Results for 'childrens' best interests'

959 found
Order:
  1.  53
    Children, best interests and the courts: a response to Bridgeman.Barry Lyons - 2010 - Clinical Ethics 5 (4):188-194.
    In the context of critically ill children, Baines contended that the best interests test was neither objective nor coherent, and thus of little applicability in making end-of-life decisions. In reply, Bridgeman attempted to refute these claims through legal analysis and contended that the doctrine allowed for responsive, fact-specific, context-sensitive and prudential reasoning. This paper is a response to Bridgeman, and argues that an examination of case law reveals the subjective and value-laden nature of the test. Courts must make (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  2. The Best Interest of Children and the Basis of Family Policy: The Issue of Reproductive Caring Units.Christian Munthe & Thomas Hartvigsson - 2012 - In Daniela Cutas & Sarah Chan (eds.), Families – Beyond the Nuclear Ideal. Bloomsbury Academic.
    The notion of the best interest of children figures prominently in family and reproductive policy discussions and there is a considerable body of empirical research attempting to connect the interests of children to how families and society interact. Most of this research regards the effects of societal responses to perceived problems in families, thus underlying policy on interventions such as adoption, foster care and temporary assumption of custodianship, but also support structures that help families cope with various challenges. (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  3.  6
    Judging children's best interests: Centring bodily integrity.Marie Fox & Michael Thomson - 2024 - Clinical Ethics 19 (4):341-348.
    This article addresses how bodily integrity has been mobilised in the context of genital cutting of male infants and the extent to which the concept is taken into account in legal decision-making in the United Kingdom. While bioethicists have debated whether interventions on children's bodies are more appropriately determined on the basis of hypothetical consent or in the child's best interest, it is clear that in law the relevant test is whether interventions are in the child's best interest. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  4.  55
    The best interest standard and children: clarifying a concept and responding to its critics.Johan Christiaan Bester - 2019 - Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (2):117-124.
    This work clarifies the role of the best interest standard (BIS) as ethical principle in the medical care of children. It relates the BIS to the ethical framework of medical practice. The BIS is shown to be a general principle in medical ethics, providing grounding to prima facie obligations. The foundational BIS of Kopelman and Buchanan and Brock are reviewed and shown to be in agreement with the BIS here defended. Critics describe the BIS as being too demanding, narrow, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  5. Who is ‘the child’? Best interests and individuality of children in discretionary decision-making.Jenny Krutzinna - manuscript
    While the substantiation of “best interests” has received much attention, the question of how “the child” is conceptualised to ensure any action taken or decision made is in the particular child’s best interests has been largely neglected. In this paper, I argue that the lack of robust understanding of who “the child” is means that we continue to make many generalisations and category-based assumptions in determining the child’s best interests. In addressing the challenge of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  6.  65
    The best interests of the child and the return of results in genetic research: international comparative perspectives.Ma’N. H. Zawati, David Parry & Bartha Maria Knoppers - 2014 - BMC Medical Ethics 15 (1):72.
    Paediatric genomic research raises particularly challenging questions on whether and under what circumstances to return research results. In the paediatric context, decision-making is guided by the best interests of the child framework, as enshrined in the 1989 international Convention on the Rights of the Child. According to this Convention, rights and responsibilities are shared between children, parents, researchers, and the state. These "relational" obligations are further complicated in the context of genetic research.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  7.  99
    The Harm Principle Cannot Replace the Best Interest Standard: Problems With Using the Harm Principle for Medical Decision Making for Children.Johan Christiaan Bester - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (8):9-19.
    For many years the prevailing paradigm for medical decision making for children has been the best interest standard. Recently, some authors have proposed that Mill’s “harm principle” should be used to mediate or to replace the best interest standard. This article critically examines the harm principle movement and identifies serious defects within the project of using Mill’s harm principle for medical decision making for children. While the harm principle proponents successfully highlight some difficulties in present-day use of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  8.  68
    Using the best interests standard to decide whether to test children for untreatable, late-onset genetic diseases.Loretta M. Kopelman - 2007 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 32 (4):375 – 394.
