its Impact on American Law.Jerry Organ - 2004 - Journal of Catholic Social Thought 1 (2):277-312.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Adam Smith's Moral Philosophy: A Historical and Contemporary Perspective on Markets, Law, Ethics, and Culture.Jerry Evensky - 2005 - Cambridge University Press.
    Adam Smith is the best known among economists for his book, The Wealth of Nations, often viewed as the keystone of modern economic thought. For many he has become associated with a quasi-libertarian laissez-faire philosophy. Others, often heterodox economists and social philosophers, on the contrary, focus on Smith's Theory of Moral Sentiments, and explore his moral theory. There has been a long debate about the relationship or lack thereof between these, his two great works. This work treats these dimensions of (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  5.  34
    Doubts about Death: The Silence of the Institute of Medicine.Jerry Menikoff - 1998 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 26 (2):157-165.
    Traditionally, organ retrieval from cadavers has taken place only in cases where the declaration of death has occurred using “brain death” criteria. Under these criteria, specific tests are performed to demonstrate directly a lack of brain activity. Recently, as a result of efforts to increase organ procurement, attention has been directed at the use of so-called “non-heart-beating” donors : individuals who are declared dead not as a result of direct measurements of brain function, but rather as a result of the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  6. You can fool some of the people all of the time, everything else being equal: Hedged laws and psychological explanation.Jerry A. Fodor - 1991 - Mind 100 (397):19-34.
  7.  63
    What the doctor didn't say: the hidden truth about medical research.Jerry Menikoff - 2006 - New York: Oxford University Press. Edited by Edward P. Richards.
    Most people know precious little about the risks and benefits of participating in a clinical trial--a medical research study involving some innovative treatment for a medical problem. Yet millions of people each year participate anyway. Patients at Risk explains the reality: that our current system intentionally hides much of the information people need to make the right choice about whether to participate. Witness the following scenarios: -Hundreds of patients with colon cancer undergo a new form of keyhole surgery at leading (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  8.  34
    Laws and Order in Eighteenth-Century Chemistry. Alistair Duncan.Jerry Gough - 1997 - Isis 88 (1):147-147.
  9.  63
    Plato's Vision of Chaos.Jerry S. Clegg - 1976 - Classical Quarterly 26 (01):52-.
    In the creation myth of the Timaeus Plato describes God as wishing that all things should be good so far as is possible. Wherefore, finding the whole visible sphere of the world not at rest, but moving in an irregular fashion, out of disorder He brought order, thinking that this was in every way an improvement. To achieve His end He placed intelligence in soul and soul in body, reflecting that nothing unintelligent could ever be better than something intelligent . (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  10.  30
    Life, Health, and Disability Insurance: Understanding the Relationships.Robert H. Jerry - 2007 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 35 (S2):80-89.
    This project focuses on the extent to which disability insurers should be allowed to use genetic information in underwriting and rate-setting, but this subject cannot be completely isolated from the related questions of whether life and health insurers should also have this discretion. Federal and state laws place significant restrictions on insurers’ use of genetic information in health insurance, but regulation of such use in life and disability insurance is considerably more modest. This essay examines the reasons for this disparity (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  11.  15
    Beyond Financial Incentives: Organizational Ethics and Organizational Integrity.Jerry Goodstein & Robert Potter - 1999 - HEC Forum 11 (4):293-305.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12.  17
    Teens and morality.Jerry Shepherd - 2005 - Winona, MN: Saint Mary's Press.
    Why be good -- Laws and legalisms -- Moral actor, moral acts -- Paths of glory : virtues -- Moral heroes.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13.  7
    The New Cultural Defense.Jerry Kang - 2012 - In Jon Hanson (ed.), Ideology, Psychology, and Law. Oup Usa. pp. 261.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  24
    Allocating Responsibility by Contract.Jerry A. Green - 1980 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 8 (5):2-3.
  15.  47
    The Vulnerability of the Very Sick.Jerry Menikoff - 2009 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 37 (1):51-58.
    Suppose that someone has a serious illness. The illness will likely lead to significant disabilities, and may even cause death. Existing treatments are unsatisfactory. The patient learns about a clinical trial, in which some allegedly promising new treatment for that illness is being tested.Such seriously ill patients for whom existing treatments are unsatisfactory have sometimes been categorized as medically vulnerable in the literature. Should these patients indeed be considered vulnerable subjects and be provided with special protections? And if the answer (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  16.  48
    Beyond financial incentives: Organizational ethics and organizational integrity. [REVIEW]Jerry Goodstein & RobertLyman Potter - 1999 - HEC Forum 11 (4):293-305.
