Results for 'propositions, '

949 found
Order:
See also
  1. An algorithm for axiomatizing and theorem proving in finite many-valued propositional logics* Walter A. Carnielli.Proving in Finite Many-Valued Propositional - forthcoming - Logique Et Analyse.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  12
    Lester Embree.Human Scientific Propositions - 1992 - In D. P. Chattopadhyaya, Lester Embree & Jitendranath Mohanty (eds.), Phenomenology and Indian Philosophy. New Delhi: State University of New York Press.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  12
    Paolo Crivelli.I. Propositions - 2012 - In Christopher Shields (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle. Oxford University Press USA. pp. 113.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. Peter Caws.Propositions True - 2003 - In Heather Dyke (ed.), Time and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 99.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  5.  22
    The Norms of Reason, RICHARD W. MILLER.Are Some Propositions Empirically Necessary - 1995 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (2):183-184.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  6.  14
    Philosophical abstracts.Tensed Propositions as Predicates - 1969 - American Philosophical Quarterly 6 (4).
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7. General Propositions and Causality.Frank Plumpton Ramsey - 1925 - In The Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays. London, England: Routledge & Kegan Paul. pp. 237-255.
    This article rebuts Ramsey's earlier theory, in 'Universals of Law and of Fact', of how laws of nature differ from other true generalisations. It argues that our laws are rules we use in judging 'if I meet an F I shall regard it as a G'. This temporal asymmetry is derived from that of cause and effect and used to distinguish what's past as what we can know about without knowing our present intentions.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   245 citations  
  8. (1 other version)Impossible worlds and propositions: Against the parity thesis.Francesco Berto - 2010 - Philosophical Quarterly 60 (240):471-486.
    Accounts of propositions as sets of possible worlds have been criticized for conflating distinct impossible propositions. In response to this problem, some have proposed to introduce impossible worlds to represent distinct impossibilities, endorsing the thesis that impossible worlds must be of the same kind; this has been called the parity thesis. I show that this thesis faces problems, and propose a hybrid account which rejects it: possible worlds are taken as concrete Lewisian worlds, and impossibilities are represented as set-theoretic constructions (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  9. Empty names and `gappy' propositions.Anthony Everett - 2003 - Philosophical Studies 116 (1):1-36.
    In recent years a number of authors sympathetic to Referentialistaccounts of proper names have argued that utterances containingempty names express `gappy,' or incomplete, propositions. In this paper I want to take issue with this suggestion.In particular, I argue versions of this approach developedby David Braun, Nathan Salmon, Ken Taylor, and by Fred Adams,Gary Fuller, and Robert Stecker.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  10. Thisnesses, Propositions, and Truth.David Ingram - 2018 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 99 (3):442-463.
    Presentists, who believe that only present objects exist, should accept a thisness ontology, since it can do considerable work in defence of presentism. In this paper, I propose a version of presentism that involves thisnesses of past and present entities and I argue this view solves important problems facing standard versions of presentism.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  11.  63
    If structured propositions are logical procedures then how are procedures individuated?Marie Duží - 2019 - Synthese 196 (4):1249-1283.
    This paper deals with two issues. First, it identifies structured propositions with logical procedures. Second, it considers various rigorous definitions of the granularity of procedures, hence also of structured propositions, and comes out in favour of one of them. As for the first point, structured propositions are explicated as algorithmically structured procedures. I show that these procedures are structured wholes that are assigned to expressions as their meanings, and their constituents are sub-procedures occurring in executed mode. Moreover, procedures are not (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  12. (1 other version)Cognitive propositions.Scott Soames - 2013 - Philosophical Perspectives 27 (1):479-501.
  13. (1 other version)Facts, propositions, exemplification and truth.C. A. Baylis - 1948 - Mind 57 (228):459-479.
  14. Propositions and the objects of thought.Michael Jubien - 2001 - Philosophical Studies 104 (1):47 - 62.
  15.  89
    Empirical propositions and hypothetical statements.I. Berlin - 1950 - Mind 59 (235):289-312.
  16. Understanding beyond grasping propositions: A discussion of chess and fish.Daniel A. Wilkenfeld & Jennifer K. Hellmann - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 48 (C):46-51.
    In this paper, we argue that, contra Strevens (2013), understanding in the sciences is sometimes partially constituted by the possession of abilities; hence, it is not (in such cases) exhausted by the understander’s bearing a particular psychological or epistemic relationship to some set of structured propositions. Specifically, the case will be made that one does not really understand why a modeled phenomenon occurred unless one has the ability to actually work through (meaning run and grasp at each step) a model (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  17.  76
    Can Propositions Be Naturalistically Acceptable?Jeffrey C. King - 1994 - Midwest Studies in Philosophy 19 (1):53-75.