    A new analysis of the Best Interests Standard is given and applied to the controversy about testing children for untreatable, severe late-onset genetic diseases, such as Huntington's disease or Alzheimer's disease. A professional consensus recommends against such predictive testing, because it is not in children's best interest. Critics disagree. The Best Interests Standard can be a powerful way to resolve such disputes. This paper begins by analyzing its meaning into three necessary and jointly sufficient conditions (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  9. In Their Best Interest?: The Case Against Equal Rights for Children.Laura Martha Purdy - 1992 - Cornell University Press.
    Proponents of children's liberation (CL) argue that there are no morally relevant differences between children and adults. Consequently, special protective laws that limit children's freedom are unjustified, and should be abolished. Protectionists reject the premise of this argument, and hence also the conclusion. Proponents of CL mostly fix upon the capacity for instrumental reasoning as the criterion that should separate autonomous from non-autonomous individuals. I argue that most children are substantially worse at instrumental reasoning than most adults, and although drawing (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  10.  83
    Revisiting the Best Interest Standard: Uses and Misuses.Douglas S. Diekema - 2011 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 22 (2):128-133.
    The best interest standard is the threshold most frequently employed by physicians and ethics consultants in challenging a parent’s refusal to provide consent for a child’s medical care. In this article, I will argue that the best interest standard has evolved to serve two different functions, and that these functions differ sufficiently that they require separate standards. While the best interest standard is appropriate for choosing among alternative treatment options for children, making recommendations to parents, and making (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  11.  8
    How ‘Ought’ the Best Interests of Children be Considered in Medical Decision-making?Zoe Ritchie, Micaela Forte, Maxwell Smith & Jacob Shelley - 2024 - Canadian Journal of Bioethics / Revue canadienne de bioéthique 7 (2-3):222-224.
    Ce résumé rend compte de la conception et du déroulement d’un atelier collaboratif basé sur des cas concrets et d’un panel sur la manière dont nous « devrions » prendre en compte le meilleur intérêt des enfants dans la prise de décision médicale, présenté virtuellement lors de l’atelier et du forum communautaire de la Société canadienne de bioéthique - Canadian Bioethics Society, en mai 2023.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  12.  60
    Using the best-interests standard in treatment decisions for young children.Loretta M. Kopelman - forthcoming - Pediatric Bioethics.
  13.  69
    The theorisation of ‘best interests’ in bioethical accounts of decision-making.Giles Birchley - 2021 - BMC Medical Ethics 22 (1):1-18.
    Background Best interests is a ubiquitous principle in medical policy and practice, informing the treatment of both children and adults. Yet theory underlying the concept of best interests is unclear and rarely articulated. This paper examines bioethical literature for theoretical accounts of best interests to gain a better sense of the meanings and underlying philosophy that structure understandings. Methods A scoping review of was undertaken. Following a literature search, 57 sources were selected and analysed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  14.  87
    Deciding Together? Best Interests and Shared Decision-Making in Paediatric Intensive Care.Giles Birchley - 2014 - Health Care Analysis 22 (3):203-222.
    In the western healthcare, shared decision making has become the orthodox approach to making healthcare choices as a way of promoting patient autonomy. Despite the fact that the autonomy paradigm is poorly suited to paediatric decision making, such an approach is enshrined in English common law. When reaching moral decisions, for instance when it is unclear whether treatment or non-treatment will serve a child’s best interests, shared decision making is particularly questionable because agreement does not ensure moral validity. (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  15.  19
    The Best Interest Standard Is the Best We Have: Why the Harm Principle and Constrained Parental Autonomy Cannot Replace the Best Interest Standard in Pediatric Ethics.Johan C. Bester - 2019 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 30 (3):223-231.
