Results for 'Suspensive wronging'

953 found
Order:
  1. Suspensive Wronging.Chris Ranalli - 2025 - In Verena Wagner & Zinke Alexandra, Suspension in epistemology and beyond. New York, NY: Routledge.
    According to the thesis of doxastic wronging, we can wrong people in virtue of having certain beliefs about them. In this chapter, I motivate and defend a similar view, the thesis of suspensive wronging, that we can wrong people in virtue of bearing an indecision attitude towards certain questions that bear on certain people. I explore the extent to which the thesis of suspensive wronging fits with certain prominent conceptions of suspension of judgment, including the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2. Faith and the suspension of the ethical in fear and trembling.Andrew Cross - 2003 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 46 (1):3 – 28.
    This paper concerns Kierkegaard's notion of a teleological suspension of the ethical, which is presented by his pseudonym Johannes de Silentio in Fear and Trembling in connection with the biblical narrative of Abraham's sacrifice of Isaac. Against prevailing readings, I argue that Abraham's suspension of the ethical does not consist in his violating the ethical in order to satisfy a higher normative requirement. Rather, it consists in his preparedness to violate an overriding ethical norm, even where he does not believe (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  3. What's Wrong with Partisan Deference?Elise Woodard - forthcoming - In Tamar Szabó Gendler, John Hawthorne, Julianne Chung & Alex Worsnip, Oxford Studies in Epistemology, Vol. 8. Oxford University Press.
    Deference in politics is often necessary. To answer questions like, “Should the government increase the federal minimum wage?” and “Should the state introduce a vaccine mandate?”, we need to know relevant scientific and economic facts, make complex value judgments, and answer questions about incentives and implementation. Lay citizens typically lack the time, resources, and competence to answer these questions on their own. Hence, they must defer to others. But to whom should they defer? A common answer is that they should—or (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  74
    The way things go: moral relativism and suspension of judgment.Eduardo Pérez-Navarro - 2021 - Philosophical Studies 179 (1):49-64.
    A popular accusation against moral relativism is that it goes too far in its vindication of tolerance. The idea behind accusations like this can be summarized in the slogan, frequently attributed to relativism, that “anything goes”. The aim of this paper is to defend moral relativism from the accusation that it is an “anything goes” view; from the accusation that it forces us to suspend our judgment in cases in which we do not think we should even be allowed to. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  5.  36
    What is wrong with the emergency justification of compulsory medical service?Eszter Kollar - 2017 - Journal of Medical Ethics 43 (8):560-561.
    Michael Blake holds that liberal states are precluded from introducing compulsory medical service to improve access to health care under conditions of critical health worker shortage. "Emergency circumstances" are the only exception when the suspension of liberty may be justified. I argue that there are three problems with Blake's emergency justification of compulsory service. First, his concept of emergency is vague. Second, his account does not really rely on emergency as much as liberty. Third, his conception of permissible restrictions of (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  20
    Waiting for Criticism.Cary Howie - 2008 - Diacritics 38 (4):43-58.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Waiting for CriticismCary Howie (bio)1Critical AttentionIf it is often the case that so much of what we do, as writers in a certain idiom and profession, is to wait for criticism—in the form of peer reviews, book reviews, tenure reviews, and so many other kinds of review that one would not be wrong to characterize the profession as constitutively myopic, incapable of seeing anything without looking at it again—there (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. The Deconstructive Angel.M. H. Abrams - 1977 - Critical Inquiry 3 (3):425-438.
    That brings me to the crux of my disagreement with Hillis Miller. The central contention is not simply that I am sometimes, or always, wrong in my interpretation, but instead that I—like other traditional historians—can never be right in my interpretation. For Miller assents to Nietzsche's challenge of "the concept of 'rightness' in interpretation," and to Nietzsche's assertion that "the same text authorizes innumerable interpretations : there is no 'correct' interpretation."1 Nietzsche's views of interpretation, as Miller says, are relevant to (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  8. Problems in Pleasants' Wittgensteinian Idea of Basic Moral Certainties.Jordi Fairhurst - 2019 - Ethical Perspectives 26 (2):271-298.
    Pleasants argues in favour of the idea of basic moral certainties. Analogous to Wittgenstein’s basic empirical certainties, basic moral certainties are universal certainties that cannot be justified, asserted or meaningfully doubted. They are a fundamental condition of morality as such, thus allowing us to carry out other moral operations. Brice and Rummens have criticized Pleasants’ proposal, arguing that basic moral certainties are significantly disanalogous to Wittgenstein’s basic empirical certainties. Brice argues that Pleasants does not differentiate between a bottom-up and a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  9.  49
    Abraham, Isaac, And The Jewish Tradition: An Ethical Reappraisal.Ronald M. Green - 1982 - Journal of Religious Ethics 10 (1):1-21.
