Results for 'predicativity, Feferman, Weyl, Poincaré, Russell, proof theory'

948 found
Order:
  1. Predicativity and Feferman.Laura Crosilla - 2017 - In Gerhard Jäger & Wilfried Sieg, Feferman on Foundations: Logic, Mathematics, Philosophy. Cham: Springer. pp. 423-447.
    Predicativity is a notable example of fruitful interaction between philosophy and mathematical logic. It originated at the beginning of the 20th century from methodological and philosophical reflections on a changing concept of set. A clarification of this notion has prompted the development of fundamental new technical instruments, from Russell's type theory to an important chapter in proof theory, which saw the decisive involvement of Kreisel, Feferman and Schütte. The technical outcomes of predica-tivity have since taken a life (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  2.  18
    Poincaré–weyl’s predicativity: Going beyond $\gamma _{0}$.Arnon Avron - 2024 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 30 (1):41-91.
    On the basis of Poincaré and Weyl’s view of predicativity as invariance, we develop an extensive framework for predicative, type-free first-order set theory in which $\Gamma _0$ and much bigger ordinals can be defined as von Neumann ordinals. This refutes the accepted view of $\Gamma _0$ as the “limit of predicativity”.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. (1 other version)Exploring predicativity.Laura Crosilla - 1995 - In Exploring Predicativity. pp. 83-108.
    Prominent constructive theories of sets as Martin-Löf type theory and Aczel and Myhill constructive set theory, feature a distinctive form of constructivity: predicativity. This may be phrased as a constructibility requirement for sets, which ought to be finitely specifiable in terms of some uncontroversial initial “objects” and simple operations over them. Predicativity emerged at the beginning of the 20th century as a fundamental component of an influential analysis of the paradoxes by Poincaré and Russell. According to this analysis (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4.  29
    A New Approach to Predicative Set Theory.Arnon Avron - 2010 - In Ralf Schindler, Ways of Proof Theory. De Gruyter. pp. 31-64.
    We suggest a new framework for the Weyl-Feferman predicativist program by constructing a formal predicative set theory P ZF which resembles ZF , and is suitable for mechanization. The basic idea is that the predicatively acceptable instances of the comprehension schema are those which determine the collections they define in an absolute way, independent of the extension of the “surrounding universe”. The language of P ZF is type-free, and it reflects real mathematical practice in making an extensive use of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  51
    On the Strength of some Semi-Constructive Theories.Solomon Feferman - 2012 - In Ulrich Berger, Hannes Diener, Peter Schuster & Monika Seisenberger, Logic, Construction, Computation. De Gruyter. pp. 201-226.
    Most axiomatizations of set theory that have been treated metamathematically have been based either entirely on classical logic or entirely on intuitionistic logic. But a natural conception of the settheoretic universe is as an indefinite (or “potential”) totality, to which intuitionistic logic is more appropriately applied, while each set is taken to be a definite (or “completed”) totality, for which classical logic is appropriate; so on that view, set theory should be axiomatized on some correspondingly mixed basis. Similarly, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  6.  79
    Classical predicative logic-enriched type theories.Robin Adams & Zhaohui Luo - 2010 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 161 (11):1315-1345.
    A logic-enriched type theory is a type theory extended with a primitive mechanism for forming and proving propositions. We construct two LTTs, named and , which we claim correspond closely to the classical predicative systems of second order arithmetic and . We justify this claim by translating each second order system into the corresponding LTT, and proving that these translations are conservative. This is part of an ongoing research project to investigate how LTTs may be used to formalise (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  7. Poincaré: Mathematics & logic & intuition.Colin Mclarty - 1997 - Philosophia Mathematica 5 (2):97-115.
    often insisted existence in mathematics means logical consistency, and formal logic is the sole guarantor of rigor. The paper joins this to his view of intuition and his own mathematics. It looks at predicativity and the infinite, Poincaré's early endorsement of the axiom of choice, and Cantor's set theory versus Zermelo's axioms. Poincaré discussed constructivism sympathetically only once, a few months before his death, and conspicuously avoided committing himself. We end with Poincaré on Couturat, Russell, and Hilbert.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  8. Russell on Spinoza’s Substance Monism.Pierfrancesco Basile - 2012 - Metaphysica 13 (1):27-41.
