Results for 'Pure Act'

966 found
Order:
  1.  33
    Unmoved Mover as Pure Act or Unmoved Mover in Act? The Mystery of a Subscript Iota.Silvia Fazzo - 2016 - In Christoph Horn (ed.), Aristotle’s "Metaphysics" Lambda – New Essays. De Gruyter. pp. 181-206.
  2. Whitehead's Transformation of Pure Act.Lewis S. Ford - 1977 - The Thomist 41 (3):381.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. The theory of mind as pure act.Giovanni Gentile - 1922 - London,: Macmillan & co.. Edited by Herbert Wildon Carr.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  4. 20. Giovanni Gentile. The Act of Thinking as Pure Act.Rebecca Copenhaver & Brian P. A. Copenhaver - 2012 - In Rebecca Copenhaver & Brian P. A. Copenhaver (eds.), From Kant to Croce: Modern Philosophy in Italy, 1800-1950. University of Toronto Press. pp. 683-694.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  32
    Book Review:The Theory of Mind as Pure Act. Giovanni Gentile. [REVIEW]John Laird - 1923 - International Journal of Ethics 33 (2):213-.
  6.  20
    The Theory of Mind as Pure Act. [REVIEW]Warner Fite - 1923 - Philosophical Review 32 (5):548-551.
  7.  15
    A commentary on the Ukrainian translation of „The General Theory of Mind as Pure Act” by Giovanni Gentile.Ivan Ivashchenko - 2013 - Sententiae 29 (2):163-168.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  22
    Pure Food: Securing the Pure Food and Drugs Act of 1906. James Harvey Young.James Whorton - 1991 - Isis 82 (3):586-588.
  9. On acts, pure and impure.Yannis Stavrakakis - 2010 - International Journal of Žižek Studies 4 (2).
  10.  57
    Pure Categorial Principles.Laurence Goldstein - 1983 - The Monist 66 (3):410-421.
    If nowadays categories seems to cover a multitude of different enquiries, we can see some continuity and coherence among them, and we can get some sense of what the subject is, by going back to the first treatise to receive the name, the Categories of Aristotle. The scheme of categories worked out by Aristotle in that book was used by him in subsequent works to solve a variety of problems. On one plausible hypothesis, Aristotle’s scheme was partly shaped by ontological (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11.  34
    Acting in Order to Know, Knowing in Order to Act: Sosa on Epistemic and Practical Deliberation.Jesús Navarro - 2016 - Disputatio 8 (43):233-252.
    The questions ‘Do I know p?’ and ‘shall I take p as a reason to act?’ seem to belong to different domains — or so claims Ernest Sosa in his Judgment and Agency, the latest version of his virtue epistemology. According to Sosa, we may formulate the first question in a purely epistemological way — a matter of knowledge “full stop” —, while the second one is necessarily intruded by pragmatic factors — a matter of “actionable knowledge”. Both should be (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  12.  36
    Pure word deafness and the bilateral processing of the speech code.David Poeppel - 2001 - Cognitive Science 25 (5):679-693.
    The analysis of pure word deafness (PWD) suggests that speech perception, construed as the integration of acoustic information to yield representations that enter into the linguistic computational system, (i) is separable in a modular sense from other aspects of auditory cognition and (ii) is mediated by the posterior superior temporal cortex in both hemispheres. PWD data are consistent with neuropsychological and neuroimaging evidence in a manner that suggests that the speech code is analyzed bilaterally. The typical lateralization associated with (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  13.  10
    Années, 1781-1801: Kant, critique de la raison pure, vingt ans de réception: actes du 5e Congrès international de la Société d'études kantiennes de langue française, Montréal, 27-29 septembre 2001.Claude Sociâetâe D'âetudes Kantiennes de Langue Franðcaise & Pichâe (eds.) - 2002 - Paris: Libr. philosophique J. Vrin.
    Depuis deux siecles, la Critique de la raison pure occupe une place centrale dans notre paysage philosophique. Deja du vivant de Kant, cette influence commence a s'exercer, et de maniere fulgurante. D'abord recue avec scepticisme, la premiere Critique suscite bientot l'enthousiames, au point de faire ecole, pour se voir ensuite sursumee par la jeune generation. Les etudes ici rassemblees temoignent de la diversite et de l'intensite de cette premiere reception, qui va de l'accusation d'idealisme dirigee contre la Critique, jusqu'au (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. Acting intentionally and the side-effect effect: 'Theory of mind' and moral judgment.Joshua Knobe, Adam Cohen & Alan Leslie - 2006 - Psychological Science 17:421-427.