    Would the Jewish tradition agree with Søren Kierkegaard's claim that the biblical episode of Abraham's near-sacrifice of Isaac represents a fearful "teleological suspension of the ethical"? After surveying a variety of classical Jewish sources, the author concludes that Kierkegaard's interpretation has almost no resonance within the Jewish tradition. Rather than involving a suspension of the ethical, this episode is viewed by Jewish writers as involving a moment of supreme moral responsibility on the part of both God and man. This treatment (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  10. Dr. George Cheyne, Chevalier Ramsay, and Hume's Letter to a Physician.John P. Wright - 2003 - Hume Studies 29 (1):125-141.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Studies Volume 29, Number 1, April 2003, pp. 125-141 Dr. George Cheyne, Chevalier Ramsay, and Hume's Letter to a Physician JOHN P. WRIGHT The publication of a new intellectual biography of George Cheyne1 provides a "propitious" occasion for "a thoroughly skeptical review"2 of the question which has long exercised Hume scholars, whether Cheyne was the intended recipient of David Hume's fascinating pie-Treatise Letter to a Physician,3 the letter (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  11. Reasons to Not Believe (and Reasons to Act).Blake Roeber - 2016 - Episteme 13 (4):439-48.
    In “Reasons to Believe and Reasons to Act,” Stewart Cohen argues that balance of reasons accounts of rational action get the wrong results when applied to doxastic attitudes, and that there are therefore important differences between reasons to believe and reasons to act. In this paper, I argue that balance of reasons accounts of rational action get the right results when applied to the cases that Cohen considers, and that these results highlight interesting similarities between reasons to believe and reasons (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  12.  34
    Vive la Différence.J. R. Lucas - 1978 - Philosophy 53 (205):363-.
    Some of my best friends are women, but I would not want my sister to marry one of them. Modern-minded persons criticize me for manifesting such out-dated prejudices, and would like to send me to Coventry for a compulsory course of reindoctrination. They may be right. It could conceivably be the case that in due course the Sex Discrimination Act will be tightened up, even to the extent of our recognizing that there are no ‘good reasons why the State should (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  13.  86
    Comic romance.Benjamin La Farge - 2009 - Philosophy and Literature 33 (1):pp. 18-35.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Comic RomanceBenjamin La FargeIOn the surface, it would seem that nothing could be more different from comedy than romance. Comedy deflates, romance inflates. Comedy is realistic, romance fantastical. Comedy reduces, romance elevates. Comedy is democratic, romance heroic. Yet there are underlying similarities. Both involve a conflict between destructive and restorative impulses. In both, appearances are typically mistaken for reality, and both end happily. Above all, both are governed by (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  32
    Compromise: What Makes it Bad?Nigel Biggar - 2018 - Studies in Christian Ethics 31 (1):34-48.
    This article considers what makes a compromise bad. First, it defines a compromise as a decision involving a loss of good (i.e., an evil), which should therefore be accompanied by ‘agent-regret’. Regret, however, is not moral guilt. Pace proponents of ‘dirty hands’, a morally right compromise cannot retain elements of moral wrongness (as distinct from non-moral evil). Second, the article proceeds to elaborate the features of bad compromise further in terms of common moral sense: the preference of less rather than (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  15. Once Again From the Beginning: On the Relationship of Skepticism and Philosophy in Hegel's System.Miles Hentrup - 2016 - Dissertation, Stony Brook University
    This dissertation examines the relationship of skepticism and philosophy in the work of G.W.F. Hegel. Whereas other commentators have come to recognize the epistemological significance of Hegel's encounter with skepticism, emphasizing the strength of his system against skeptical challenges to the possibility of knowledge, I argue that Hegel develops his metaphysics in part through his ongoing engagement with the skeptical tradition. As such, I argue that Hegel's interest is not in refuting skepticism, but in defining its legitimate role within the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. Phenomenology and Skepticism: A Critical Study of Husserl's Transcendental Idealism.David Blinder - 1981 - Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley
    The dissertation critically examines Husserl's transcendental idealism as a response to epistemological skepticism. Contrary to prevailing interpretations, I argue that Husserl intended to formulate a non-reductive, idealist justification of empirical knowledge. I take the standard phenomenalistic interpretation of Husserl's idealism to be right in discerning his basic concern with the refutation of skepticism, but wrong in construing the transcendental reduction as an ontological reduction of the natural world to "ideal" sets of transcendental experiences. On the other hand, recent "neutrality views" (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17.  27
    My Ability to Flourish.Paulette Koehler - 2013 - Narrative Inquiry in Bioethics 3 (3):4-5.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:My Ability to FlourishPaulette KoehlerIn twenty years of convulsions, I’ve never heard a neurologist mention the word “epilepsy.” Over this time, the intensity of my original simple partial seizures, “simple” signifying retained consciousness and “partial” indicating disturbances restricted to a specific area of my brain, grew to the complex level on my left temporal lobe. I believe this development was influenced by my use of prescribed medications. Several neurologists (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  20
    The Child and the Hero: Coming of Age in Catullus and Vergil (review).Christine G. Perkell - 1999 - American Journal of Philology 120 (3):464-468.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Reviewed by:The Child and the Hero: Coming of Age in Catullus and VergilChristine PerkellMark Petrini. The Child and the Hero: Coming of Age in Catullus and Vergil. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1997. 152 pp. Cloth, $37.50.This brief study of youthful figures in the Aeneid proposes that Vergil represents the “coming of age” or initiation into adulthood as the devastating collision of the innocent child with the treacherous, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  22
    Attorney ‘mal-practices’: an invisible ethical problem in the early American republic.Sarah Winsberg - 2016 - Legal Ethics 19 (2):187-206.
