Results for 'simple ideas'

962 found
Order:
  1. Simple Ideas and Hume’s Missing Shade of Blue.Emily Kelahan - 2016 - Philosophia 44 (3):809-825.
    This paper provides support for the unorthodox view that Hume’s simple ideas are most fruitfully understood as theoretical posits by showing that adopting this interpretation solves a lingering interpretive difficulty, the missing shade of blue. The missing shade of blue is thought to pose a serious challenge to the legitimacy of Hume’s copy principle. Thinking of Humean simple ideas as theoretical posits reveals a dialectical mismatch between Hume and his envisioned reader that, once understood, makes it (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  2. Anarchism: A Simple Idea.Glenn Wallis - 2020 - Anarchist Library.
    At the very root of anarchy is a simple idea: social organization without (an) a dominating figure or controller (archos). Though simple, realizing such a form in our daily lives is virtually impossible. Though virtually impossible, this idea, when pursued, is profoundly constructive.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3.  10
    Simple Ideas.Kenneth P. Winkler - 1989 - In Berkeley: An Interpretation. Oxford, GB: Oxford University Press UK.
    Many empiricists, among them Locke and Hume, make a distinction between simple and complex ideas. Berkeley refuses to do so, because he finds connections—objective connections incompatible with simplicity—even among the ‘simplest’ of ideas. Simple ideas, in his view, are illegitimately abstract.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  4. The Adequacy of Simple Ideas in Locke--A Rehabilitation of Berkeley's Criticisms.J. Bermudez - 1992 - Locke Studies 23:25.
  5.  63
    Simple ideas and resemblance.Lilly-Marlene Russow - 1980 - Philosophical Quarterly 30 (121):342-350.
  6.  63
    Qualities and Simple Ideas: Hume and his Debt to Berkeley.Alan Nelson & David Landy - 2011 - In Lawrence Nolan (ed.), Primary and secondary qualities: the historical and ongoing debate. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. pp. 216-238.
  7. Are Locke¿s simple ideas abstract?Kathy Squadrito - 1996 - Diálogos. Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad de Puerto Rico 31 (68):155-164.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8.  38
    Simple ideas.David L. Perry - 1966 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 27 (2):278-280.
  9.  3
    Qualities and simple ideas : Hume and his debt to Berkeley.Alan Nelson & David Landy - 2011 - In Lawrence Nolan (ed.), Primary and secondary qualities: the historical and ongoing debate. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. pp. 216-238.
  10. What makes Locke's simple ideas adequate?Sally Ferguson - manuscript
    In a recent paper, José Luis Bermúdez argues that Locke's claim that all simple ideas are adequate is inconsistent with other claims he makes in the Essay concerning the nature of such ideas. In particular, Bermúdez argues that Locke is unjustified in claiming that all simple ideas are adequate, because simple ideas of secondary qualities are in fact not. In this paper I argue that Bermúdez has missed an essential aspect of Locke's distinction (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  11. Locke's Simple Ideas, The Blooming, Buzzing Confusion, and Quasi-Photographic Perception.T. Heyd - 1994 - Locke Studies 25.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  12.  26
    A Functionalist Interpretation of Locke's Theory of Simple Ideas.Thomas Vinci - 1985 - History of Philosophy Quarterly 2 (2):179 - 194.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Locke and Sensory Experience--Another Look at Simple Ideas of Sensation.R. Hall - 1994 - Locke Studies 25:11.
  14. Locke on the semantic and epistemic role of simple ideas of sensation.Martha Brandt Bolton - 2004 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85 (3):301–321.
    This paper argues that Locke has a representative theory of sensitive knowledge. Perceivers are immediately aware of nothing but sensory ideas in the mind; yet perceivers think of real external substances that correspond to and cause those ideas, and they are warranted in believing that those substances exist (at that time). The theory poses two questions: what warrants the truth of such beliefs? What is it in virtue of which sensory ideas represent external objects and how do (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  15.  13
    Context and Connection in Metaphor: How Simple Ideas Shape Human Experienceby David Ritchie.Kathleen Ahrens - 2011 - Metaphor and Symbol 26 (3):240-242.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. A simple but powerful idea : actual sequences and free will.Carolina Sartorio - 2023 - In Taylor W. Cyr, Andrew Law & Neal A. Tognazzini (eds.), Freedom, Responsibility, and Value: Essays in Honor of John Martin Fischer. New York: Routledge.