    The concept of acting intentionally is an important nexus where ‘theory of mind’ and moral judgment meet. Preschool children’s judgments of intentional action show a valence-driven asymmetry. Children say that a foreseen but disavowed side-effect is brought about 'on purpose' when the side-effect itself is morally bad but not when it is morally good. This is the first demonstration in preschoolers that moral judgment influences judgments of ‘on-purpose’ (as opposed to purpose influencing moral judgment). Judgments of intentional action are usually (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   109 citations  
  15.  89
    "Pure" versus "practical" epistemic justification.James A. Montmarquet - 2007 - Metaphilosophy 38 (1):71–87.
    In this article I distinguish a type of justification that is "epistemic" in pertaining to the grounds of one's belief, and "practical" in its connection to what act(s) one may undertake, based on that belief. Such justification, on the proposed account, depends mainly on the proportioning of "inner epistemic virtue" to the "outer risks" implied by one's act. The resulting conception strikes a balance between the unduly moralistic conception of William Clifford and contemporary naturalist virtue theories.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  16.  70
    Act Psychology and Phenomenology: Husserl on Egoic Acts.Benjamin Sheredos - 2017 - Husserl Studies 33 (3):191-209.
    Husserl famously retracted his early portrayal, in Logische Untersuchungen, of phenomenology as empirical psychology. Previous scholarship has typically understood this transcendental turn in light of the Ideen’s revised conception of the ἐποχή, and its distinction between noesa and noemata. This essay thematizes the evolution of the concept of mental acts in Husserl’s work as a way of understanding the shift. I show how the recognition of the pure ego in Ideen I and II enabled Husserl to radically alter his (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  17. Act and Rule Consequentialism: A Synthesis.Jussi Suikkanen - forthcoming - Moral Philosophy and Politics.
    As an indirect ethical theory, rule consequentialism first evaluates moral codes in terms of how good the consequences of their general adoption are and then individual actions in terms of whether or not the optimific code authorises them. There are three well-known and powerful objections to rule consequentialism’s indirect structure: the ideal world objection, the rule worship objection, and the incoherence objection. These objections are all based on cases in which following the optimific code has suboptimal consequences in the real (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Purely Performative Resuscitation: Treating the Patient as an Object.Aleksy Tarasenko-Struc - forthcoming - Bioethics.
    Despite its prevalence today, the practice of purely performative resuscitation (PPR)—paradigmatically, the ‘slow code’—has attracted more critics in bioethics than defenders. The most common criticism of the slow code is that it’s fundamentally deceptive or harmful, while the most common justification offered is that it may benefit the patient’s loved ones, by symbolically honoring the patient or the care team’s relationship with the family. I argue that critics and defenders of the slow code each have a point. Advocates of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  70
    Pure logical grammar: Anticipatory categoriality and articulated categoriality.John J. Drummond - 2003 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 11 (2):125 – 139.
    In reworking his Logical Investigations Husserl adopts two positions that were not actually incorporated into later editions of the Investigations but do appear in other writings: a new distinction between signitive and significative intentions, and the claim that even naming and perceiving acts are categorially formed. This paper investigates Husserl's notion of noematic sense and the pure grammatical ' categories ' intimated therein in order to shed light on these new positions. The paper argues that the development of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  20. Intentionality and Pure Logical Grammar in Husserl's Theory of Meaning.Terrence C. Wright - 1992 - Dissertation, Bryn Mawr College
    This dissertation concerns Edmund Husserl's theory of meaning. It focuses on Husserl's position as it develops from the Logical Investigations, published in 1900-01, through the writing of the Ideas in 1913. ;I argue that there are two theories of meaning at operation in Husserl's thinking in the Logical Investigations. One which is based upon the theory of pure logical grammar, the other based upon the theory of intentional acts of consciousness. I also consider the way in which Husserl's employs (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  17
    The Rich and the Pure: Philanthropy and the Making of Christian Society in Early Byzantium.Paul Stephenson - 2023 - Common Knowledge 29 (1):124-125.