    Russell’s critique of substance monism is an ideal starting point from which to understand some main concepts in Spinoza’s difficult metaphysics. This paper provides an in-depth examination of Spinoza’s proof that only one substance exists. On this basis, it rejects Russell’s interpretation of Spinoza’s theory of reality as founded upon the logical doctrine that all propositions consist of a predicate and a subject. An alternative interpretation is offered: Spinoza’s substance is not a bearer of properties, as Russell implied, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9. Russell's theory of descriptions vs. the predicative analysis: A reply to Graff.Berit Brogaard - unknown
    I. Descriptions in Predicative Position The predicative analysis and Russell’s theory part company when it comes to the argument structure assigned to sentences like (1). (1) Washington is the greatest French soldier. On a standard Russellian analysis, (1) has the following (a) logical form and (b) truth conditions.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  42
    (1 other version)Well-ordering proofs for Martin-Löf type theory.Anton Setzer - 1998 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 92 (2):113-159.
    We present well-ordering proofs for Martin-Löf's type theory with W-type and one universe. These proofs, together with an embedding of the type theory in a set theoretical system as carried out in Setzer show that the proof theoretical strength of the type theory is precisely ψΩ1Ω1 + ω, which is slightly more than the strength of Feferman's theory T0, classical set theory KPI and the subsystem of analysis + . The strength of intensional and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  11.  68
    From predication to programming.Karel Lambert - 2001 - Minds and Machines 11 (2):257-265.
    A free logic is one in which a singular term can fail to refer to an existent object, for example, `Vulcan' or `5/0'. This essay demonstrates the fruitfulness of a version of this non-classical logic of terms (negative free logic) by showing (1) how it can be used not only to repair a looming inconsistency in Quine's theory of predication, the most influential semantical theory in contemporary philosophical logic, but also (2) how Beeson, Farmer and Feferman, among others, (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  17
    (1 other version)The Proof Theory of Classical and Constructive Inductive Definitions. A Forty Year Saga, 1968 – 2008.Solomon Feferman - 2010 - In Ralf Schindler, Ways of Proof Theory. De Gruyter. pp. 7-30.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  13.  86
    Does reductive proof theory have a viable rationale?Solomon Feferman - 2000 - Erkenntnis 53 (1-2):63-96.
    The goals of reduction andreductionism in the natural sciences are mainly explanatoryin character, while those inmathematics are primarily foundational.In contrast to global reductionistprograms which aim to reduce all ofmathematics to one supposedly ``universal'' system or foundational scheme, reductive proof theory pursues local reductions of one formal system to another which is more justified in some sense. In this direction, two specific rationales have been proposed as aims for reductive proof theory, the constructive consistency-proof rationale and (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  14.  57
    A correspondence between Martin-löf type theory, the ramified theory of types and pure type systems.Fairouz Kamareddine & Twan Laan - 2001 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 10 (3):375-402.
    In Russell''s Ramified Theory of Types RTT, two hierarchical concepts dominate:orders and types. The use of orders has as a consequencethat the logic part of RTT is predicative.The concept of order however, is almost deadsince Ramsey eliminated it from RTT. This is whywe find Church''s simple theory of types (which uses the type concept without the order one) at the bottom of the Barendregt Cube rather than RTT. Despite the disappearance of orders which have a strong correlation with (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  15.  8
    Ordinals and Functionals in Proof Theory.Solomon Feferman - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (4):625-626.