    Lawyers and judges in the early American republic were surprisingly reluctant to penalise colleagues for malpractice and misconduct towards clients. Though they were part of a legal culture obsessed with preserving lawyers’ moral rectitude, they nonetheless remained sceptical of attempts to address malpractice. This article explores that apparent contradiction. I analyse allegedly wronged clients’ unsuccessful attempts to seek legal satisfaction, whether in civil, criminal, or professional suspension proceedings. I find that the period’s public-spirited legal ethics was in fact a major (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. Grande Sertão: Veredas by João Guimarães Rosa.Felipe W. Martinez, Nancy Fumero & Ben Segal - 2013 - Continent 3 (1):27-43.
    INTRODUCTION BY NANCY FUMERO What is a translation that stalls comprehension? That, when read, parsed, obfuscates comprehension through any language – English, Portuguese. It is inevitable that readers expect fidelity from translations. That language mirror with a sort of precision that enables the reader to become of another location, condition, to grasp in English in a similar vein as readers of Portuguese might from João Guimarães Rosa’s GRANDE SERTÃO: VEREDAS. There is the expectation that translations enable mobility. That what was (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  54
    Desire and Monstrosity in the Disaster Film: Alfred Hitchcock's The Birds.David Humbert - 2010 - Contagion: Journal of Violence, Mimesis, and Culture 17:87-103.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Desire and Monstrosity in the Disaster Film:Alfred Hitchcock's The BirdsDavid Humbert (bio)The theme of the relationship between desire and violence appears regularly in modern film criticism, and studies of this issue range in theoretical orientation from the Lacanian to the feminist.1 Though René Girard's view of this relationship is also regularly mentioned in studies of film violence, it is often with less than full appreciation of the way in (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  90
    Some Varieties of Relativism.Keith E. Yandell - 1986 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 19 (1/2):61 - 85.
    There is another sort of ‘defense’ of relativism that I mention in conclusion. Sometimes one finds the view that one is rightly punished for a crime only if they admit committing it, and that it was a crime — something wrongly done: ‘punishment conditional on confession’ is the rule proposed. It might seem that this would give impunity to a criminal hardy enough to deny the fact, or the evil, of her deed; so it would, unless it was also understood (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Meaning of work in western culture.Dh Wrong - 1971 - Humanitas 7 (2):215-226.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24. (respect principle) does this: We are to treat those individuals who have inherent value in ways that respect their inherent value.... The principle does not apply only to how we are to treat some individuals having inherent value (eg, those with).Trapping Are Wrong - forthcoming - Environmental Ethics: Divergence and Convergence.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. Alguien, en efecto, ha debido malinterpretar algo: El desafío de Fodor y Piattelli-Palmarini al darwinismo.Got Wrong - 2011 - Ludus Vitalis 19 (35).
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  50
    Reflections on the death of socialism: Changing perceptions of the state/society line. [REVIEW]Dennis H. Wrong - 2000 - Theory and Society 29 (2):175-185.
  27. Filling in.Why Dennett is Wrong, Patricia Smith Churchland & Vilayanur S. Ramachandran - 1994 - In Antti Revonsuo & Matti Kamppinen, Consciousness in Philosophy and Cognitive Neuroscience. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  28. Human nature and the perspective of sociology.Dennis H. Wrong - forthcoming - Social Research: An International Quarterly.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  29.  17
    Disaggregating the Idea of Capitalism.Dennis Wrong - 1992 - Theory, Culture and Society 9 (1):147-158.