    While the best interest standard (BIS) enjoys wide endorsement as the ethical and decision-making standard in pediatrics, it has been criticized as vague and indeterminate. Alternate decision-making standards have been proposed to replace or augment the BIS, notably the harm principle (HP) and constrained parental autonomy (CPA) model. In this edition of The Journal of Clinical Ethics, Lainie Friedman Ross argues that CPA is a better standard than the BIS or the HP as both guide and limiter in pediatrics. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  16. The Best-Interests Standard as Threshold, Ideal, and Standard of Reasonableness.L. M. Kopelman - 1997 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 22 (3):271-289.
    The best-interests standard is a widely used ethical, legal, and social basis for policy and decision-making involving children and other incompetent persons. It is under attack, however, as self-defeating, individualistic, unknowable, vague, dangerous, and open to abuse. The author defends this standard by identifying its employment, first, as a threshold for intervention and judgment (as in child abuse and neglect rulings), second, as an ideal to establish policies or prima facie duties, and, third, as a standard of reasonableness. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  17.  27
    In Their Best Interest?: The Case Against Equal Rights for Children.Michael Leahy - 1993 - Philosophical Books 34 (1):57-58.
  18.  57
    The Best Interest Standard: Both Guide and Limit to Medical Decision Making on Behalf of Incapacitated Patients.Thaddeus Mason Pope - 2011 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 22 (2):134-138.
    In this issue of JCE, Douglas Diekema argues that the best interest standard (BIS) has been misemployed to serve two materially different functions. On the one hand, clinicians and parents use the BIS to recommend and to make treatment decisions on behalf of children. On the other hand, clinicians and state authorities use the BIS to determine when the government should interfere with parental decision-making authority. Diekema concedes that the BIS is appropriately used to “guide” parents in making medical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  19.  92
    Beyond the Best Interests of Children: Four Views of the Family and of Foundational Disagreements Regarding Pediatric Decision Making.H. T. Engelhardt - 2010 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 35 (5):499-517.
    This paper presents four different understandings of the family and their concomitant views of the authority of the family in pediatric medical decision making. These different views are grounded in robustly developed, and conflicting, worldviews supported by disparate basic premises about the nature of morality. The traditional worldviews are often found within religious communities that embrace foundational metaphysical premises at odds with the commitments of the liberal account of the family dominant in the secular culture of the West. These disputes (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  20.  22
    Evolving capacity of children and their best interests in the context of health research in South Africa: An ethico‐legal position.Melodie Labuschaigne, Safia Mahomed & Ames Dhai - 2023 - Developing World Bioethics 23 (4):358-366.
    The existing ethico-legal regulation of adolescent children's participation in health research in South Africa is currently unclear. The article interrogates the existing framework governing children's consent to research participation, with specific emphasis on discrepancies in consent norms in law and ethical guidelines. Against the backdrop of the constitutional directive that requires that a child's best interests are of paramount importance in every matter concerning the child, the article assesses whether sufficient consideration is given to children's evolving maturity and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  33
    Children and health-care research: best treatment, best interests and best practice.Hazel Biggs - 2011 - Clinical Ethics 6 (1):15-19.
    In order for children to receive the best possible medical treatment, it is essential that research is conducted to discover safe and effective interventions and dosages. This article focuses on the legal and ethical implications of recruiting into health-care research minors who are not competent to consent. It considers the role played by best interests in obtaining valid parental consent for the participation of children in research, both at common law and under the Regulations that govern clinical (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22.  44
    Best Interests in the MCA 2005—What can Healthcare Law Learn from Family Law?Shazia Choudhry - 2008 - Health Care Analysis 16 (3):240-251.
    The ‘best interests’ standard is a highly seductive standard in English law. Not only does it appear to be fairly uncontroversial but it also presents as the most sensible, objective and ‘fair’ method of dealing with decision making on behalf of those who are perceived to be the most vulnerable within society. This article aims to provide a critical appraisal of how the standard has been applied within family law, to outline how the standard is to be applied (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  51
    Too Close to the Knives: Children's Rights, Parental Authority, and Best Interests in the Context of Elective Pediatric Surgeries.Maggie Taylor - 2018 - Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 28 (3):281-308.