  17. Simples and the idea of analysis in the tractatus.Marie McGinn - 2007 - In Guy Kahane, Edward Kanterian & Oskari Kuusela (eds.), Wittgenstein and His Interpreters: Essays in Memory of Gordon Baker. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18.  15
    Berkeley: Crítica de las ideas abstractas. La abstracción como simple semántica.Lorenzo Vicente Burgoa - 1996 - Daimon: Revista Internacional de Filosofía 12:49-60.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19.  46
    How to Distinguish Simple Objectless Ideas.Jan Claas - 2022 - History and Philosophy of Logic 44 (4):422-441.
    Bernard Bolzano offers a criterion of individuation for ideas, according to which ideas are distinct if and only if they represent different objects or are composed differently. It fails to individuate ideas that are both simple and fail to represent, in particular syncategorematic ideas and logical constants. However, Bolzano also provides the means to close this gap. He suggests that we can distinguish ideas if they are not substitutable for each other in propositions, which (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20.  12
    Simples and the Idea of Analysis in the Tractatus.Marie McGinn - 2007 - In Guy Kahane, Edward Kanterian & Oskari Kuusela (eds.), Wittgenstein and His Interpreters: Essays in Memory of Gordon Baker. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 200–220.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. Basic Income: A Simple and Powerful Idea for the Twenty-First Century.Philippe Van Parijs - 2004 - Politics and Society 32 (1):7-39.
    A basic income is an income paid by a political community to all its members on an individual basis, without means test or work requirement. This article surveys the various forms the basic income proposal has taken and how they relate to kin ideas; synthesizes the central case for basic income, as a strategy against both poverty and unemployment; examines the question of whether and in what sense a universal basic income is affordable; and discusses the most promising next (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  22.  82
    Rational constraints and the Simple View.E. di Nucci - 2010 - Analysis 70 (3):481-486.
    According to the Simple View of intentional action, I have intentionally switched on the light only if I intended to switch on the light. The idea that intending to is necessary for intentionally -ing has been challenged by Bratman (1984, 1987) with a counter-example in which a videogame player is trying to hit either of two targets while knowing that she cannot hit both targets. When a target is hit, the game finishes. And if both targets are about to (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  23. The physics of extended simples.D. Braddon-Mitchell & K. Miller - 2006 - Analysis 66 (3):222-226.
    The idea that there could be spatially extended mereological simples has recently been defended by a number of metaphysicians (Markosian 1998, 2004; Simons 2004; Parsons (2000) also takes the idea seriously). Peter Simons (2004) goes further, arguing not only that spatially extended mereological simples (henceforth just extended simples) are possible, but that it is more plausible that our world is composed of such simples, than that it is composed of either point-sized simples, or of atomless gunk. The difficulty for these (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  24.  63
    A simple Henkin-style completeness proof for Gödel 3-valued logic G3.Gemma Robles - 2014 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 23 (4):371-390.
    A simple Henkin-style completeness proof for Gödel 3-valued propositional logic G3 is provided. The idea is to endow G3 with an under-determined semantics of the type defined by Dunn. The key concept in u-semantics is that of “under-determined interpretation”. It is shown that consistent prime theories built upon G3 can be understood as u-interpretations. In order to prove this fact we follow Brady by defining G3 as an extension of Anderson and Belnap’s positive fragment of First Degree Entailment Logic.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  25.  47
    Hutcheson's idea of beauty: Simple or complex?Peter Kivy - 1992 - Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 50 (3):243-245.
  26.  77
    Exploring Alternatives to the Simple Model: Is There an Atomistic Option?Luke Robinson - 2011 - In Mark Timmons (ed.), Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.
    The simple model maintains that morally relevant factors combine in a simple, additive way, like weights on a scale. Although intuitive and familiar, this model entails that certain plausible views about particular cases and how morally relevant factors combine and interact therein are false. Shelly Kagan suggests that we could accommodate the relevant views and interactions by rejecting either of two assumptions the simple model makes: that the moral status of an act is determined by the sum (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  27. What is an Extended Simple Region?Zachary Goodsell, Michael Duncan & Kristie Miller - 2019 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 101 (3):649-659.