  17.  64
    Using Patent Data to Assess the Value of Pharmaceutical Innovation.Aaron S. Kesselheim & Jerry Avorn - 2009 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 37 (2):176-183.
    Only 19 new molecular entities and 3 biologics were approved by the Food and Drug Administration in 2007, the lowest rate in 24 years. This disappointing output occurred despite steady clinical trial and regulatory review times, the FDA maintaining high approval rates, and the pharmaceutical industry consistently reporting increasing revenues. A government report suggests that fewer new drug applications have been submitted to the FDA by the pharmaceutical industry in recent years. These data have rekindled the debate as to the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  18.  68
    Mitigating Racial Bias in Machine Learning.Kristin M. Kostick-Quenet, I. Glenn Cohen, Sara Gerke, Bernard Lo, James Antaki, Faezah Movahedi, Hasna Njah, Lauren Schoen, Jerry E. Estep & J. S. Blumenthal-Barby - 2022 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 50 (1):92-100.
    When applied in the health sector, AI-based applications raise not only ethical but legal and safety concerns, where algorithms trained on data from majority populations can generate less accurate or reliable results for minorities and other disadvantaged groups.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  19. Recent Developments in Health Care Law: Partners in Innovation. [REVIEW]Roberta M. Berry, Lisa Bliss, Sylvia Caley, Paul A. Lombardo, Jerri Nims Rooker, Jonathan Todres & Leslie E. Wolf - 2010 - HEC Forum 22 (2):85-116.
    This article reviews recent developments in health care law, focusing on the engagement of law as a partner in health care innovation. The article addresses: the history and contents of recent United States federal law restricting the use of genetic information by insurers and employers; the recent federal policy recommending routine HIV testing; the recent revision of federal policy regarding the funding of human embryonic stem cell research; the history, current status, and need for future attention to advance directives; the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  13
    When can we Kick (Some) Humans “Out of the Loop”? An Examination of the use of AI in Medical Imaging for Lumbar Spinal Stenosis.Kathryn Muyskens, Yonghui Ma, Jerry Menikoff, James Hallinan & Julian Savulescu - 2025 - Asian Bioethics Review 17 (1):207-223.
    Artificial intelligence (AI) has attracted an increasing amount of attention, both positive and negative. Its potential applications in healthcare are indeed manifold and revolutionary, and within the realm of medical imaging and radiology (which will be the focus of this paper), significant increases in accuracy and speed, as well as significant savings in cost, stand to be gained through the adoption of this technology. Because of its novelty, a norm of keeping humans “in the loop” wherever AI mechanisms are deployed (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  21.  25
    Characteristics of Clinical Trials Launched Early in the COVID-19 Pandemic in the US and in France.Véronique Raimond, Julien Mousquès, Jerry Avorn & Aaron S. Kesselheim - 2021 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 49 (1):139-151.
    Based on hierarchical classification and logistic regression of early US and French COVID-19 clinical trials we show that despite the registration of a large number of trials, only a minority had characteristics usually associated with providing robust and relevant evidence.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  11
    Origins and Ownership of Remdesivir: Implications for Pricing.ChangWon C. Lee, Jonathan J. Darrow, Jerry Avorn & Aaron S. Kesselheim - 2020 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 48 (3):613-618.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23.  15
    Challenges to legal theory: essays in honour of Professor José Iturmendi Morales.José Iturmendi Morales, Falcón Y. Tella, María José, Martínez Muñoz, Juan Antonio & Deirdre B. Jerry (eds.) - 2021 - Boston: Brill | Nijhoff.
    Challenges to Legal Theory offers the reader a fascinating journey though a variety of multi-disciplinary topics, ranging from law and literature, and law and religion, to legal philosophy and constitutional law. The collection reflects some of the challenges that the field of legal theory currently faces. It is compiled by a selection of international and Spanish scholars, whose essays are made available in English translation for the first time. The volume is based on a collection of essays, published in Spanish, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  35
    Patients' Knowledge of Key Messaging in Drug Safety Communications for Zolpidem and Eszopiclone: A National Survey.Aaron S. Kesselheim, Michael S. Sinha, Paula Rausch, Zhigang Lu, Frazer A. Tessema, Brian M. Lappin, Esther H. Zhou, Gerald J. Dal Pan, Lee Zwanziger, Amy Ramanadham, Anita Loughlin, Cheryl Enger, Jerry Avorn & Eric G. Campbell - 2019 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 47 (3):430-441.