  16.  78
    Church's type theory.Peter Andrews - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Church’s type theory, aka simple type theory, is a formal logical language which includes classical first-order and propositional logic, but is more expressive in a practical sense. It is used, with some modifications and enhancements, in most modern applications of type theory. It is particularly well suited to the formalization of mathematics and other disciplines and to specifying and verifying hardware and software. It also plays an important role in the study of the formal semantics of natural (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  17.  26
    Conservativity of Transitive Closure over weak operational set theory.Laura Crosilla & Andrea Cantini - 2012 - In Ulrich Berger, Hannes Diener, Peter Schuster & Monika Seisenberger, Logic, Construction, Computation. De Gruyter.
    Constructive set theory a' la Myhill-Aczel has been extended in (Cantini and Crosilla 2008, Cantini and Crosilla 2010) to incorporate a notion of (partial, non--extensional) operation. Constructive operational set theory is a constructive and predicative analogue of Beeson's Inuitionistic set theory with rules and of Feferman's Operational set theory (Beeson 1988, Feferman 2006, Jaeger 2007, Jaeger 2009, Jaeger 1009b). This paper is concerned with an extension of constructive operational set theory (Cantini and Crosilla 2010) by (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  80
    In the Light of Logic.Solomon Feferman - 1998 - New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    In this collection of essays written over a period of twenty years, Solomon Feferman explains advanced results in modern logic and employs them to cast light on significant problems in the foundations of mathematics. Most troubling among these is the revolutionary way in which Georg Cantor elaborated the nature of the infinite, and in doing so helped transform the face of twentieth-century mathematics. Feferman details the development of Cantorian concepts and the foundational difficulties they engendered. He argues that the freedom (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  19.  58
    Nonclassical Truth with Classical Strength. A Proof-Theoretic Analysis of Compositional Truth Over Hype.Martin Fischer, Carlo Nicolai & Pablo Dopico - 2023 - Review of Symbolic Logic 16 (2):425-448.
    Questions concerning the proof-theoretic strength of classical versus nonclassical theories of truth have received some attention recently. A particularly convenient case study concerns classical and nonclassical axiomatizations of fixed-point semantics. It is known that nonclassical axiomatizations in four- or three-valued logics are substantially weaker than their classical counterparts. In this paper we consider the addition of a suitable conditional to First-Degree Entailment—a logic recently studied by Hannes Leitgeb under the label HYPE. We show in particular that, by formulating the (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  20.  52
    Russell, Poincaré, and Whitehead’s Relational Theory of Space.Patrick J. Hurley - 1979 - Process Studies 9 (1):14-21.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21.  27
    (1 other version)Prawitz Dag. Ideas and results in proof theory. Proceedings of the Second Scandinavian Logic Symposium, edited by Fenstad J. E., Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, vol. 63, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam and London 1971, pp. 235–307. [REVIEW]Solomon Feferman - 1975 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (2):232-234.
  22.  32
    Principia ’s Second Edition [review of Bernard Linsky, The Evolution of Principia Mathematica: Bertrand Russell’s Manuscripts and Notes for the Second Edition ]. [REVIEW]Russell Wahl - 2013 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 33 (1):59-67.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:russell: the Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies n.s. 33 (summer 2013): 59–94 The Bertrand Russell Research Centre, McMaster U. issn 0036–01631; online 1913–8032 oeviews PRINCIPIA’S SECOND EDITION Russell Wahl English and Philosophy / Idaho State U. Pocatello, id 83209, usa wahlruss@isu.edu Bernard Linsky. The Evolution of Principia Mathematica: Bertrand Russell’s Manuscripts and Notes for the Second Edition. Cambridge: Cambridge U. P., 2011. Pp. vii, 407; 2 plates. isbn: 978-1-10700-327-9. (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. Poincaré vs. Russell on the rôle of logic in mathematicst.Michael Detlefsen - 1993 - Philosophia Mathematica 1 (1):24-49.
