Results for 'Rigor'

971 found
Order:
  1.  49
    Rigor and Structure.John P. Burgess - 2015 - Oxford, England: Oxford University Press UK.
    While we are commonly told that the distinctive method of mathematics is rigorous proof, and that the special topic of mathematics is abstract structure, there has been no agreement among mathematicians, logicians, or philosophers as to just what either of these assertions means. John P. Burgess clarifies the nature of mathematical rigor and of mathematical structure, and above all of the relation between the two, taking into account some of the latest developments in mathematics, including the rise of experimental (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  2.  91
    Mathematical rigor, proof gap and the validity of mathematical inference.Yacin Hamami - 2014 - Philosophia Scientiae 18 (1):7-26.
    Mathematical rigor is commonly formulated by mathematicians and philosophers using the notion of proof gap: a mathematical proof is rig­orous when there is no gaps in the mathematical reasoning of the proof. Any philosophical approach to mathematical rigor along this line requires then an account of what a proof gap is. However, the notion of proof gap makes sense only relatively to a given conception of valid mathematical reasoning, i.e., to a given conception of the validity of mathematical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  3.  88
    Mathematical rigor and proof.Yacin Hamami - 2022 - Review of Symbolic Logic 15 (2):409-449.
    Mathematical proof is the primary form of justification for mathematical knowledge, but in order to count as a proper justification for a piece of mathematical knowl- edge, a mathematical proof must be rigorous. What does it mean then for a mathematical proof to be rigorous? According to what I shall call the standard view, a mathematical proof is rigorous if and only if it can be routinely translated into a formal proof. The standard view is almost an orthodoxy among contemporary (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  4. A rigorous proof of determinism derived from the special theory of relativity.C. W. Rietdijk - 1966 - Philosophy of Science 33 (4):341-344.
    A proof is given that there does not exist an event, that is not already in the past for some possible distant observer at the (our) moment that the latter is "now" for us. Such event is as "legally" past for that distant observer as is the moment five minutes ago on the sun for us (irrespective of the circumstance that the light of the sun cannot reach us in a period of five minutes). Only an extreme positivism: "that which (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   94 citations  
  5. Rigorous results, cross-model justification, and the transfer of empirical warrant: the case of many-body models in physics.Axel Gelfert - 2009 - Synthese 169 (3):497-519.
    This paper argues that a successful philosophical analysis of models and simulations must accommodate an account of mathematically rigorous results. Such rigorous results may be thought of as genuinely model-specific contributions, which can neither be deduced from fundamental theory nor inferred from empirical data. Rigorous results provide new indirect ways of assessing the success of models and simulations and are crucial to understanding the connections between different models. This is most obvious in cases where rigorous results map different models on (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  6. Rigor in Research, Honesty and Values.M. Hohl - 2016 - Constructivist Foundations 11 (3):585-586.
    Open peer commentary on the article “Design Research as a Variety of Second-Order Cybernetic Practice” by Ben Sweeting. Upshot: I reflect on the theme of honesty in research and discuss the adjoining requirements of rigor from an academic perspective. Central to my discussion is Glanville’s assertion that what researchers - from either science or design - presented was not what they actually thought and did.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  32
    Republican Rigorism: Hegelian Views of Emancipation in 1848.Douglas Moggach - 2003 - The European Legacy 8 (4):441-457.
    This paper examines whether Bruno Bauer's critical assessment of Jewish emancipation in Prussia is consistent with his other republican writings in the 1840s. It argues that Bauer's political position is a form of republican rigorism, according to which human emancipation requires identification with universal interests, and not the defence of particular identities. Rigorism involves the elimination of internal as well as external heteronomous influences, and implies shifting the boundaries between the juridical and the moral realms as defined by Kant. Subjects' (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Mathematical Rigor in Physics: Putting Exact Results in Their Place.Axel Gelfert - 2005 - Philosophy of Science 72 (5):723-738.
    The present paper examines the role of exact results in the theory of many‐body physics, and specifically the example of the Mermin‐Wagner theorem, a rigorous result concerning the absence of phase transitions in low‐dimensional systems. While the theorem has been shown to hold for a wide range of many‐body models, it is frequently ‘violated’ by results derived from the same models using numerical techniques. This raises the question of how scientists regulate their theoretical commitments in such cases, given that the (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  9.  14
    Rigorous Purposes of Analysis in Greek Geometry.Viktor Blåsjö - 2021 - Philosophia Scientiae 25:55-80.