    The notion of an extended simple region (henceforth ESR) has recently been marshalled in the service of arguments for a variety of conclusions. Exactly how to understand the idea of extendedness as it applies to simple regions, however, has been largely ignored, or, perhaps better, assumed. In this paper we first (§1) outline what we take to be the standard way that philosophers are thinking about extendedness, namely as an intrinsic property of regions. We then introduce an alternative (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  28.  64
    Some Simple Facts Apropos Theocritus I. 51.A. Y. Campbell - 1932 - Classical Quarterly 26 (01):55-.
    In the last number of C.Q. Mr. A. D. Knox has drawn up a list of Theocriteans who, he suggests, ‘have all of them made the most elementary mistake’ of failing to consider the possibility at least that it is the Boy, and not the Fox, who is the subject of καθξ in Id. I. 51. From that list he will have to with-draw two names, Gow and Campbell. This construction, which Mr. Knox propounds as a novelty, had been suggested (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Locke's Simple Account of Sensitive Knowledge.Jennifer Smalligan Marušić - 2016 - Philosophical Review 125 (2):205-239.
    Locke seems to hold that we have knowledge of the existence of external objects through sensation. Two problems face Locke's account. The first problem concerns the logical form of knowledge of real existence. Locke defines knowledge as the perception of the agreement or disagreement between ideas. However, perceiving agreements between ideas seems to yield knowledge only of analytic truths, not propositions about existence. The second problem concerns the epistemic status of sensitive knowledge: How could the senses yield certain (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  30.  45
    A Simple Solution to the Problem of De Se Belief Ascriptions.Ari Maunu - 2000 - Communication and Cognition: An Interdisciplinary Quarterly Journal 33 (3-4):199-226.
    I show how a de se belief ascription such as "Privatus believes that he himself is rich" may be dealt with by means of a scope distinction over and above that one separating de dicto and de re ascriptions. The idea is, roughly, that 'Privatus...himself' forms in this statement a unity, a single "spread" sign that is at the same time in a de re and de dicto position. If so, H-N. Castañeda's contention that the "quasi-indicator" 'he himself' ('she herself', (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31. Naturaleza de las ideas innatas cartesianas.Rafael Corazón González - 1993 - Anuario Filosófico 26 (1):47-78.
    Innate ideas are not objective ideas which have ceased to be doubtful. They are not ideas of attributes or modes but rather true realities. Therefore, they are simple, clear, and distinct. These ideas are not possible to analyze. Innate ideas are not conceived when thinking of "something" but when the real world is felt. Therefore, they correspond with objective ideas.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32.  60
    A Simple Proof that Super-Consistency Implies Cut Elimination.Gilles Dowek & Olivier Hermant - 2012 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 53 (4):439-456.
    We give a simple and direct proof that super-consistency implies the cut-elimination property in deduction modulo. This proof can be seen as a simplification of the proof that super-consistency implies proof normalization. It also takes ideas from the semantic proofs of cut elimination that proceed by proving the completeness of the cut-free calculus. As an application, we compare our work with the cut-elimination theorems in higher-order logic that involve V-complexes.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  37
    Simple generic structures.Massoud Pourmahdian - 2003 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 121 (2-3):227-260.
    A study of smooth classes whose generic structures have simple theory is carried out in a spirit similar to Hrushovski 147; Simplicity and the Lascar group, preprint, 1997) and Baldwin–Shi 1). We attach to a smooth class K0, of finite -structures a canonical inductive theory TNat, in an extension-by-definition of the language . Here TNat and the class of existentially closed models of =T+,EX, play an important role in description of the theory of the K0,-generic. We show that if (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  34.  12
    L’incarnazione dell’idea nello spazio della scrittura.Renato Boccali - 2019 - Rivista di Estetica 71:241-256.