    In the early years of this century, Poincaré and Russell engaged in a debate concerning the nature of mathematical reasoning. Siding with Kant, Poincaré argued that mathematical reasoning is characteristically non-logical in character. Russell urged the contrary view, maintaining that (i) the plausibility originally enjoyed by Kant's view was due primarily to the underdeveloped state of logic in his (i.e., Kant's) time, and that (ii) with the aid of recent developments in logic, it is possible to demonstrate its falsity. This (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  24. Predicativity, the Russell-Myhill Paradox, and Church’s Intensional Logic.Sean Walsh - 2016 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 45 (3):277-326.
    This paper sets out a predicative response to the Russell-Myhill paradox of propositions within the framework of Church’s intensional logic. A predicative response places restrictions on the full comprehension schema, which asserts that every formula determines a higher-order entity. In addition to motivating the restriction on the comprehension schema from intuitions about the stability of reference, this paper contains a consistency proof for the predicative response to the Russell-Myhill paradox. The models used to establish this consistency also model other (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  25.  59
    Four Comments on Russell's Theory of Deceptions.Avrum Stroll - 1978 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (1):147-155.
    In his article, “Stroll on Russell's ‘Proof’”, Robert Fahrnkopf takes issue with four comments I made about Russell's theory of descriptions in a paper, “Russell's ‘Proof,’” which appeared in the June 1975 issue of this Journal. Though I disagree with Fahrnkopf on the points in question, there would be no point in washing our private conceptual linen in a public place were it not for the ingenious and highly original suggestions he makes in his defense of Russell. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  26.  56
    The signi cance of Hermann Weyl's.Solomon Feferman - unknown
    In his 1918 monograph \Das Kontinuum", Hermann Weyl initiated a program for the arithmetical foundations of mathematics. In the years following, this was overshadowed by the foundational schemes of Hilbert's nitary consistency program and Brouwer's intuitionistic redevelopment of mathematics. In fact, not long after his own venture, Weyl became a convert to Brouwerian intuitionism and criticized his old teacher's program. Over the years, though, he became more and more pessimistic about the practical possibilities of reworking mathematics along intuitionistic lines, and (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  57
    Systems of explicit mathematics with non-constructive μ-operator. Part I.Solomon Feferman & Gerhard Jäger - 1993 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 65 (3):243-263.
    Feferman, S. and G. Jäger, Systems of explicit mathematics with non-constructive μ-operator. Part I, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 65 243-263. This paper is mainly concerned with the proof-theoretic analysis of systems of explicit mathematics with a non-constructive minimum operator. We start off from a basic theory BON of operators and numbers and add some principles of set and formula induction on the natural numbers as well as axioms for μ. The principal results then state: BON plus (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  28.  87
    Operational set theory and small large cardinals.Solomon Feferman with with R. L. Vaught - manuscript
    “Small” large cardinal notions in the language of ZFC are those large cardinal notions that are consistent with V = L. Besides their original formulation in classical set theory, we have a variety of analogue notions in systems of admissible set theory, admissible recursion theory, constructive set theory, constructive type theory, explicit mathematics and recursive ordinal notations (as used in proof theory). On the face of it, it is surprising that such distinctively set-theoretical (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  82
    Another look at the second incompleteness theorem.Albert Visser - 2020 - Review of Symbolic Logic 13 (2):269-295.
    In this paper we study proofs of some general forms of the Second Incompleteness Theorem. These forms conform to the Feferman format, where the proof predicate is fixed and the representation of the set of axioms varies. We extend the Feferman framework in one important point: we allow the interpretation of number theory to vary.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  30. Dead Letters.Russell Ford - 2013 - LIT: Literature Interpretation Theory 24 (4):299-317.
    This essay considers Richard Calder’s Dead trilogy as an important contribution to the argument concerning how pornography’s pernicious effects might be mitigated or disrupted. Paying close attention to the way that Calder uses the rhetoric of fiction to challenge pornographic stereotypes that have achieved hegemonic status, the essay argues that Calder’s trilogy provides an important link between debates about pornography and contemporary philosophical discussions of alterity and community. Finally, it argues that, for Calder, sexuality is implicitly predicated on a reconceptualization (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  54
    The unfolding of non-finitist arithmetic.Solomon Feferman & Thomas Strahm - 2000 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 104 (1-3):75-96.