    Analyses in Greek geometry are traditionally seen as heuristic devices. However, many occurrences of analysis in formal treatises are difficult to justify in such terms. I show that Greek analysies of geometrics can also serve formal mathematical purposes, which are arguably incomplete without which their associated syntheses are arguably incomplete. Firstly, when the solution of a problem is preceded by an analysis, the analysis latter proves rigorously that there are no other solutions to the problem than those offered in the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  10.  26
    O rigor científico: princípios elementares extraídos de Aristóteles no interesse da teologia.Clodovis Boff - 2015 - Horizonte 13 (39):1559-1579.
    Against the modern tendency to considerate just the formal-empirical knowledge as Science, and this one mathematized as much as possible, here many declarations of Aristotle are raised in order to show that the scientific rigour is not univocal but analogic: it is determined according to the nature of the object to be known. This is a so elementary epistemological rule that not knowing it is understood by that philosopher as apaideusia, i.e., lack of basic education in the knowledge sphere in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. On rigorous definitions.Nuel Belnap - 1993 - Philosophical Studies 72 (2-3):115 - 146.
  12. Reconciling Rigor and Intuition.Silvia De Toffoli - 2020 - Erkenntnis 86 (6):1783-1802.
    Criteria of acceptability for mathematical proofs are field-dependent. In topology, though not in most other domains, it is sometimes acceptable to appeal to visual intuition to support inferential steps. In previous work :829–842, 2014; Lolli, Panza, Venturi From logic to practice, Springer, Berlin, 2015; Larvor Mathematical cultures, Springer, Berlin, 2016) my co-author and I aimed at spelling out how topological proofs work on their own terms, without appealing to formal proofs which might be associated with them. In this article, I (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  13. Rigorous information-theoretic derivation of quantum-statistical thermodynamics. II.William Band & James L. Park - 1977 - Foundations of Physics 7 (9-10):705-721.
    Part I of the present work outlined the rigorous application of information theory to a quantum mechanical system in a thermodynamic equilibrium state. The general formula developed there for the best-guess density operator $\hat \rho$ was indeterminate because it involved in an essential way an unspecified prior probability distribution over the continuumD H of strong equilibrium density operators. In Part II mathematical evaluation of $\hat \rho$ is completed after an epistemological analysis which leads first to the discretization ofD H and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14. What is Mathematical Rigor?John Burgess & Silvia De Toffoli - 2022 - Aphex 25:1-17.
    Rigorous proof is supposed to guarantee that the premises invoked imply the conclusion reached, and the problem of rigor may be described as that of bringing together the perspectives of formal logic and mathematical practice on how this is to be achieved. This problem has recently raised a lot of discussion among philosophers of mathematics. We survey some possible solutions and argue that failure to understand its terms properly has led to misunderstandings in the literature.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  15.  20
    Rigorism of Truth: "Moses the Egyptian" and Other Writings on Freud and Arendt.Hans Blumenberg - 2017 - Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Edited by Ahlrich Meyer & Joe Paul Kroll.
    In "Moses the Egyptian"--the centerpiece of Rigorism of Truth, the German philosopher Hans Blumenberg addresses two defining figures in the intellectual history of the twentieth century: Sigmund Freud and Hannah Arendt. Unpublished during his lifetime, this essay analyzes Freud's Moses and Monotheism and Arendt's Eichmann in Jerusalem, and discovers in both a principled rigidity that turns into recklessness because it is blind to the politics of the unknown. Offering striking insights into the importance of myth in politics and the extent (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  16.  33
    A rigorous approach for testing the constructionist hypotheses of brain function.Gopikrishna Deshpande, K. Sathian, Xiaoping Hu & Joseph A. Buckhalt - 2012 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 35 (3):148-149.
    Although the target article provides strong evidence against the locationist view, evidence for the constructionist view is inconclusive, because co-activation of brain regions does not necessarily imply connectivity between them. We propose a rigorous approach wherein connectivity between co-activated regions is first modeled using exploratory Granger causality, and then confirmed using dynamic causal modeling or Bayesian modeling.
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Kantian rigorism and mitigating circumstances.Tamar Schapiro - 2006 - Ethics 117 (1):32–57.