    “Give to everyone who begs from you,” Jesus advised his followers. Most of us do not and rush on by, concerned for our safety, for what the beggar will buy with our gift of alms, for who will benefit from our gift. Fewer stop and give something: if not cash, then a snack or beverage, and their precious time. A century since Marcel Mauss published his famous essay, we all feel quite well informed about “the gift.” In this richly detailed (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Is A Purely First Person Account Of Human Action Defensible?Christopher Tollefsen - 2006 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 9 (4):441-460.
    There are two perspectives available from which to understand an agent's intention in acting. The first is the perspective of the acting agent: what did she take to be her end, and the means necessary to achieve that end? The other is a third person perspective that is attentive to causal or conceptual relations: was some causal outcome of the agent's action sufficiently close, or so conceptually related, to what the agent did that it should be considered part of her (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  23.  73
    Towards a Theory of Pure Procedural Climate Justice.Eric Brandstedt & Bengt Brülde - 2019 - Journal of Applied Philosophy 36 (5):785-799.
    A challenge for the theorising of climate justice is that even when the agents whose actions are supposed to be regulated are cooperative and act in good faith, they may still disagree about how the burdens and benefits of dealing with climate change should be distributed. This article is a contribution to the formulation of a useful role for normative theorising in light of this bounded nature of climate justice. We outline a theory of pure procedural climate justice; its (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  28
    Pure Economic Loss as a Special Kind of Loss in Lithuanian Tort Law.Simona Selelionytė-Drukteinienė - 2009 - Jurisprudencija: Mokslo darbu žurnalas 118 (4):123-146.
    In tort law, including Lithuanian tort law, damage usually is divided into two types: pecuniary and non-pecuniary damage. The concept of non-pecuniary damage has recently become a focus of attention of Lithuanian legal researchers. However, it has to be noted that the issues related to the concept of pecuniary damage remain scarcely analysed. As a result, the unique type of pecuniary damage, i.e. the damage of purely economic character, has received no attention whatsoever in Lithuanian tort law. It is usually (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Pure versus Hybrid Expressivism and the Enigma of Conventional Implicature.Stephen Barker - 2014 - In Guy Fletcher & Michael Ridge (eds.), Having It Both Ways: Hybrid Theories and Modern Metaethics. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 199-222.
    Can hybridism about moral claims be made to work? I argue it can if we accept the conventional implicature approach developed in Barker (Analysis 2000). However, this kind of hybrid expressivism is only acceptable if we can make sense of conventional implicature, the kind of meaning carried by operators like ‘even’, ‘but’, etc. Conventional implictures are a form of pragmatic presupposition, which involves an unsaid mode of delivery of content. I argue that we can make sense of conventional implicatures, but (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  26. The Puzzle of Pure Moral Motivation.Adam Lerner - 2018 - Oxford Studies in Metaethics 13:123-144.
    People engage in pure moral inquiry whenever they inquire into the moral features of some act, agent, or state of affairs without inquiring into the non-moral features of that act, agent, or state of affairs. This chapter argues that ordinary people act rationally when they engage in pure moral inquiry, and so any adequate view in metaethics ought to be able to explain this fact. The Puzzle of Pure Moral Motivation is how to provide such an explanation. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  27.  59
    Intentional action and pure causality: A critical discussion of some central conceptual distinctions in the work of Jon Elster.Tore Sandven - 1995 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 25 (3):286-317.
    This article discusses fundamental problems in "rational choice theory," as outlined by Jon Elster. Elster's discussion of why institutions may not be said to act shows his fundamental presupposition that only "monolithic," unitary entities are capable of action. This is, for him, a reason why only individual human beings may be said to act. Furthermore, human beings may be said to act only insofar as they "maximize" (their "utility") on the basis of a unitary, complete, consistent "preference structure." All action (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  28. The Threefold Referral of Acts to the Ultimate End in Thomas Aquinas and His Commentators.Thomas M. Osborne Jr - 2008 - Angelicum 85:715-736.
