Results for 'John L. Meech'

962 found
Order:
  1. Defeasible Reasoning.John L. Pollock - 1987 - Cognitive Science 11 (4):481-518.
    There was a long tradition in philosophy according to which good reasoning had to be deductively valid. However, that tradition began to be questioned in the 1960’s, and is now thoroughly discredited. What caused its downfall was the recognition that many familiar kinds of reasoning are not deductively valid, but clearly confer justification on their conclusions. Here are some simple examples.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   360 citations  
  2.  18
    How to reason defeasibly.John L. Pollock - 1992 - Artificial Intelligence 57 (1):1-42.
  3.  62
    How to Build a Person: A Prolegomenon.John L. Pollock - 1989 - MIT Press.
    Pollock describes an exciting theory of rationality and its partial implementation in OSCAR, a computer system whose descendants will literally be persons.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   100 citations  
  4.  25
    Organization of abilities and the development of intelligence.John L. Horn - 1968 - Psychological Review 75 (3):242-259.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  5. Knowledge and Justification.John L. Pollock - 1974 - Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Edited by John Pollock.
    Princeton University Press, 1974. This book is out of print, but can be downloaded as a pdf file (5 MB).
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   181 citations  
  6. Epistemic norms.John L. Pollock - 1987 - Synthese 71 (1):61 - 95.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  7.  75
    ``Defeasible Reasoning with Variable Degrees of Justification".John L. Pollock - 2001 - Artificial Intelligence 133 (1-2):233-282.
    The question addressed in this paper is how the degree of justification of a belief is determined. A conclusion may be supported by several different arguments, the arguments typically being defeasible, and there may also be arguments of varying strengths for defeaters for some of the supporting arguments. What is sought is a way of computing the “on sum” degree of justification of a conclusion in terms of the degrees of justification of all relevant premises and the strengths of all (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  8.  14
    Justification and defeat.John L. Pollock - 1994 - Artificial Intelligence 67 (2):377-407.
  9. A refined theory of counterfactuals.John L. Pollock - 1981 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (2):239 - 266.
  10. The Law of the Jungle: Moral Alternatives and Principles of Evolution.John L. Mackie - 1978 - Philosophy 53 (206):455 - 464.
    When people speak of ‘the law of the jungle’, they usually mean unions restrained and ruthless competition, with everyone out solely for his own advantage. But the phrase was coined by Rudyard Kipling, in The Second Jungle Book, and he meant something very different. His law of the jungle is a law that wolves in a pack are supposed to obey. His poem says that ‘the strength of the Pack is the Wolf, and the strength of the Wolf is the (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  11. (1 other version)Contemporary theories of knowledge.John L. Pollock - 1986 - London: Hutchinson.
    This new edition of the classic Contemporary Theories of Knowledge has been significantly updated to include analyses of the recent literature in epistemology.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   543 citations  
  12.  34
    The earliest missionaries of the Copenhagen spirit.John L. Heilbron - 1985 - Revue d'Histoire des Sciences 38 (3-4):195-230.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  13. Institutional analysis and the role of ideas in political economy.John L. Campbell - 1998 - Theory and Society 27 (3):377-409.
  14. (1 other version)Hermann Weyl on intuition and the continuum.John L. Bell - 2000 - Philosophia Mathematica 8 (3):259-273.
    Hermann Weyl, one of the twentieth century's greatest mathematicians, was unusual in possessing acute literary and philosophical sensibilities—sensibilities to which he gave full expression in his writings. In this paper I use quotations from these writings to provide a sketch of Weyl's philosophical orientation, following which I attempt to elucidate his views on the mathematical continuum, bringing out the central role he assigned to intuition.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  15.  42
    Turning Science to Account.John L. Rudolph - 2005 - Isis 96 (3):353-389.
    ABSTRACT In the second decade of the twentieth century a new subject appeared in American high schools, aimed at providing citizens with an understanding of the essential nature of scientific thinking. “General science,” as it was called, was developed and promoted by an emerging class of professional educators who sought to offer a version of science that they believed would both excite public interest and prove useful in the everyday lives of the masses of students streaming into the rapidly expanding (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  16. Perceptual knowledge.John L. Pollock - 1971 - Philosophical Review 80 (3):287-319.
  17.  64
    A theory of direct inference.John L. Pollock - 1983 - Theory and Decision 15 (1):29-95.
  18. Defeasible Reasoning and Degrees of Justification.Pollock † & L. John - 2010 - Argument and Computation 1 (1):7-22.
  19. Language and thought.John L. Pollock - 1982 - Princeton University Press. Edited by Lloyd Humberstone.
    Princeton University Press, 1982. This book is out of print, but can be downloaded as a pdf file (5 MB).