    The unfolding of schematic formal systems is a novel concept which was initiated in Feferman , Gödel ’96, Lecture Notes in Logic, Springer, Berlin, 1996, pp. 3–22). This paper is mainly concerned with the proof-theoretic analysis of various unfolding systems for non-finitist arithmetic . In particular, we examine two restricted unfoldings and , as well as a full unfolding, . The principal results then state: is equivalent to ; is equivalent to ; is equivalent to . Thus is (...)-theoretically equivalent to predicative analysis. (shrink)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  32.  54
    (1 other version)Adorno's Dreams and the Aesthetic of Violence.Russell Perkins - 2011 - Telos: Critical Theory of the Contemporary 2011 (155):21-37.
    ExcerptI then looked more closely at the picture of the child and realized to my inexpressible horror that it was a picture of me as a child. This was proof of my guilt… . I wasted no time with denials but said at once to Agathe that only two possibilities remained: either immediate flight and concealment, or suicide. She said very firmly that only the latter came into consideration. Overcome by fear and horror, I awoke.1So ends the account of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  90
    Semantics and Proof Theory of the Epsilon Calculus.Richard Zach - 2017 - In Ghosh Sujata & Prasad Sanjiva, Logic and Its Applications. ICLA 2017. Springer. pp. 27-47.
    The epsilon operator is a term-forming operator which replaces quantifiers in ordinary predicate logic. The application of this undervalued formalism has been hampered by the absence of well-behaved proof systems on the one hand, and accessible presentations of its theory on the other. One significant early result for the original axiomatic proof system for the epsilon-calculus is the first epsilon theorem, for which a proof is sketched. The system itself is discussed, also relative to possible semantic (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  34.  48
    Stability proofs and consistency proofs: A loose analogy.Norwood Russell Hanson - 1964 - Philosophy of Science 31 (4):301-318.
    A loose analogy relates the work of Laplace and Hilbert. These thinkers had roughly similar objectives. At a time when so much of our analytic effort goes to distinguishing mathematics and logic from physical theory, such an analogy can still be instructive, even though differences will always divide endeavors such as those of Laplace and Hilbert.
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35. (1 other version)Truth, Partial Logic and Infinitary Proof Systems.Martin Fischer & Norbert Gratzl - 2017 - Studia Logica 106 (3):1-26.
    In this paper we apply proof theoretic methods used for classical systems in order to obtain upper bounds for systems in partial logic. We focus on a truth predicate interpreted in a Kripke style way via strong Kleene; whereas the aim is to connect harmoniously the partial version of Kripke–Feferman with its intended semantics. The method we apply is based on infinitary proof systems containing an ω-rule.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  36.  99
    Typical ambiguity: Trying to have your cake and eat it too.Solomon Feferman - manuscript
    Ambiguity is a property of syntactic expressions which is ubiquitous in all informal languages–natural, scientific and mathematical; the efficient use of language depends to an exceptional extent on this feature. Disambiguation is the process of separating out the possible meanings of ambiguous expressions. Ambiguity is typical if the process of disambiguation can be carried out in some systematic way. Russell made use of typical ambiguity in the theory of types in order to combine the assurance of its (apparent) consistency (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  37.  62
    Systems of explicit mathematics with non-constructive μ-operator. Part II.Solomon Feferman & Gerhard Jäger - 1996 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 79 (1):37-52.
    This paper is mainly concerned with proof-theoretic analysis of some second-order systems of explicit mathematics with a non-constructive minimum operator. By introducing axioms for variable types we extend our first-order theory BON to the elementary explicit type theory EET and add several forms of induction as well as axioms for μ. The principal results then state: EET plus set induction is proof-theoretically equivalent to Peano arithmetic PA <0).
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  38. Why a Little Bit Goes a Long Way: Logical Foundations of Scientifically Applicable Mathematics.Solomon Feferman - 1992 - PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992:442 - 455.