  18. Dicisigns and Habits: Implicit Propositions and Habit-Taking in Peirce’s Pragmatism.Frederik Stjernfelt - 2016 - In Myrdene Anderson & Donna West (eds.), Consensus on Peirce’s Concept of Habit: Before and Beyond Consciousness. Springer Verlag.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  19.  6
    The Role of Subsistent Propositions and Logical Forms in Russell's 1913 Philosophical Logic and in the Russell-Wittgenstein Dispute.Herbert Hochberg - 1996 - In Ignacio Angelelli & María Cerezo (eds.), Studies on the History of Logic: Proceedings of the III. Symposium on the History of Logic. Berlin, Germany: Walter de Gruyter. pp. 317-342.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  31
    On constructive functions ranging over propositions.H. Luckhardt - 1980 - Studia Logica 39 (4):371 - 374.
    It is shown that there is no constructive extensional truth-value mapping from the speciesP of all propositions into known constructive structures P.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  21.  51
    The Place of Relations in Hieronymus Pardo's Semantics of Propositions.Paloma Pérez-Ilzarbe - 2016 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 24 (3):512-531.
    I examine a sixteenth-century development of the anti-realist propositional semantics which is based on the notion of ‘mode’. Pardo uses this notion to offer a personal interpretation of the Buridanian criticism of complexe significabilia. He develops a middle way between the reduction of the significate of propositions to particular things and the postulation of non-standard entities which are only complexly signifiable. The key to this middle way is Pardo's understanding of the notion of ‘mode’ as connoting a relation between individual (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Structures and circumstances: two ways to fine-grain propositions.David Ripley - 2012 - Synthese 189 (1):97 - 118.
    This paper discusses two distinct strategies that have been adopted to provide fine-grained propositions; that is, propositions individuated more finely than sets of possible worlds. One strategy takes propositions to have internal structure, while the other looks beyond possible worlds, and takes propositions to be sets of circumstances, where possible worlds do not exhaust the circumstances. The usual arguments for these positions turn on fineness-of-grain issues: just how finely should propositions be individuated? Here, I compare the two strategies with an (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   41 citations  
  23. Singular Propositions and Singular Thoughts.Arthur Sullivan - 1998 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 39 (1):114-127.
  24. Singular Thoughts and Singular Propositions.Joshua Armstrong & Jason Stanley - 2011 - Philosophical Studies 154 (2):205 - 222.
    A singular thought about an object o is one that is directly about o in a characteristic way—grasp of that thought requires having some special epistemic relation to the object o, and the thought is ontologically dependent on o. One account of the nature of singular thought exploits a Russellian Structured Account of Propositions, according to which contents are represented by means of structured n-tuples of objects, properties, and functions. A proposition is singular, according to this framework, if and only (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  25. Indexical Propositions and De Re Belief Ascriptions.Mark Balaguer - 2005 - Synthese 146 (3):325-355.
    I develop here a novel version of the Fregean view of belief ascriptions (i.e., sentences of the form ‘S believes that p’) and I explain how my view accounts for various problem cases that many philosophers have supposed are incompatible with Fregeanism. The so-called problem cases involve (a) what Perry calls essential indexicals and (b) de re ascriptions in which it is acceptable to substitute coreferential but non-synonymous terms in belief contexts. I also respond to two traditional worries about what (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  26.  90
    Propositions and Sentences.Alonzo Church & Nelson Goodman - 1957 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 22 (2):205-208.
  27. On propositions and fineness of grain (again!).Jeffrey C. King - 2019 - Synthese 196 (4).
  28. Arbitrary reference, numbers, and propositions.Michele Palmira - 2018 - European Journal of Philosophy 26 (3):1069-1085.
    Reductionist realist accounts of certain entities, such as the natural numbers and propositions, have been taken to be fatally undermined by what we may call the problem of arbitrary identification. The problem is that there are multiple and equally adequate reductions of the natural numbers to sets (see Benacerraf, 1965), as well as of propositions to unstructured or structured entities (see, e.g., Bealer, 1998; King, Soames, & Speaks, 2014; Melia, 1992). This paper sets out to solve the problem by canvassing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Worlds and Propositions Set Free.Otávio Bueno, Christopher Menzel & Edward N. Zalta - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (4):797–820.
    The authors provide an object-theoretic analysis of two paradoxes in the theory of possible worlds and propositions stemming from Russell and Kaplan. After laying out the paradoxes, the authors provide a brief overview of object theory and point out how syntactic restrictions that prevent object-theoretic versions of the classical paradoxes are justified philosophically. The authors then trace the origins of the Russell paradox to a problematic application of set theory in the definition of worlds. Next the authors show that an (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  30.  93
    Indefinite Propositions and Anaphora in Stoic Logic.Paolo Crivelli - 1994 - Phronesis 39 (2):187 - 206.
  31. Judgements, facts and propositions: theories of truth in Russell, Wittgenstein and Ramsey.Colin Johnston & Peter Sullivan - 2018 - In Michael Glanzberg (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Truth. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. pp. 150-192.