    This paper advances a novel conception of the child’s best interest in regard to pediatric surgeries that do not promote the preventive or therapeutic health needs of children, or elective pediatric surgeries (EPS). First, children’s capacity for decision-making is examined, and the best decision-making model for EPS is identified as the Best Interest Standard. What follows is a discussion of the interests of children in the context of EPS, the correlation of fundamental interests to rights, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  24.  40
    Health Care Decisionmaking by Children Is It in Their Best Interest?Lainie Friedman Ross - 1997 - Hastings Center Report 27 (6):41-46.
    The argument for children's rights in health care has been long in the making. The success of this position is reflected in the 1995 American Academy of Pediatrics recommendations for the role of children in health care decisionmaking, which suggest that children be given greater voice as they mature. But there are good moral and practical reasons for exercising caution in these health care situations, especially when the child and parents disagree. Parents need the moral and legal space within which (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  25. Surrogate Motherhood and the Best Interests of Children.Angela R. Holder - 1988 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 16 (1-2):51-56.
  26.  43
    Is ‘best interests’ the right standard in cases like that of Charlie Gard?Robert D. Truog - 2020 - Journal of Medical Ethics 46 (1):16-17.
    Savulescu and colleagues have provided interesting insights into how the UK public view the ‘best interests’ of children like Charlie Gard. But is best interests the right standard for evaluating these types of cases? In the USA, both clinical decisions and legal judgments tend to follow the ‘harm principle’, which holds that parental choices for their children should prevail unless their decisions subject the child to avoidable harm. The case of Charlie Gard, and others like it, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  27.  12
    Medical Decision Making for Medically Complex Children in Foster Care: Who Knows the Child’s Best Interests?Renee D. Boss, Rachel A. B. Dodge & Rebecca R. Seltzer - 2018 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 29 (2):139-144.
    Approximately one in 10 children in foster care are medically complex and require intensive medical supervision, frequent hospitalization, and difficult medical decision making. Some of these children are in foster care because their parents cannot care for their medical needs; other parents are responsible for their child’s medical needs due to abuse or neglect. In either case, there can be uncertainty about the role that a child’s biological parents should play in making serious medical decisions. Here we highlight some of (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  40
    The determination of the best interests in relation to childhood immunisation.Angus Dawson - 2005 - Bioethics 19 (1):72-89.
    ABSTRACTThere are many different ethical arguments that might be advanced for and against childhood vaccinations. In this paper I explore one particular argument that focuses on the idea that such vaccinations are justifiable because they are held to be in the best interests of a particular child. Two issues arise from this idea. The first issue is how best interests are to be determined in this case. The second issue is what follows from this to justify (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  29.  44
    Is respecting children's rationality in their best interest in an authoritarian context?Parvaneh Ghazinejad & Claudia Ruitenberg - 2014 - Ethics and Education 9 (3):317-328.
    Based on the experiences of one of the authors teaching philosophy for children in Iran, the paper asks whether respecting children's rationality, in the form of cultivating their ability and disposition to think critically, is in their best interest in an authoritarian context such as Iran. It argues that, in authoritarian contexts, respect for children's capacity for rational thought must be balanced with responsibility for their safety in their community. In other words, children's ‘best interest’ must consider children (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  30.  17
    The child's best interest in gamete donation.Femke Takes - 2021 - Bioethics 36 (1):10-17.
    Procreation with donor gametes is widespread and commonly accepted, but it involves ethical questions about the child's best interest. Understanding the historical structures of the moral discussion of gamete donation may contribute to reflecting on the child's best interest. This is why I have analysed the debate on gamete donation in the Netherlands, and this analysis has uncovered some striking discontinuities. Notions of the child's best interest have undergone a radical swing. In the past, it was considered (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. The determination of 'best interests' in relation to childhood vaccinations (published in bioethics 19(1)).Angus Dawson - 2005 - Bioethics 19 (2):187-205.