    A task of any moral theory is to account for both the rigidity and the flexibility of moral rules. Utilitarianism faces the problem of building rigidity into a framework that tends towards objectionable flexibility. Kantianism faces the problem of building flexibility into a framework that tends towards objectionable rigidity. I offer an argument on this front on behalf of Kantians. I show how Kantians can maintain that actions are right and wrong "in themselves," while still maintaining that such actions can (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  18.  20
    (1 other version)Rigorism and the 'New Kant'.Robert B. Pippin - 2001 - In Volker Gerhardt, Rolf-Peter Horstmann & Ralph Schumacher (eds.), Kant Und Die Berliner Aufklärung: Akten des IX Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. New York: Walter de Gruyter. pp. 313-326.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  19.  10
    Hans Blumenberg on the rigorism of truth and the strangeness of the past.James Kent - 2021 - Thesis Eleven 165 (1):37-52.
    In this paper I discuss Hans Blumenberg’s The Rigorism of Truth, a short polemic that criticizes Freud and Hannah Arendt for placing a misplaced faith in the liberatory potential of rational truth in moments of historical disaster. The secondary literature suggests that this piece exhibits either all the signs of a late, Romantic capitulation to the ‘need’ for myth, or Blumenberg’s failure to recognize his own faith and debts to the ‘mythology’ of reason’s emancipatory hopes. My argument hinges on the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Can Philosophy be a Rigorous Science?Herman Philipse - 2009 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 65:155-176.
    It is difficult to imagine that a Royal Institute of Physics would organize an annual lecture series on the theme ‘conceptions of physics’. Similarly, it is quite improbable that a Royal Institute of Astronomy would even contemplate inviting speakers for a lecture series called ‘conceptions of astronomy’. What, then, is so special about philosophy that the theme of this lecture series does not appear to be altogether outlandish? Is it, perhaps, that philosophy is the reflective discipline par excellence, so that (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  21.  41
    Rigor and Clarity: Foundations of Mathematics in France and England, 1800–1840.Joan L. Richards - 1991 - Science in Context 4 (2):297-319.
    The ArgumentIt has long been apparent that in the nineteenth century, mathematics in France and England developed along different lines. The differences, which might well be labelled stylistic, are most easy to see on the foundational level. At first this may seem surprising because it is such a fundamental area, but, upon reflection, it is to be expected. Ultimately discussions about the foundations of mathematics turn on views about what mathematics is, and this is a question which is answered by (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  22. A rigorous analytic solution of nonlinear differential equation of the poisson-bolitzmann type.S. N. Bagchi & G. P. Das - 1965 - In Karl W. Linsenmann (ed.), Proceedings. St. Louis, Lutheran Academy for Scholarship. pp. 29--28.
  23.  31
    Rigorous Solution of Slopes’ Stability considering Hydrostatic Pressure.Chengchao Li, Pengming Jiang & Aizhao Zhou - 2018 - Complexity 2018:1-10.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. A Rigorous Analysis of the Clauser–Horne–Shimony–Holt Inequality Experiment When Trials Need Not be Independent.Peter Bierhorst - 2014 - Foundations of Physics 44 (7):736-761.
    The Clauser–Horne–Shimony–Holt (CHSH) inequality is a constraint that local hidden variable theories must obey. Quantum Mechanics predicts a violation of this inequality in certain experimental settings. Treatments of this subject frequently make simplifying assumptions about the probability spaces available to a local hidden variable theory, such as assuming the state of the system is a discrete or absolutely continuous random variable, or assuming that repeated experimental trials are independent and identically distributed. In this paper, we do two things: first, show (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  7
    Rigor and objectivity as foundations of the rationality of physics in Evandro Agazzi.Linda Marcela Rivera Guerrero, Arjuna Gabriel Castellanos Muñoz & Carlos Andrés Gómez Rodas - 2024 - Sophia. Colección de Filosofía de la Educación 37:47-77.
    En la epistemología actual, hay dos actitudes opuestas en relación con las ciencias empíricas.Por una parte, aparecen como herramienta esencial para el avance del conocimiento. Por otro lado, existe duda sobre las bases metafísicas y epistemológicas de esa confianza en el saber científico, lo cual ha llevado a la ciencia por caminos de escepticismo y pragmatismo. Este trabajo se propone aportar filosóficamente a la racionalidad y al estatuto ontológico de la física, teniendo como punto de partida algunas obras del filósofo (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  14
    The Rigor of a Certain Inhumanity: Toward a Wider Suffrage.John Llewelyn - 2012 - Indiana University Press.
    The Rigor of a Certain Inhumanity is a rich and passionate, playful and perceptive work of philosophical analysis.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27. Mathematical rigor in physics.Mark Steiner - 1992 - In Michael Detlefsen (ed.), Proof and Knowledge in Mathematics. New York: Routledge. pp. 158.