    Drug Safety Communications are used by the Food and Drug Administration to inform health care providers, patients, caregivers, and the general public about safety issues related to FDA-approved drugs. To assess patient knowledge of the messaging contained in DSCs related to the sleep aids zolpidem and eszopiclone, we conducted a large, cross-sectional patient survey of 1,982 commercially insured patients selected by stratified random sampling from the Optum Research Database who had filled at least two prescriptions for either zolpidem or eszopiclone (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  25.  2
    Response to Nakamura et al.Kathryn Muyskens, Yonghui Ma, Jerry Menikoff, James Hallinan & Julian Savulescu - 2025 - Asian Bioethics Review 17 (1):17-19.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26. Assessing Risk in Implementing New Artificial Intelligence Triage Tools—How Much Risk is Reasonable in an Already Risky World?Alexa Nord-Bronzyk, Julian Savulescu, Angela Ballantyne, Annette Braunack-Mayer, Pavitra Krishnaswamy, Tamra Lysaght, Marcus E. H. Ong, Nan Liu, Jerry Menikoff, Mayli Mertens & Michael Dunn - 2025 - Asian Bioethics Review 17 (1):187-205.
    Risk prediction in emergency medicine (EM) holds unique challenges due to issues surrounding urgency, blurry research-practise distinctions, and the high-pressure environment in emergency departments (ED). Artificial intelligence (AI) risk prediction tools have been developed with the aim of streamlining triaging processes and mitigating perennial issues affecting EDs globally, such as overcrowding and delays. The implementation of these tools is complicated by the potential risks associated with over-triage and under-triage, untraceable false positives, as well as the potential for the biases of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27.  40
    Electronic Fetal Monitoring and Obstetrical Malpractice.Barry S. Schifrin, Henry Weissman & Jerry Wiley - 1985 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 13 (3):100-105.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28. Jerry L. Mashaw, Greed, Chaos, and Governance: Using Public Choice to Improve Public Law Reviewed by.J. E. Penner - 1998 - Philosophy in Review 18 (2):125-127.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  42
    Review of Jerry Menikoff, Law and Bioethics: An Introduction. [REVIEW]B. Natalie Demers - 2002 - American Journal of Bioethics 2 (1):67-68.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30. Psychological laws and nonmonotonic logic.Arnold Silverberg - 1996 - Erkenntnis 44 (2):199-224.
    In this essay I enter into a recently published debate between Stephen Schiffer and Jerry Fodor concerning whether adequate sense can be made of the ceteris paribus conditions in special science laws, much of their focus being on the case of putative psychological laws. Schiffer argues that adequate sense cannot be made of ceteris paribus clauses, while Fodor attempts to overcome Schiffer's arguments, in defense of special science laws. More recently, Peter Mott has attempted to show that Fodor's response (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  31. Jerry Cohen’s Why Not Socialism? Some Thoughts.John E. Roemer - 2010 - The Journal of Ethics 14 (3-4):255-262.
    In his book Why Not Socialism?, G.A. Cohen described several kinds of inequality that would be acceptable under socialism, yet nonetheless harmful to community. I describe another kind of inequality with this property, deriving from the legitimate transmission of preferences and values from parents to children. In the same book, Cohen proposes that the designing of a socialist allocation mechanism is a key problem for socialist theory. I maintain this is less of a problem than he believes. Finally, some thoughts (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  32.  35
    On Fodor's First Law of the Nonexistence of Cognitive Science.Gregory L. Murphy - 2019 - Cognitive Science 43 (5):e12735.
    In his enormously influentialThe Modularity of Mind, Jerry Fodor (1983) proposed that the mind was divided into input modules and central processes. Much subsequent research focused on the modules and whether processes like speech perception or spatial vision are truly modular. Much less attention has been given to Fodor's writing on the central processes, what would today be called higher‐level cognition. In “Fodor's First Law of the Nonexistence of Cognitive Science,” he argued that central processes are “bad candidates for (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  54
    Reviews in Medical Ethics: The Ethics and Regulation of Research with Human Subjects, Carl Coleman, Jerry Menikoff, Jesse Goldner, and Nancy Dubler, eds., (LexisNexis) 2005.David B. Resnik - 2006 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 34 (2):465-466.
    The Ethics and Regulation of Research with Human Subjects, edited by Professors Carl Coleman of Seton Hall, Jerry Menikoff of the University of Kansas, Jesse Goldner of Saint Louis University, and Nancy Dubler of the Albert Einstein College of Medicine, is an up-to-date and authoritative collection of readings on ethical, legal, and policy issues in research with human subjects. The authors have modeled their text on the casebook style commonly used in law schools. At 746 pages, plus front matter (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  52
    Laws, Demands, and Dispositions: John Dewey and his ‘Concept Pragmatism’.Jady Hsin - 2014 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 50 (2):286.