    Thomas discusses the referral of acts to the ultimate end unsystematically and in diverse texts. These texts are interesting in that they raise difficult questions. For example, on Thomas’s view there can be a disparity between the moral value of the act and that of the ultimate end. But what does he mean when he claims that venial sins may be habitually referred to God as the supernatural ultimate end? Moreover, he claims both that every good is desired for the (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  35
    Kant and the Capacity to Judge; Sensibility and Discursivity in the TranscendentaI Analytic of the Critique of Pure Reason (review).Michelle Greer - 1999 - Journal of the History of Philosophy 37 (2):372-374.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:Kant and the Capacity to Judge; Sensibility and Discursivity in the Transcendental Analytic of the Critique of Pure Reason by Beatrice LonguenesseMichelle GreerBeatrice Longuenesse. Kant and the Capacity to Judge; Sensibility and Discursivity in the Transcendental Analytic of the Critique of Pure Reason. Translation by Charles T. Wolfe. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998. Pp. xv + 420. Cloth, $59.50.Kant and the Capacity to Judge is (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. There Are No Purely Aesthetic Obligations.John Dyck - 2021 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 102 (4):592-612.
    Do aesthetic reasons have normative authority over us? Could there be anything like an aesthetic ‘ought’ or an aesthetic obligation? I argue that there are no aesthetic obligations. We have reasons to act certain ways regarding various aesthetic objects – most notably, reasons to attend to and appreciate those objects. But, I argue, these reasons never amount to duties. This is because aesthetic reasons are merely evaluative, not deontic. They can only entice us or invite us – they can never (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  31. Acting Intentionally and Acting for a Reason.Maria Alvarez - 2009 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 52 (3):293-305.
    This paper explores the question whether whatever is done intentionally is done for a reason. Apart from helping us to think about those concepts, the question is interesting because it affords an opportunity to identify a number of misconceptions about reasons. In the paper I argue that there are things that are done intentionally but not done for a reason. I examine two different kinds of example: things done “because one wants to” and “purely expressive actions”. Concerning the first, I (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  32.  31
    A Unificationist Approach to Wrongful Pure Risking.Kritika Maheshwari - 2024 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 68.
    What makes cases of pure risking sometimes wrong? There is a strong intuition that the wrongness of pure risking stands in an explanatory relationship with the wrongness of the non-risky act, other things being equal. Yet, we cannot simply take this for granted insofar as in cases of wrongful pure risking, the risked outcome fails to materialize. To this end, I motivate and develop an underexplored approach in the literature that I call Unificationism. According to the Unificationist (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Reasons explanations and pure agency.Richard H. Feldman & Andrei A. Buckareff - 2003 - Philosophical Studies 112 (2):135-145.
    We focus on the recent non-causal theory of reasons explanationsof free action proffered by a proponent of the agency theory, Timothy O'Connor. We argue that the conditions O'Connor offersare neither necessary nor sufficient for a person to act for a reason. Finally, we note that the role O'Connor assigns toreasons in the etiology of actions results in further conceptual difficulties for agent-causalism.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34.  45
    "Out of the Order of Number": Benjamin and Irigaray Toward a Politics of Pure Means.Peter D. Fenves - 1998 - Diacritics 28 (1):43-58.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:“Out of the Order of Number”: Benjamin and Irigaray Toward a Politics of Pure MeansPeter Fenves* (bio)At the heart of the legal orders that arose in conjunction with the Enlightenment idea of law as rules of conduct universally applicable to all those who belong to a properly instituted political body lies a formula for the justification of the violence on which the law depends in order for it (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  35.  64
    Rights to Liberty in Purely Private Matters: Part II.Jonathan Riley - 1990 - Economics and Philosophy 6 (1):27-64.
    A claim that certain purely private matters should be beyond the reach of society's laws, moral rules, and other customs is central to the distinctive liberalism of John Stuart Mill. On Liberty, perhaps the most eloquent defense of individual liberty ever written, laments the hostility allegedly displayed in modern mass societies toward “the right of each individual to act [in private matters] as seems good to his judgement and inclinations”. In Mill's view, a free society must design its institutions with (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  36.  17
    “Descriptive Metaphysics”, Descriptive Analytics, Descriptive Aesthetics. The Structure of Cognition in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.Mukhutdinov Oleg - 2020 - Studies in Transcendental Philosophy 1 (1).