  28.  25
    Rigor and the Context-Dependence of Diagrams: The Case of Euler Diagrams.David Waszek - 2004 - In A. Blackwell, K. Marriott & A. Shimojima (eds.), Diagrammatic Representation and Inference. Springer. pp. 382-389.
    Euler famously used diagrams to illustrate syllogisms in his Lettres à une princesse d’Allemagne [1]. His diagrams are usually seen as suffering from a fatal “ambiguity problem” [11]: as soon as they involve intersecting circles, which are required for the representation of existential statements, it becomes unclear what exactly may be read off from them, and as Hammer & Shin conclusively showed, any set of reading conventions can lead to erroneous conclusions. I claim that Euler diagrams can, however, be used (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  34
    Rigorous Reasoning.Peter Cave - 1994 - Philosophy Now 9:14-17.
  30.  14
    Rigor mortis: how sloppy science creates worthless cures, crushes hope, and wastes billions.Richard Harris - 2017 - New York: Basic Books.
    American taxpayers spend $30 billion annually funding biomedical research. By some estimates, half of the results from these studies can't be replicated elsewhere-the science is simply wrong. Often, research institutes and academia emphasize publishing results over getting the right answers, incentivizing poor experimental design, improper methods, and sloppy statistics. Bad science doesn't just hold back medical progress, it can sign the equivalent of a death sentence. How are those with breast cancer helped when the cell on which 900 papers are (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  31.  7
    The psychology of rigorous humanism.Joseph Frank Rychlak - 1987 - New York: New York University Press.
    In this second edition, Joseph Rychlak has retained his analysis of the philosophical antecedents of psychology and, at the same time, has considerably revised more complicated material illustration rigorous humanism to make the book more accessible for students. Rychlak here offers an analysis of the philosophical traditions underlying the social sciences and shows how functionalism came to dominate the modern science of psychology in America.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  32. Republican rigorism and emancipation in Bruno Bauer.Douglas Moggach - 2006 - In The New Hegelians: Politics and Philosophy in the Hegelian School. New York: Cambridge University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Mathematical rigor--who needs it?Philip Kitcher - 1981 - Noûs 15 (4):469-493.
  34. The rigorous concept of aesthetics as philosophical discipline and its critics.Antonio Gutierrez Pozo - 2012 - Pensamiento 68 (256):199-224.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. Is mathematical rigor necessary in physics?Kevin Davey - 2003 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54 (3):439-463.
    Many arguments found in the physics literature involve concepts that are not well-defined by the usual standards of mathematics. I argue that physicists are entitled to employ such concepts without rigorously defining them so long as they restrict the sorts of mathematical arguments in which these concepts are involved. Restrictions of this sort allow the physicist to ignore calculations involving these concepts that might lead to contradictory results. I argue that such restrictions need not be ad hoc, but can sometimes (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  36. Modalities in Ackermann's “rigorous implication”.Alan Ross Anderson & Nuel D. Belnap - 1959 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 24 (2):107-111.
    Following a suggestion of Feys, we use “rigorous implication” as a translation of Ackermann's strenge Implikation ([1]). Interest in Ackermann's system stems in part from the fact that it formalizes the properties of a strong, natural sort of implication which provably avoids standard implicational paradoxes, and which is consequently a good candidate for a formalization of entailment (considered as a narrower relation than that of strict implication). Our present purpose will not be to defend this suggestion, but rather to present (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  37.  21
    Mathematical Rigor and the Origin of the Exhaustion Method.Theokritos Kouremenos - 1997 - Centaurus 39 (3):230-252.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  38.  32
    Toward a rigorous quantum field theory.Stanley Gudder - 1994 - Foundations of Physics 24 (9):1205-1225.
    This paper outlines a framework that may provide a mathematically rigorous quantum field theory. The framework relies upon the methods of nonstandard analysis. A theory of nonstandard inner product spaces and operators on these spaces is first developed. This theory is then applied to construct nonstandard Fock spaces which extend the standard Fock spaces. Then a rigorous framework for the field operators of quantum field theory is presented. The results are illustrated for the case of Klein-Gordon fields.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  90
    Between Rigor and Reality: Many-Body Models in Condensed Matter Physics.Axel Gelfert - 2015 - In Brigitte Falkenburg & Margaret Morrison (eds.), Why More is Different: Philosophical Issues in Condensed Matter Physics and Complex Systems. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer. pp. 201-226.