  30.  37
    Jenny ReaRdon 18. The Human Genome Diversity Project.What Went Wrong - 2011 - In Sandra Harding, The postcolonial science and technology studies reader. Durham: Duke University Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  26
    Not a “Reality” Show.T. Wrong & E. Baumgart - 2013 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 24 (1):58-63.
    The authors of the preceding articles1 raise legitimate questions about patient and staff rights and the unintended consequences of allowing ABC News to film inside teaching hospitals. We explain why we regard their fears as baseless and not supported by what we heard from individuals portrayed in the filming, our decade-long experience making medical documentaries, and the full un-aired context of the scenes shown in the broadcast. The authors don’t and can’t know what conversations we had, what documents we reviewed, (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. The Concept of Alienation Revisited in Philosophy, History and Social Action. Essays in Honor of Lewis Feuer.Dh Wrong - 1988 - Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 107:461-473.
  33. Cultural relativism as ideology.Dennis H. Wrong - 1997 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 11 (2):291-300.
    Abstract The concept of culture was originally an expression of German nationalism, which reacted to the French Enlightenment by asserting the uniqueness and incomparability of all cultures as historical creations. This understanding of cultural diversity, which prevailed in American anthropology, is widely understood to imply the moral equality of all cultures. Yet its relativism originally applied to different individuals socialized in the values of their culture, rather than to different cultures. The debate over multiculturalism, which presupposes cultural relativism, ignores this (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  39
    A note on Marx and Weber in Gouldner's thought.DennisH Wrong - 1982 - Theory and Society 11 (6):899-905.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  9
    The modern condition: essays at century's end.Dennis Hume Wrong - 1998 - Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.
    In this collection, a leading sociologist brings his distinctive method of social criticism to bear on some of the most significant ideas, political and social events, and thinkers of the late twentieth century. In the first section, the author examines several concepts that have figured prominently in recent political-ideological controversies: capitalism, rationality, totalitarianism, power, alienation, left and right, and cultural relativism/ multiculturalism. He considers their origins, historical shifts in their meaning and the myths surrounding them, and their resonance beyond their (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  24
    Is capitalism eternal?Dennis H. Wrong - 2004 - Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 16 (1):23-32.
    Abstract Several scholars have observed that in contrast to ?socialism,? ?capitalism? was not an ideology promoted by a social class or movement but an economy that emerged ?spontaneously? from particular historical conditions. Since the decline of the Soviet Union, no new version of socialism has been promulgated, although complaints about the inequalities of capitalism inevitably persist and will certainly continue. Capitalism, if not ?eternal,? remains a highly probable form of economy under conditions of economic surplus, extensive division of labor, urbanism, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Class Fertility Differentials Before 1850.Dennis H. Wrong - forthcoming - Social Research: An International Quarterly.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Index to Volume Fifty-Six.Wim De Reu & Right Words Seem Wrong - 2006 - Philosophy East and West 56 (4):709-714.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Index to Volume Fifty-SixArticlesBernier, Bernard, National Communion: Watsuji Tetsurō's Conception of Ethics, Power, and the Japanese Imperial State, 1 : 84-105Between Principle and Situation: Contrasting Styles in the Japanese and Korean Traditions of Moral Culture, Chai-sik Chung, 2 : 253-280Buxton, Nicholas, The Crow and the Coconut: Accident, Coincidence, and Causation in the Yogavāiṣṭha, 3 : 392-408Chan, Sin Yee, The Confucian Notion of Jing (Respect), Sin Yee Chan, 2 : (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Remedies'.P. Birks & Wrongs Rights - 2000 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 1.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40. 15 Backward and Forward with Tort Law.John Gardner & Torts as Wrongs - 2005 - In Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O'Rourke & David Shier, Law and social justice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. pp. 255.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Suspension as a mood.Benoit Guilielmo & Artūrs Logins - forthcoming - Philosophical Psychology.
    Suspension of judgment is a ubiquitous phenomenon in our lives. It is also relevant for several debates in contemporary epistemology (e.g., evidentialism/pragmatism; peer-disagreement/higher-order evidence; inquiry). The goal of this paper is to arrive at a better understanding of what suspension of judgment is. We first question the popular assumption that we call the Triad view according to which there are three and only three (paradigmatic) doxastic attitudes, namely, belief, disbelief, and suspension of judgment. We elaborate a cumulative argument regarding crucial (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. A Tale of Two Doctrines: Moral Encroachment and Doxastic Wronging.Rima Basu - 2021 - In Jennifer Lackey, Applied Epistemology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. pp. 99-118.