    The article considers possibility of applying the concept of descriptive metaphysics to the project of Kant's transcendental philosophy. According to analytical philosophy, descriptive metaphysics is the description of structures of thinking about the world. The basis for describing acts of thinking about the world from Kant's point of view is the description of forms of intuition. Transcendental (descriptive) analysis of understanding must be preceded by transcendental (descriptive) aesthetics as an investigation of pure intuitions of space and time. Phenomenon of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. The Gravity of Pure Forces.Nico Jenkins - 2011 - Continent 1 (1):60-67.
    continent. 1.1 (2011): 60-67. At the beginning of Martin Heidegger’s lecture “Time and Being,” presented to the University of Freiburg in 1962, he cautions against, it would seem, the requirement that philosophy make sense, or be necessarily responsible (Stambaugh, 1972). At that time Heidegger's project focused on thinking as thinking and in order to elucidate his ideas he drew comparisons between his project and two paintings by Paul Klee as well with a poem by Georg Trakl. In front of Klee's (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Linguistic intuitions in context: a defense of nonskeptical pure invariantism.John Turri - 2014 - In Anthony Robert Booth & Darrell P. Rowbottom (eds.), Intuitions. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press UK. pp. 165-184.
    Epistemic invariantism is the view that the truth conditions of knowledge ascriptions don’t vary across contexts. Epistemic purism is the view that purely practical factors can’t directly affect the strength of your epistemic position. The combination of purism and invariantism, pure invariantism, is the received view in contemporary epistemology. It has lately been criticized by contextualists, who deny invariantism, and impurists, who deny purism. A central charge against pure invariantism is that it poorly accommodates linguistic intuitions about certain (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39. Années, 1781-1801: Kant, critique de la raison pure, vingt ans de réception: actes du 5e Congrès international de la Société d'études kantiennes de langue française, Montréal, 27-29 septembre 2001.Claude Piché (ed.) - 2002 - Paris: Libr. philosophique J. Vrin.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  66
    Mapping the Imagination: Distinct Acts, Objects, and Modalities.Rudolf Bernet - 2020 - Husserl Studies 36 (3):213-226.
    This article begins by presenting the two most important transformations that establish a genuine Husserlian approach to the imagination: the first lies in the grasping of imagination, despite its essential differences with perception and hallucination, as an intuitive, or sensuous consciousness ; the second lies in the insight that imagination, or better – phantasy –, requires no images, mental or otherwise. Further, the distinction between pure and perceptual phantasies and their respective fictional objects is drawn out. A comparison between (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  41.  23
    Pure Experience and Historical Reality.G. Gentile - 2014 - Collingwood and British Idealism Studies 20 (1-2):277-309.
    In this, Gentile's inaugural lecture delivered at the University of Pisa in 1914, he describes his approach to and conception of history. The opening sections of the lecture display a more personal and relaxed, at times effusive side to Gentile's writing as he praises his former teachers, offering readers some insight into his influences and his view of his own philosophical project. In the later sections, he turns to the technical question of how we, as concrete subjects living, thinking and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  24
    Performative updates and the modeling of speech acts.Manfred Krifka - 2024 - Synthese 203 (1):1-31.
    This paper develops a way to model performative speech acts within a framework of dynamic semantics. It introduces a distinction between performative and informative updates, where informative updates filter out indices of context sets (cf. Stalnaker, Cole (ed), Pragmatics, Academic Press, 1978), whereas performative updates change their indices (cf. Szabolcsi, Kiefer (ed), Hungarian linguistics, John Benjamins, 1982). The notion of index change is investigated in detail, identifying implementations by a function or by a relation. Declarations like _the meeting is (hereby) (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  5
    Prometheus Underground: Probing the Scientist in Depth as the Carnal First Act of French Phenomenology with Arnaud Dandieu and Claude Chevalley.Christian Roy - 2024 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 38 (3):274-286.
    ABSTRACT Arnaud Dandieu (1897–1933), a Personalist transdisciplinary thinker, joined up with Claude Chevalley (1909–84), cofounder of the Bourbaki group of mathematicians, to conduct a phenomenological study of the scientist’s activity over several articles. It shows the current development of “carnal hermeneutics” already present among the earliest manifestations of French phenomenology, in a tactile approach to the sense of depth as key to the search for knowledge, from the sorcerer to the scientist, building on the phenomenological psychology of Eugène Minkowski (1885–1972). (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44. The Phenomenon of Ego-Splitting in Husserl’s Phenomenology of Pure Phantasy.Marco Cavallaro - 2017 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 48 (2):162-177.