    Cognitive science has come down with a nasty cold, so Jerry Fodor has recently lamented, and the afflicting strain is something called concept pragmatism.1 Its chief symptom is the urge to identify the content of a concept with the inferences habitually drawn upon in its use (a ‘definition-in-use’), these serving also as its condition of possession, in knowing how to draw those inferences definitive of the concept.2 The affliction is quite fatal if Fodor is right, but the welfare of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Review of Jerry Fodor's The Elm and the expert. [REVIEW]Pierre Jacob - 1996 - European Journal of Philosophy 4 (3):373-378.
    I discuss Fodor's examination of what he calls 'Frege cases' and which he takes to be exceptions to psychologica laws.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  58
    Surgical castration, Texas law and the case of Mr T.William J. Winslade - 2014 - Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (9):591-592.
    Persons who commit crimes involving sexual abuse of children exploit their victims in several ways. Sex offenders use their power and authority over vulnerable children to whom they have easy access. Teachers, coaches, clergy, family members and childcare workers have been exposed as sex offenders. The Pennsylvania State University football coach, Jerry Sandusky, is now in prison for his many crimes. The widespread cover up of sexual abuse by Catholic priests in the USA and other countries is a horrendous (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37. Natural selection, causality, and laws: What Fodor and piatelli-palmarini got wrong.Elliott Sober - 2010 - Philosophy of Science 77 (4):594-607.
    In their book What Darwin Got Wrong, Jerry Fodor and Massimo Piattelli-Palmarini construct an a priori philosophical argument and an empirical biological argument. The biological argument aims to show that natural selection is much less important in the evolutionary process than many biologists maintain. The a priori argument begins with the claim that there cannot be selection for one but not the other of two traits that are perfectly correlated in a population; it concludes that there cannot be an (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  38.  19
    Between facts and principles: jurisdiction in international human rights law.Lea Raible - 2021 - Jurisprudence 13 (1):52-72.
    In international human rights law ‘jurisdiction’ is the centre of the debate on extraterritorial obligations. The purpose of the present paper is to a) analyse how facts and principles contribute t...
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  34
    Implementing California's Law on Assisted Dying.Ruchika Mishra - 2017 - Hastings Center Report 47 (2):7-8.
    On October 5, 2015, Governor Jerry Brown approved bill ABX2 15, the End of Life Option Act, making California the fifth state in the country to allow physician-assisted dying. The law was modeled after Oregon's 1997 Death with Dignity Act. When the legislative special session ended on March 10, 2016, California health care providers had only ninety days to respond to the state mandate before the law would take effect, on June 9, 2016. Experience with the law so far (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40. Asymmetrical dependence between causal laws does not account for meaning.Alberto Voltolini - 1998 - In V. Abrusci (ed.), Prospettive della Logica e della Filosofia della scienza. ETS. pp. 307-316.
    In (1990), Jerry Fodor has defended a naturalized conception of meaning for Mentalese expressions which relies on the notion of asymmetric dependence. According to this conception, any naturalized theory of meaning must be able to account for the fact that meaning is robust, namely that any token of a certain Mentalese expression “x” retains the expression’s meaning, X, for any Y (≠ X) which happens to cause it. Now, this robustness of “x”‘s meaning can precisely be explained in terms (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  37
    The State of Nature and Laws of Seinfeld: Not That There’s Anything Wrong With That. [REVIEW]Aaron R. S. Lorenz - 2014 - International Journal for the Semiotics of Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique 27 (1):65-84.
    Seinfeld (1989–1998) and it’s co-creator’s Curb Your Enthusiasm (2000–present), are each considered groundbreaking television. Critics regard their humor and intellectual comedy as Twain-like and creative. While both shows have been criticized for their character’s indifference and apolitical attitude, the programs resonate with those in society who more subtly consider law and politics. This project argues that Seinfeld and Curb present a unique theory of justice. These two shows constitute a common and current image of what is just in society. While (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  42.  75
    Fodor’s Vindication of Folk Psychology and the Charge of Epiphenomenalism.Nicholas P. Power - 1996 - Journal of Philosophical Research 21 (January):183-196.