    Does science justify any part of mathematics and, if so, what part? These questions are related to the so-called indispensability arguments propounded, among others, by Quine and Putnam; moreover, both were led to accept significant portions of set theory on that basis. However, set theory rests on a strong form of Platonic realism which has been variously criticized as a foundation of mathematics and is at odds with scientific realism. Recent logical results show that it is possible to (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  39.  38
    New waves in philosophical logic.Greg Restall & Gillian Kay Russell (eds.) - 2012 - New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
    Machine generated contents note: -- Series Editors' PrefaceAcknowledgementsNotes on ContributorsHow Things Are Elsewhere; W. Schwarz Information Change and First-Order Dynamic Logic; B.Kooi Interpreting and Applying Proof Theories for Modal Logic; F.Poggiolesi & G.Restall The Logic(s) of Modal Knowledge; D.Cohnitz On Probabilistically Closed Languages; H.Leitgeb Dogmatism, Probability and Logical Uncertainty; B.Weatherson & D.Jehle Skepticism about Reasoning; S.Roush, K.Allen & I.HerbertLessons in Philosophy of Logic from Medieval Obligations; C.D.Novaes How to Rule Out Things with Words: Strong Paraconsistency and the Algebra of (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40. Unfolding finitist arithmetic.Solomon Feferman & Thomas Strahm - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (4):665-689.
    The concept of the (full) unfolding of a schematic system is used to answer the following question: Which operations and predicates, and which principles concerning them, ought to be accepted if one has accepted ? The program to determine for various systems of foundational significance was previously carried out for a system of nonfinitist arithmetic, ; it was shown that is proof-theoretically equivalent to predicative analysis. In the present paper we work out the unfolding notions for a basic schematic (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  41. Proof theory in the USSR 1925–1969.Grigori Mints - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (2):385-424.
    We present a survey of proof theory in the USSR beginning with the paper by Kolmogorov [1925] and ending (mostly) in 1969; the last two sections deal with work done by A. A. Markov and N. A. Shanin in the early seventies, providing a kind of effective interpretation of negative arithmetic formulas. The material is arranged in chronological order and subdivided according to topics of investigation. The exposition is more detailed when the work is little known in the (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  42. Toward a topic-specific logicism? Russell's theory of geometry in the principles of mathematics.Sébastien Gandon - 2009 - Philosophia Mathematica 17 (1):35-72.
    Russell's philosophy is rightly described as a programme of reduction of mathematics to logic. Now the theory of geometry developed in 1903 does not fit this picture well, since it is deeply rooted in the purely synthetic projective approach, which conflicts with all the endeavours to reduce geometry to analytical geometry. The first goal of this paper is to present an overview of this conception. The second aim is more far-reaching. The fact that such a theory of geometry (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  43.  8
    A Neglected Interpretation of Das Kontinuum.Michele Contente Czech Academy of Sciences, Prague & Czech Republic - forthcoming - History and Philosophy of Logic:1-25.
    Hermann's Weyl Das Kontinuum has inspired several studies in logic and foundations of mathematics over the last century. The book provides a remarkable reconstruction of a large portion of classical mathematics on a predicative basis. However, diverging interpretations of the predicative system formulated by Weyl have been proposed in the literature. In the present work, I analyze an early formalization of Weyl's ideas proposed by [Casari, E. 1964. Questioni di Filosofia Della Matematica, Milano: Feltrinelli] and compare it with other, more (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  22
    A Neglected Interpretation of Das Kontinuum.Michele Contente - forthcoming - History and Philosophy of Logic:1-25.