    Husserl’s phenomenology of imagination embraces a cluster of different theories and approaches regarding the multi-faced phenomenon of imaginative experience. In this paper I consider one aspect that seems to be crucial to the understanding of a particular form of imagination that Husserl names pure phantasy. I argue that the phenomenon of Ego-splitting discloses the best way to elucidate the peculiarity of pure phantasy with respect to other forms of representative acts and to any simple form of act modification. (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  45. Mental Acts and Mechanistic Psychology in Descartes' Passions.Gary Hatfield - 2007 - In Neil G. Robertson, Gordon McOuat & Thomas C. Vinci (eds.), Descartes and the Modern. Cambridge Scholars Press. pp. 49-71.
    This chapter examines the mechanistic psychology of Descartes in the _Passions_, while also drawing on the _Treatise on Man_. It develops the idea of a Cartesian “psychology” that relies on purely bodily mechanisms by showing that he explained some behaviorally appropriate responses through bodily mechanisms alone and that he envisioned the tailoring of such responses to environmental circumstances through a purely corporeal “memory.” An animal’s adjustment of behavior as caused by recurring patterns of sensory stimulation falls under the notion of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  43
    Canon as an Act of Creation: Giorgio Agamben and the Extended Logic of the Messianic.Colby Dickinson - 2010 - Bijdragen 71 (2):132-158.
    The ‘messianic’ is one of philosophy’s most appropriated religious terms, yet one apparently now bereft of its historical religious particularity. This essay thus explores a genealogical approach to the ‘messianic’ which might prove helpful in uncovering the reasons for this transformation from the theological to the philosophical, and what role, if any, theology still has in determining the meaning and usage of this term. Accordingly, this essay traces the term through the work of Walter Benjamin, Jacques Derrida and Giorgio Agamben. (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  47. Space as Form of Intuition and as Formal Intuition: On the Note to B160 in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason.Christian Onof & Dennis Schulting - 2015 - Philosophical Review 124 (1):1-58.
    In his argument for the possibility of knowledge of spatial objects, in the Transcendental Deduction of the B-version of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant makes a crucial distinction between space as “form of intuition” and space as “formal intuition.” The traditional interpretation regards the distinction between the two notions as reflecting a distinction between indeterminate space and determinations of space by the understanding, respectively. By contrast, a recent influential reading has argued that the two notions can be fused (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  48. Practical reasons to believe, epistemic reasons to act, and the baffled action theorist.Nomy Arpaly - 2023 - Philosophical Issues 33 (1):22-32.
    I argue that unless belief is voluntary in a very strict sense – that is, unless credence is simply under our direct control – there can be no practical reasons to believe. I defend this view against recent work by Susanna Rinard. I then argue that for very similar reasons, barring the truth of strict doxastic voluntarism, there cannot be epistemic reasons to act, only purely practical reasons possessed by those whose goal is attaining knowledge or justified belief.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  49.  43
    The Three Minds and Faith, Hope, and Love in Pure Land Buddhism.Sharon Baker - 2005 - Buddhist-Christian Studies 25 (1):49-65.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Buddhist-Christian Studies 25 (2005) 49-65 [Access article in PDF] The Three Minds and Faith, Hope, and Love in Pure Land Buddhism Sharon Baker Southern Methodist University,Messiah College Generally, the Buddhist path to nirvana calls a person to leave the mundane life and live as a monk, a sage, or a saint who continually works toward the pure state, toward nirvana. The way to Buddhahood can take the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Imagination in Kant's "Critique of Pure Reason".Soraj Hongladarom - 1991 - Dissertation, Indiana University
    The role and nature of imagination in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason is intensively examined. In addition, the text of Kant's Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View will also be considered because it helps illustrate this issue. Imagination is the fundamental power of the mind responsible for any act of forming and putting together representations. A new interpretation of imagination in Kant is given which recognizes its necessary roles as the factor responsible for producing space and time, as (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 966