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  20. Epistemology and Probability.John L. Pollock - 1983 - Noûs 17 (1):65.
    Probability is sometimes regarded as a universal panacea for epistemology. It has been supposed that the rationality of belief is almost entirely a matter of probabilities. Unfortunately, those philosophers who have thought about this most extensively have tended to be probability theorists first, and epistemologists only secondarily. In my estimation, this has tended to make them insensitive to the complexities exhibited by epistemic justification. In this paper I propose to turn the tables. I begin by laying out some rather simple (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  21.  38
    Judgment of time as a function of serial position and stress.John L. Falk & Dalbir Bindra - 1954 - Journal of Experimental Psychology 47 (4):279.
  22. (1 other version)Introduction to connectionism.John L. Tienson - 1987 - Southern Journal of Philosophy (Suppl.) 1:1-16.
  23.  15
    (1 other version)The logical foundations of goal-regression planning in autonomous agents.John L. Pollock - 1998 - Artificial Intelligence 106 (2):267-334.
  24.  13
    VI. Formal Semantics.John L. Pollock - 1984 - In The foundations of philosophical semantics. Princeton University Press. pp. 172-229.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  25.  53
    The Continuous, the Discrete and the Infinitesimal in Philosophy and Mathematics.John L. Bell - 2019 - Springer Verlag.
    This book explores and articulates the concepts of the continuous and the infinitesimal from two points of view: the philosophical and the mathematical. The first section covers the history of these ideas in philosophy. Chapter one, entitled ‘The continuous and the discrete in Ancient Greece, the Orient and the European Middle Ages,’ reviews the work of Plato, Aristotle, Epicurus, and other Ancient Greeks; the elements of early Chinese, Indian and Islamic thought; and early Europeans including Henry of Harclay, Nicholas of (...)
    No categories
  26. Causal probability.John L. Pollock - 2002 - Synthese 132 (1-2):143 - 185.
    Examples growing out of the Newcomb problem have convinced many people that decision theory should proceed in terms of some kind of causal probability. I endorse this view and define and investigate a variety of causal probability. My definition is related to Skyrms' definition, but proceeds in terms of objective probabilities rather than subjective probabilities and avoids taking causal dependence as a primitive concept.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  27.  38
    The building of Oscar.John L. Pollock - 1988 - Philosophical Perspectives 2:315-344.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28.  25
    Introduction to symbolic logic.John L. Pollock - 1969 - New York,: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.
  29.  68
    Foundations for direct inference.John L. Pollock - 1994 - Theory and Decision 17 (3):221-255.
  30. Reasoning about change and persistence: A solution to the frame problem.John L. Pollock - 1997 - Noûs 31 (2):143-169.
  31. How to do things with words.John L. Austin - 1962 - Oxford [Eng.]: Clarendon Press. Edited by Marina Sbisá & J. O. Urmson.
    For this second edition, the editors have returned to Austin's original lecture notes, amending the printed text where it seemed necessary.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1732 citations  
  32.  49
    The quantum theoretical concept of measurement.John L. McKnight - 1957 - Philosophy of Science 24 (4):321-330.
    As a preliminary to the modern theory of measurement with which this paper is chiefly concerned, it is desirable to review a few of the characteristics and implications of classical physics to illustrate the far reaching changes that have taken place in our conception of nature as the result of the development of quantum mechanics.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  33. What am I? Virtual machines and the mind/body problem.John L. Pollock - 2008 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (2):237–309.
    When your word processor or email program is running on your computer, this creates a "virtual machine” that manipulates windows, files, text, etc. What is this virtual machine, and what are the virtual objects it manipulates? Many standard arguments in the philosophy of mind have exact analogues for virtual machines and virtual objects, but we do not want to draw the wild metaphysical conclusions that have sometimes tempted philosophers in the philosophy of mind. A computer file is not made of (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  34.  93
    Wilderness and heritage values.John L. Hammond - 1985 - Environmental Ethics 7 (2):165-170.
    Some proponents of the preservation of American wildemess-for example, Aldo Leopold-have argued in terms of the role of wildemess in forming and maintaining a set of distinctive national character traits. l examine and defend the value judgment implicit in Leopold’s argument. The value of one's cultural heritage is, I contend, as important and valid as other familiar goods appealed to in defense of social policy.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  35.  88
    The bush doctrine, preventive war, and international law.John L. Hammond - 2005 - Philosophical Forum 36 (1):97–111.