    The present paper focuses on a particular class of models intended to describe and explain the physical behaviour of systems that consist of a large number of interacting particles. Such many-body models are characterized by a specific Hamiltonian (energy operator) and are frequently employed in condensed matter physics in order to account for such phenomena as magnetism, superconductivity, and other phase transitions. Because of the dual role of many-body models as models of physical sys-tems (with specific physical phenomena as their (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Rigor, Reproof and Bolzano's Critical Program.Michael Detlefsen - 2010 - In Pierre Edouard Bour, Manuel Rebuschi & Laurent Rollet (eds.), Construction: A Festschrift for Gerhard Heinzmann. King's College Publications. pp. 171-184.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  14
    Rigorous Standards, At What Price? Or What Will Students Learn When No One is Looking?Barbara Applebaum - 2001 - Paideusis: Journal of the Canadian Philosophy of Education Society 14 (1):15-29.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  15
    Der Rigor der Gerechtigkeit: Eine an der Triage in der COVID-19-Pandemie orientierte theologische Analyse.Mathias Wirth - 2021 - Zeitschrift Für Evangelische Ethik 65 (3):202-214.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  61
    Rigor; or, stupid uselessness.Geoffrey Bennington - 2012 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 50 (s1):20-38.
    In his seminars on the death penalty, Derrida consistently describes Kant's arguments in favor of capital punishment as “rigorous” and explicitly relates that rigor to the mechanisms of execution and the subsequent rigor mortis of the corpse. ‘Rigor’ has also often been a contested term in descriptions of deconstruction: different commentators have either deplored or celebrated the presence or the absence of rigor in Derrida's work. Derrida himself uses the term a good deal throughout his career, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  44.  8
    The Modern Project to Rigor: Descartes to Nietzsche.Patrick Madigan - 1985 - Upa.
    Building on the works of Popkin, Gilson, Fackenheim, and Kaufmann, the author expands the scope of what can be treated by the hypothesis of skepticism or pursuit of rigor in the modern world.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  2
    Intellectually Rigorous but Morally Tolerant: Exploring Moral Leniency as a Mediator Between Cognitive Style and “Utilitarian” Judgment.Manon D. Gouiran & Florian Cova - 2024 - Cognitive Science 48 (12):e70024.
    Past research on people's moral judgments about moral dilemmas has revealed a connection between utilitarian judgment and reflective cognitive style. This has traditionally been interpreted as reflection is conducive to utilitarianism. However, recent research shows that the connection between reflective cognitive style and utilitarian judgments holds only when participants are asked whether the utilitarian option is permissible, and disappears when they are asked whether it is recommended. To explain this phenomenon, we propose that reflective cognitive style is associated with a (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  75
    Rigorous proof and the history of mathematics: Comments on Crowe.Douglas Jesseph - 1990 - Synthese 83 (3):449 - 453.
    Duhem's portrayal of the history of mathematics as manifesting calm and regular development is traced to his conception of mathematical rigor as an essentially static concept. This account is undermined by citing controversies over rigorous demonstration from the eighteenth and twentieth centuries.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  22
    Rigor and formalization.Pawel Pawlowski & Karim Zahidi - 2024 - Synthese 203 (3):1-18.
    This paper critically examines and evaluates Yacin Hamami’s reconstruction of the standard view of mathematical rigor. We will argue that the reconstruction offered by Hamami is premised on a strong and controversial epistemological thesis and a strong and controversial thesis in the philosophy of mind. Secondly, we will argue that Hamami’s reconstruction of the standard view robs it of its original philosophical rationale, i.e. making sense of the notion of rigor in mathematical practice.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  48.  16
    A Rigorous Set Theoretical Foundation of the Structuralist Approach.H. Peter - 1996 - In Wolfgang Balzer & Carles Ulises Moulines (eds.), Structuralist theory of science: focal issues, new results. New York: Walter de Gruyter. pp. 6--233.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  41
    Extremely rigorous subliminal paradigms demonstrate unconscious influences on simple decisions.Michael Snodgrass, Howard Shevrin & James A. Abelson - 2014 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 37 (1):39-40.
  50. Phenomenology as rigorous science.Taylor Carman - 2007 - In Brian Leiter & Michael Rosen (eds.), The Oxford handbook of continental philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.
    Edmund Husserl, the founder of modern phenomenology, always insisted that philosophy is not just a scholarly discipline, but can and must aspire to the status of a ‘strict’ or ‘rigorous science’ (strenge Wissenschaft). Heidegger, by contrast, began his winter lectures in 1929 by dismissing what he called the ‘delusion’ that philosophy was or could be either a discipline or a science as the most disastrous debasement of its innermost essence. To understand what Husserl had in mind, it is important to (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
1 — 50 / 971