    ERRATUMWe regret that, due to a technical error, the uncorrected version of Angus Dawson's article was printed in 19:1. We apologise to the author and reprint in full the corrected version of the paper on the following pages. A. Dawson et al.. Bioethics 2005; 19: 72–89. ABSTRACTThere are many different ethical arguments that might be advanced for and against childhood vaccinations. In this paper I will explore one particular argument that focuses on the idea that childhood vaccinations are justifiable because (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  32.  83
    Predictive Genetic Testing of Children and the Role of the Best Interest Standard: Currents in Contemporary Bioethics.Lainie Friedman Ross - 2013 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 41 (4):899-906.
    The genetic testing and screening of children has been fraught with controversy since Robert Guthrie developed the bacterial inhibition assay to test for phenylketonuria and advocated for rapid uptake of universal newborn screening in the early 1960s. Today with fast and affordable mass screening of the whole genome on the horizon, the debate about when and in what scenarios children should undergo genetic testing and screening has gained renewed attention. United States professional guidelines — both the American College of Medical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33. Is Transracial Adoption in the Best Interests of Ethnic Minority Children?: Questions Concerning Legal and Scientific Interpretations of a Child’s Best Interests.Shelley M. Park & Cheryl Green - 2000 - Adoption Quarterly 3 (4):5-34.
    This paper examines a variety of social scientific studies purporting to demonstrate that transracial adoption is in the best interests of children. Finding flaws in these studies and the ethical and political arguments based upon such scientific findings, we argue for adoption practices and policies that respect the racial and ethnic identities of children of color and their communities of origin.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  34. Velvet Eugenics : In the Best Interests of Our Future Children?Rosemarie Garland-Thomson - 2024 - In Neal Baer (ed.), The promise and peril of CRISPR. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  17
    In Their Best Interest? The Case Against Equal Rights For Children. [REVIEW]Randall Curren - 1996 - Thinking: The Journal of Philosophy for Children 12 (4):44-45.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36. Cloning and Harming: Children, Future Persons, and the "Best Interest" Test.M. Roberts - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics and Public Policy 13 (1):37-62.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  29
    Is Mandatory Autonomy Education in the Best Interests of Children?Melissa Moschella - 2015 - Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 89:299-310.
    In this paper I argue that liberal proponents of mandatory autonomy education tend to overlook or underestimate the potential threats that such an education poses to the overall well-being of children (including, ironically, threats to the development of genuine autonomy). They do so by paying insufficient attention to the importance of moral virtue as a constitutive element of and precondition for genuine autonomy, and by failing to recognize how the development and consolidation of moral virtue may be undermined by the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  17
    Pediatric Neuro-enhancement, Best Interest, and Autonomy: A Case of Normative Reversal.Veljko Dubljević & Eric Racine - 2019 - In Saskia K. Nagel (ed.), Shaping Children: Ethical and Social Questions That Arise When Enhancing the Young. Springer Verlag. pp. 199-212.
    The debate on “cognitive enhancement” has moved from discussions about enhancement in adults to enhancement in children and adolescents. Similar to positions expressed in the adult context, some have argued that pediatric cognitive enhancement is acceptable and even laudable. However, the implications differ between the adult and the pediatric contexts. For example, in the debate over cognitive enhancement in adults, i.e., those who have legal majority, respect for autonomy demands that personal preferences not be overridden in absence of strong arguments (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  98
    Parental Decision Making: The Best Interest Principle, Child Autonomy, and Reasonableness.Ryan Hubbard & Jake Greenblum - 2019 - HEC Forum 31 (3):233-240.
    On what basis should we judge whether a parent’s medical decision for their child is morally acceptable? In a recent article, Johan Bester attempts to answer this question by defending a version of the Best Interest Standard for parental decision making. The purpose of this paper is to identify a number of problems faced by Bester’s version of BIS and to suggest ways to redress these problems. Accordingly, we intend to advance the project of formulating a method for guiding (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  1
    Critically ill children and the law: medical decision-making and the best interests principle.Richard Hain - forthcoming - The New Bioethics:1-4.
    Books about the law can sometimes be dull and hard to follow. This one is not. It is easy to read; the writing style is accessible and the book is well organised and well structured. The author clo...