    Hermann's Weyl Das Kontinuum has inspired several studies in logic and foundations of mathematics over the last century. The book provides a remarkable reconstruction of a large portion of classical mathematics on a predicative basis. However, diverging interpretations of the predicative system formulated by Weyl have been proposed in the literature. In the present work, I analyze an early formalization of Weyl's ideas proposed by [Casari, E. 1964. Questioni di Filosofia Della Matematica, Milano: Feltrinelli] and compare it with other, more (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  66
    Hilbert's program modi ed.Solomon Feferman - unknown
    The background to the development of proof theory since 1960 is contained in the article (MATHEMATICS, FOUNDATIONS OF), Vol. 5, pp. 208- 209. Brie y, Hilbert's program (H.P.), inaugurated in the 1920s, aimed to secure the foundations of mathematics by giving nitary consistency proofs of formal systems such as for number theory, analysis and set theory, in which informal mathematics can be represented directly. These systems are based on classical logic and implicitly or explicitly depend on (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46. Harmonious logic: Craig’s interpolation theorem and its descendants.Solomon Feferman - 2008 - Synthese 164 (3):341-357.
    Though deceptively simple and plausible on the face of it, Craig's interpolation theorem has proved to be a central logical property that has been used to reveal a deep harmony between the syntax and semantics of first order logic. Craig's theorem was generalized soon after by Lyndon, with application to the characterization of first order properties preserved under homomorphism. After retracing the early history, this article is mainly devoted to a survey of subsequent generalizations and applications, especially of many-sorted interpolation (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  47.  53
    Gaisi Takeuti. Proof theory. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, vol. 81. North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam and Oxford, and American Elsevier Publishing Company, New York, 1975, vii + 372 pp. - Gaisi Takeuti. Proof theory. Second edition of the preceding. Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics, vol. 81. North-Holland, Amsterdam etc. 1987, x + 490 pp. - Georg Kreisel. Proof theory: some personal recollections. Therein, pp. 395–405. - Wolfram Pohlers. Contributions of the Schütte school in Munich to proof theory. Therein, pp. 406–431. - Stephen G. Simpson. Subsystems of Z2 and reverse mathematics. Therein, pp. 432–446. - Soloman Feferman. Proof theory: a personal report. Therein, pp. 447–485. [REVIEW]Dag Prawitz - 1991 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (3):1094.
  48. A Cantorian argument against Frege's and early Russell's theories of descriptions.Kevin C. Klement - 2008 - In Nicholas Griffin & Dale Jacquette, Russell Vs. Meinong: The Legacy of "on Denoting". London and New York: Routledge. pp. 65-77.
    It would be an understatement to say that Russell was interested in Cantorian diagonal paradoxes. His discovery of the various versions of Russell’s paradox—the classes version, the predicates version, the propositional functions version—had a lasting effect on his views in philosophical logic. Similar Cantorian paradoxes regarding propositions—such as that discussed in §500 of The Principles of Mathematics—were surely among the reasons Russell eventually abandoned his ontology of propositions.1 However, Russell’s reasons for abandoning what he called “denoting concepts”, and his rejection (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  49.  68
    For philosophy of mathematics: 5 questions.Solomon Feferman - 2007 - In V. F. Hendricks & Hannes Leitgeb, Philosophy of Mathematics: Five Questions. Automatic Press/VIP.
    When I was a teenager growing up in Los Angeles in the early 1940s, my dream was to become a mathematical physicist: I was fascinated by the ideas of relativity theory and quantum mechanics, and I read popular expositions which, in those days, besides Einstein’s The Meaning of Relativity, was limited to books by the likes of Arthur S. Eddington and James Jeans. I breezed through the high-school mathematics courses (calculus was not then on offer, and my teachers barely (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50. Review: Warren Goldfarb’s Deductive Logic. [REVIEW]Gillian Russell - 2005 - Australasian Journal of Logic 3:63-66.
    Deductive Logic is an introductory textbook in formal logic. The book is divided into four parts covering (i) truth-functional logic, (ii) monadic quantifi- cation, (iii) polyadic quantification and (iv) names and identity, and there are exercises for all these topics at the end of the book. In the truth-functional logic part, the reader learns to produce paraphrases of English statements and arguments in logical notation (this subsection is called “analysis”), then about the semantic properties of such paraphrased statements and arguments, (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 948