    In this paper, I argue that morality might bear on belief in at least two conceptually distinct ways. The first is that morality might bear on belief by bearing on questions of justification. The claim that it does is the doctrine of moral encroachment. The second, is that morality might bear on belief given the central role belief plays in mediating and thereby constituting our relationships with one another. The claim that it does is the doctrine of doxastic wronging. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  43. Suspension of Judgment, Rationality's Competition, and the Reach of the Epistemic.Errol Lord - 2020 - In Sebastian Schmidt & Gerhard Ernst, The Ethics of Belief and Beyond: Understanding Mental Normativity. Abingdon, UK: Routledge. pp. 126-145.
    Errol Lord explores the boundaries of epistemic normativity. He argues that we can understand these better by thinking about which mental states are competitors in rationality’s competition. He argues that belief, disbelief, and two kinds of suspension of judgment are competitors. Lord shows that there are non-evidential reasons for suspension of judgment. One upshot is an independent motivation for a certain sort of pragmatist view of epistemic rationality.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  44. Belief, blame, and inquiry: a defense of doxastic wronging.Z. Quanbeck - 2023 - Philosophical Studies 180 (10-11):2955-2975.
    According to the thesis of doxastic wronging, our beliefs can non-derivatively wrong others. A recent criticism of this view claims that proponents of the doxastic wronging thesis have no principled grounds for denying that credences can likewise non-derivatively wrong, so they must countenance pervasive conflicts between morality and epistemic rationality. This paper defends the thesis of doxastic wronging from this objection by arguing that belief bears distinctive relationships to inquiry and blame that can explain why beliefs, but (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45. Suspension of Judgement: Fittingness, Reasons, and Permissivism.Michael Vollmer - 2023 - Episteme:1-16.
    This paper defends three theses on the normativity of the suspension of judgment. First, even if beliefs have to fit the truth and disbelief the false, suspension can still have satisfiable fittingness conditions. Second, combining this view with specific theses on the link between fittingness and normative reasons in favour of attitudes commits one to the existence of reasons to suspend judgement, which are neither reasons to believe nor reasons to disbelieve. These independent reasons, in turn, generate a form of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  46. Teleological Suspensions In Fear and Trembling.Kris McDaniel - 2018 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 100 (2):425-451.
    I focus here on the teleological suspension of the ethical as it appears in Fear and Trembling. A common reading of Fear and Trembling is that it explores whether there are religious reasons for action that settle that one must do an action even when all the moral reasons for action tell against doing it. This interpretation has been contested. But I defend it by showing how the explicit teleological suspension of the ethical mirrors implicit teleological suspensions of the epistemological (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  47. Risking and Wronging.Rahul Kumar - 2015 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 43 (1):27-51.
  48. Suspension, Equipollence, and Inquiry: A Reply to Wieland.Diego E. Machuca - 2015 - Analytic Philosophy 56 (2):177-187.
    It is generally thought that suspension of judgment about a proposition p is the doxastic attitude one is rationally compelled to adopt whenever the epistemic reasons for and against p are equipollent or equally credible, that is, whenever the total body of available evidence bearing on p epistemically justifies neither belief nor disbelief in p. However, in a recent contribution to this journal, Jan Wieland proposes “to broaden the conditions for suspension, and argue that it is rational to suspend belief (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49. The Epistemic Insignificance of Doxastic Wronging.DiDomenico David - forthcoming - Southwest Philosophy Review.
    Doxastic wronging is wronging that occurs in virtue of a belief. What epistemic significance, if any, does doxastic wronging have for the normativity of inquiry? Recently, some philosophers have defended views according to which doxastic wronging has an epistemic impact on the norms governing belief formation and revision. In this paper, I sketch a theory of the zetetic significance of doxastic wronging that denies its epistemic significance. In other words, although doxastic wronging is relevant (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Rights, Harming and Wronging: A Restatement of the Interest Theory.Visa A. J. Kurki - 2018 - Oxford Journal of Legal Studies (3):430-450.
    This article introduces a new formulation of the interest theory of rights. The focus is on ‘Bentham’s test’, which was devised by Matthew Kramer to limit the expansiveness of the interest theory. According to the test, a party holds a right correlative to a duty only if that party stands to undergo a development that is typically detrimental if the duty is breached. The article shows how the entire interest theory can be reformulated in terms of the test. The article (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
1 — 50 / 953