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41. Children and Bioethics: Uses and Abuses of the Best-Interests Standard.L. M. Kopelman - 1997 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 22 (3):213-217.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  42.  76
    Death and best interests: a response to the legal challenge.Paul Baines - 2010 - Clinical Ethics 5 (4):195-200.
    In an earlier paper I argued that we do not have an objective conception of best interests and that this is a particular problem because the courts describe that they use an ‘…objective approach or test. That test is the best interests of the patient’ when choosing for children. I further argued that there was no obvious way in which we could hope to develop an objective notion of best interests. As well as this, (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  43.  65
    Parenting and the Best Interests of Minors.R. S. Downie & F. Randall - 1997 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 22 (3):219-231.
    The treatment decisions of competent adults, especially treatment refusals, are generally respected. In the case of minors something turns on their age, and older minors ought increasingly to make their own decisions. On the other hand, parents decide on behalf of infants and young children. Their right to do so can best be justified in terms of the importance of preserving intimate family relationships, rather than in terms of the child's best interests, although the child's best (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  44.  44
    Family interests and medical decisions for children.Paul Baines - 2017 - Bioethics 31 (8):599-607.
    Medical decisions for children are usually justified by the claim that they are in a child's best interests. More recently, following criticisms of the best interests standard, some advocate that the family's interests should influence medical decisions for children, although what is meant by family interests is often not made clear. I argue that at least two senses of family interests may be discerned. There is a ‘weak’ sense of family interests and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  33
    Harm is all you need? Best interests and disputes about parental decision-making.Giles Birchley - 2016 - Journal of Medical Ethics 42 (2):111-115.
    A growing number of bioethics papers endorse the harm threshold when judging whether to override parental decisions. Among other claims, these papers argue that the harm threshold is easily understood by lay and professional audiences and correctly conforms to societal expectations of parents in regard to their children. English law contains a harm threshold which mediates the use of the best interests test in cases where a child may be removed from her parents. Using Diekema9s seminal paper as (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  46.  30
    DCDD and Children: A Defense of the “Best Interests” Standard.Pablo De Lora - 2015 - American Journal of Bioethics 15 (8):21-22.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  47.  46
    Testing Children for Genetic Predispositions: Is it in Their Best Interest?Diane E. Hoffmann & Eric A. Wulfsberg - 1995 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 23 (4):331-344.
    Researchers summoned a Baltimore County woman to an office at the Johns Hopkins School of Public Health last spring to tell her the bad news. They had found a genetic threat lurking in her 7-year-old son's DNA—a mutant gene that almost always triggers a rare form of colon cancer. It was the same illness that led surgeons to remove her colon in 1979. While the boy, Michael, now 8, is still perfectly healthy, without surgery he is almost certain to develop (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  48. What Really Is in a Child’s Best Interest? Toward a More Precise Picture of the Interests of Children.Janet Malek - 2009 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 20 (2):175-182.
  49.  53
    Death and best interests.Paul Baines - 2008 - Clinical Ethics 3 (4):171-175.
    I will consider how we can assess the interests of critically ill children who will survive only while aggressive medical support is continued. If aggressive medical support is withdrawn, the child will die shortly afterwards. This is important because when the courts are asked to decide treatments, the standard is that decisions should be made in the best interests of the child. My claim is that this is not a coherent way to consider how some children in (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  50.  9
    When Better Isn’t Good Enough: Commentary on Ross’s “Better than Best (Interest Standard) in Pediatric Decision Making”.Erica K. Salter - 2019 - Journal of Clinical Ethics 30 (3):213-217.
    In this commentary, the author discusses two strengths and two weaknesses of “Better than Best (Interest Standard) in Pediatric Decision-Making,” in which Lainie Friedman Ross critiques the best interest standard and proposes her own model of constrained parental autonomy (CPA) as a preferable replacement for both an intervention principle and a guidance principle in pediatric decision making. The CPA’s strengths are that it detaches from the language and concept of “best” and that it better respects the family (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 959