    In 'On the nature of truth and falsehood' Russell offers both a multiple relation theory of judgment and a correspondence theory of truth. It has been a prevailing understanding of the Tractatus that Wittgenstein rejects Russell’s multiple relation idea but endorses the correspondence theory. Ramsey took the opposite view. In his 'Facts and Propositions', Ramsey endorses Russell’s multiple relation idea, rejects the correspondence theory, and then asserts that these moves are both due to Wittgenstein. This chapter will argue that Ramsey’s (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  32.  14
    Cicero On Propositions: Academica Ii.95.Carmen Johanson & David Londey - 1988 - Mnemosyne 41 (3-4):325-332.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33. Why propositions have no structure.M. J. Cresswell - 2002 - Noûs 36 (4):643–662.
  34.  62
    Propositions and reasoning in Russell and Frege.Gary Kemp - 1998 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 79 (3):218–235.
    Both Russell and Frege were inclined to think that there is nothing essentially linguistic about thought: any actual reliance of ours upon language is a mere psychological contingency. If so then it should be possible to formulate logic in such a way that logical relationships are not represented or expressed as principles pertaining to linguistic forms. Russell and Frege take pains to achieve this, but fail. I explain this by looking at some features of Grundgesetz and Principia . Their failure, (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  35. What are Propositions?Mark Richard - 2013 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 43 (5):702-719.
    (2013). What are Propositions? Canadian Journal of Philosophy: Vol. 43, Essays on the Nature of Propositions, pp. 702-719.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  36. On Undecidable Propositions of Formal Mathematical Systems .PostscriptumIntroductory Note to 1934.Martin Davis, Kurt Godel & Stephen C. Kleene - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (1):347.
  37. A Perspective on Propositions.L. E. Johnson - 1975 - International Logic Review 12:242.
  38. Analysis of General Propositions.P. Sen - 1978 - Indian Philosophical Quarterly 5 (2):146-160.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39. Statements and Propositions: The Detachment Argument.A. Stroll - 1970 - International Logic Review 95:89.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40. Objectives of propositions.Boguslaw Wolniewicz - 1978 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 7 (3):143-146.
  41. Métaphysique et propositions mathématiques chez Kant.Yirmiahu Yovel - 1973 - Archives de Philosophie 36 (2):239.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. The role of propositions in natural language semantics.Peter Bosch - 1982 - In Werner Leinfellner (ed.), Language and Ontology. Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky / Reidel.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  43.  98
    Quantifying over propositions in relevance logic: nonaxiomatisability of primary interpretations of ∀ p and ∃ p.Philip Kremer - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (1):334-349.
    A typical approach to semantics for relevance (and other) logics: specify a class of algebraic structures and take amodelto be one of these structures, α, together with some function or relation which associates with every formulaAa subset ofα. (This is the approach of, among others, Urquhart, Routley and Meyer and Fine.) In some cases there are restrictions on the class of subsets of α with which a formula can be associated: for example, in the semantics of Routley and Meyer [1973], (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  44. Properties, propositions and sets.Kit Fine - 1977 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 6 (1):135 - 191.
  45. Act‐type theories of propositions.Thomas Hodgson - 2021 - Philosophy Compass 16 (11).
    Many philosophers believe in things, propositions, which are the things that we believe, assert etc., and which are the contents of sentences. The act-type theory of propositions is an attempt to say what propositions are, to explain how we stand in relations to them, and to explain why they are true or false. The core idea of the act-type theory is that propositions are types of acts of predication. The theory is developed in various ways to offer explanations of the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  46.  72
    Theory of rejected propositions. I.Jerzy Słupecki, Grzegorz Bryll & Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska - 1971 - Studia Logica 29 (1):75 - 123.
    The idea of rejection of some sentences on the basis of others comes from Aristotle, as Jan Łukasiewicz states in his studies on Aristotle's syllogistic [1939, 1951], concerning rejection of the false syllogistic form and those on certain calculus of propositions. Short historical remarks on the origin and development of the notion of a rejected sentence, introduced into logic by Jan Łukasiewicz, are contained in the Introduction of this paper. This paper is to a considerable extent a summary of papers (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  47.  29
    Consistent, independent, and distinct propositions.Anjan Shukla - 1972 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 13 (3):399-406.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  52
    Are some analytic propositions contingent?S. F. Barker - 1966 - Journal of Philosophy 63 (20):637-639.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  23
    Why elementary propositions cannot be negative.Robert W. Burch - 1975 - Philosophical Studies 27 (6):433 - 435.
  50.  31
    States of Affairs, Events, and Propositions.Jaegwon Kim - 1979 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 7:147-162.
    States of affairs constitute a basic ontological category in Chisholm's metaphysical system, and yield events and propositions as subclasses. Qua events, they enter into causal relations, and qua propositions, they are objects of our intentional attitudes. This paper expounds and critically examines Chisholm's conception of a state of affairs and his constructions of events and propositions. Various difficulties with some of Chisholm's definitions and procedures are pointed out and discussed. The last section contains a set of suggested modifications to the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 949