  36. Higher-Order Logic and Type Theory.John L. Bell - 2022 - Cambridge University Press.
    This Element is an exposition of second- and higher-order logic and type theory. It begins with a presentation of the syntax and semantics of classical second-order logic, pointing up the contrasts with first-order logic. This leads to a discussion of higher-order logic based on the concept of a type. The second Section contains an account of the origins and nature of type theory, and its relationship to set theory. Section 3 introduces Local Set Theory, an important form of type theory (...)
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  14
    John Deere and the Bereavement Counselor.John L. Mcknight - 1984 - Bulletin of Science, Technology and Society 4 (6):597-604.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Infinitary logic.John L. Bell - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Traditionally, expressions in formal systems have been regarded as signifying finite inscriptions which are—at least in principle—capable of actually being written out in primitive notation. However, the fact that (first-order) formulas may be identified with natural numbers (via "Gödel numbering") and hence with finite sets makes it no longer necessary to regard formulas as inscriptions, and suggests the possibility of fashioning "languages" some of whose formulas would be naturally identified as infinite sets . A "language" of this kind is called (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  39.  50
    Laying the Raven to rest: A discussion of Hempel and the paradoxes of confirmation.John L. Pollock - 1973 - Journal of Philosophy 70 (20):747-754.
  40. Language and life history: A new perspective on the development and evolution of human language.John L. Locke & Barry Bogin - 2006 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (3):259-280.
    It has long been claimed that Homo sapiens is the only species that has language, but only recently has it been recognized that humans also have an unusual pattern of growth and development. Social mammals have two stages of pre-adult development: infancy and juvenility. Humans have two additional prolonged and pronounced life history stages: childhood, an interval of four years extending between infancy and the juvenile period that follows, and adolescence, a stage of about eight years that stretches from juvenility (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  41.  56
    Epistemology and probability.John L. Pollock - 1983 - Synthese 55 (2):231-252.
    Probability is sometimes regarded as a universal panacea for epistemology. It has been supposed that the rationality of belief is almost entirely a matter of probabilities. Unfortunately, those philosophers who have thought about this most extensively have tended to be probability theorists first, and epistemologists only secondarily. In my estimation, this has tended to make them insensitive to the complexities exhibited by epistemic justification. In this paper I propose to turn the tables. I begin by laying out some rather simple (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  42.  23
    Paradoxes of Knowledge.John L. Koethe - 1978 - Philosophical Review 87 (4):651.
  43.  51
    Trickle-up phonetics: A vocal role for the infant.John L. Locke - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (4):516-516.
    Falk claims that human language took a step forward when infants lost their ability to cling and were placed on the ground, increasing their fears, which mothers assuaged prosodically. This claim, which is unsupported by anthropological and psychological evidence, would have done little for the syllabic and segmental structure of language, and ignores infants' own contribution to the process.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44.  9
    Folk Tale, Fiction, and Saga in the Homeric Epics.John L. Myres & Rhys Carpenter - 1948 - American Journal of Philology 69 (2):205.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  45.  31
    The Case for Ethical Efficiency: A System That Has Run Out of Time.John L. Havlik, Mark R. Mercurio & Sarah C. Hull - 2022 - Hastings Center Report 52 (2):14-20.
    Hastings Center Report, Volume 52, Issue 2, Page 14-20, March‐April 2022.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46. Could Waleed Aly ever become a humanist?John L. Perkins - 2012 - The Australian Humanist (106):24.
    Perkins, John L With his regular programmes on radio and television, newspaper columns and commentary, Waleed Aly has become Australia's favourite Muslim celebrity. He is intelligent, articulate and provides incisive analysis of political and social issues. Given this, it might have been expected that he could have applied the same quality of analysis in his book, People Like Us: How Arrogance is Dividing Islam and the West (2007); however this is not the case.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  97
    Continuity and Infinitesimals.John L. Bell - unknown
    The usual meaning of the word continuous is “unbroken” or “uninterrupted”: thus a continuous entity —a continuum—has no “gaps.” We commonly suppose that space and time are continuous, and certain philosophers have maintained that all natural processes occur continuously: witness, for example, Leibniz's famous apothegm natura non facit saltus—“nature makes no jump.” In mathematics the word is used in the same general sense, but has had to be furnished with increasingly precise definitions. So, for instance, in the later 18th century (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  48.  76
    Logical Validity in Modal Logic.John L. Pollock - 1967 - The Monist 51 (1):128-135.
  49.  77
    Subjunctive generalizations.John L. Pollock - 1974 - Synthese 28 (2):199 - 214.
  50.  23
    Partial blocking and the frustration effect.John L. Allen, Nancy L. Caven, Li-An C. Leonard & M. Ray Denny - 1980 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 15 (4):260-262.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 962