    Jerry Fodor has long championed the view, recently dubbed “scientific intentional realism” (Loewer and Ray, 1991, p. xiv), that “a scientifically adequate psychology will contain laws that quantify over intentional phenomena in intentional terms.” On such a view our belief/desire psychology will be “vindicated” through empirical investigation; that is, it will be shown to denote the explanatory (or causally salient) states or events in the production of thought and behavior. That intentional properties, states, or events have causal efficacy---are not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. Individualism and the Cross Contexts Test.Jonathan Barrett - 1997 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 78 (3):242-60.
    Jerry Fodor has defended the claim that psychological theories should appeal to narrow rather than wide intentional properties. One of his arguments relies upon the cross contexts test, a test that purports to determine whether two events have the same causally relevant properties. Critics have charged that this test is too weak, since it counts certain genuinely explanatory relational properties in science as being causally irrelevant. Further, it has been claimed, the test is insensitive to the fact that special (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  44. What does Fodor’s “anti-darwinism” mean to natural theology?Yingjin Xu - 2011 - Frontiers of Philosophy in China 6 (3):465-479.
    In the current dialogue of “science and religion,” it is widely assumed that the thoughts of Darwinists and that of atheists overlap. However, Jerry Fodor, a full-fledged atheist, recently announced a war against Darwinism with his atheistic campaign. Prima facie, this “civil war” might offer a chance for theists: If Fodor is right, Darwinistic atheism will lose the cover of Darwinism and become less tenable. This paper provides a more pessimistic evaluation of the situation by explaining the following: Fodor’s (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  37
    What Does Fodor’s “Anti-Darwinism” Mean to Natural Theology?X. U. Yingjin - 2011 - Frontiers of Philosophy in China 6 (3):465-479.
    In the current dialogue of “science and religion,” it is widely assumed that the thoughts of Darwinists and that of atheists overlap. However, Jerry Fodor, a full-fledged atheist, recently announced a war against Darwinism with his atheistic campaign. Prima facie, this “civil war” might offer a chance for theists: If Fodor is right, Darwinistic atheism will lose the cover of Darwinism and become less tenable. This paper provides a more pessimistic evaluation of the situation by explaining the following: Fodor’s (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  81
    Special sciences: Still a flawed argument after all these years.Todd Edwin Jones - 2004 - Cognitive Science 28 (3):409-432.
    Jerry Fodor has argued that the multiple realizability argument, as discussed in his original “Special Sciences” article, “refutes psychophysical reductionism once and for all.” I argue that his argument in “Special Sciences” does no such thing. Furthermore, if one endorses the physicalism that most supporters of the “Special Sciences” view endorse, special science laws must be reducible, in principle. The compatibility of MR with reduction, however, need not threaten the autonomy of the special sciences.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  47.  94
    Casting the first stone: Who can, and who can't, condemn the terrorists?Ted Honderich - manuscript
    Professor Cohen, 'Jerry' to very many, has been Chichele Professor of Social and Political Theory, All Souls College, Oxford. He has been both a worthy successor to Isaiah Berlin in the chair and also his own man. Born into a Jewish family in Montral, Cohen was educated at McGill University and then in Oxford under Berlin and Gilbert Ryle. He taught philosophy vigorously at University College London and became known as the first proponent of analytical Marxism. His resolute book (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48. Broadening the Mind. [REVIEW]John Perry - 1998 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (1):223-231.
    The main topic of Jerry Fodor’s The Elm and the Expert,1, and the title of the first chapter, is “If Psychological processes are computational, how can psychological laws be intentional?” I focus on the first and second chapters; The first is devoted to setting up the question, the second to answering it.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49. Source and Channel in the informational theory of mental content.Max Kistler - 2000 - Facta Philosophica 2 (2):213-36.
    With the aim of giving a naturalistic foundation to the notion of mental representation, Fred Dretske (1981;1988) has put forward and developed the idea that the relation between a representation and its intentional content is grounded on an informational relation. In this explanatory model, mental representations are conceived of as states of organisms which a learning process has selected to play a functional role: a necessary condition for fulfilling this role is that the organism or some proper part of it (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  50. Broad versus narrow content in the explanation of action: Fodor on Frege cases.Jerome C. Wakefield - 2002 - Philosophical Psychology 15 (2):119-33.
    A major obstacle to formulating a broad-content intentional psychology is the occurrence of ''Frege cases'' - cases in which a person apparently believes or desires Fa but not Fb and acts accordingly, even though "a" and "b" have the same broad content. Frege cases seem to demand narrow-content distinctions to explain actions by the contents of beliefs and desires. Jerry Fodor ( The elm and the expert: Mentalese and its semantics , Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1994) argues that an (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
1 — 50 / 957