    Philosophy has often appropriated the reflexive element of literature disembodying the sensible idea from the text, thus exercising a coercive violence against literature, reduced to a simple epiphenomenon of a meta-literary discourse. Philosophy tends to appropriate the sensitive content of literature as a raw material to be integrated into a broader conceptual framework dissolving, in fact, the tensional truth implicit in the novelistic structure as Lukács put it. Literary experience cannot be reduced to a mere conceptual structure, to a (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  24
    The Idea of Communism.Tariq Ali - 2009 - Seagull Books.
    November 9, 2009 will mark 20 years since the fall of the Berlin Wall, the monumental event that signaled the beginning of the end of Communism in the former Soviet Union. Yet, why was this collapse of Communism considered final, but the many failures of capitalism are considered temporary and episodic? In _The Idea of Communism_, Tariq Ali addresses this very question. The idea of Communism, argues Ali, was simple and noble. _The Communist Manifesto_, which advocated the creation of (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  52
    The Ideas of the Enlightenment and Their Legacy.Morton White - 2000 - The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 7:151-159.
    Concentrating on the legacy of David Hume, I discuss the impact of his psychologism on his two most important sharp distinctions: (1) between statements about the relations of ideas and those about matters of fact; and (2) between what is and what ought to be. I argue that his concept of relations of ideas is subject to difficulties like those attending the concept of synonymy in twentieth-century discussions, and also that his psychologism should lead him to say that (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  37.  11
    Simple Fundamentals of Logic.Zekai Şen - 2019 - Felsefe Arkivi 51:331-334.
    For the most part, contemporary logicians discuss previous logicians’ ideas from different civilizations and make comments thereon, thus addressing specialists in logic studies. In many education systems, the science philosophy and logic principles do not play a preliminary role. Today, in many education systems the science of philosophical thinking and logic principles should play a preliminary role for rational inferences. Unfortunately, in education systems there is little formal training about the principles of logic and their extraordinary capacity to sharpen (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38.  92
    Explaining General Ideas.Janet Broughton - 2000 - Hume Studies 26 (2):279-289.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume Studies Volume XXVI, Number 2, November 2000, pp. 279-289 Explaining General Ideas JANET BROUGHTON Hume declared himself a scientist of man; his aim was to identify the principles according to which our impressions give rise to our thoughts, beliefs, passions and actions. He took it that there are things about these products of experience that need to be explained, and as a scientist of man he aimed (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  39.  20
    The idea of quantity at the origin of the legitimacy of mathematization in physics.Michel Paty - 2003 - In C. Gould (ed.), Constructivism and Practice: Towards a Social and Historical Epistemology. Rowman& Littlefield. pp. 109-135.
    Newton's use of mathematics in mechanics was justified by him from his neo-platonician conception of the physical world that was going along with his «absolute, true and mathematical concepts» such as space, time, motion, force, etc. But physics, afterwards, although it was based on newtonian dynamics, meant differently the legitimacy of being mathematized, and this difference can be seen already in the works of eighteenth century «Geometers» such as Euler, Clairaut and d'Alembert (and later on Lagrange, Laplace and others). Despite (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40. Conceiving simple experiences.Michael V. Antony - 2001 - Journal of Mind and Behavior 22 (3):263-86.
    That consciousness is composed of simple or basic elements that combine to form complex experiences is an idea with a long history. This idea is approached through an examination of our “picture” or conception of consciousness . It is argued that CC commits us to a certain abstract notion of simple experiential events, or simples, and that traditional critiques of simple elements of experience do not threaten simples. To the extent that CC is taken to conform to (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  41.  38
    Ideas and Images.Clive Ingram Pearson - 1961 - Review of Metaphysics 14 (3):452 - 462.
    The defining of 'image' as essentially that class of idea to which there is no object corresponding, springs from a commend able desire not to allow analysis to result in an incorrect conceptual multiplication of physical objects or situations. This result would be likely if the thinker succumbed to the temptation to consider that for every idea entertained there is somehow an objective physical situation corresponding. The simple calling of attention to the type of mental state signified by the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. The Idea of Mismatch in Evolutionary Medicine.Pierrick Bourrat & Paul Griffiths - 2024 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 75 (4):921-946.
    Mismatch is a prominent concept in evolutionary medicine, and a number of philosophers have published analyses of this concept. The word ‘mismatch’ has been used in a diversity of ways across a range of sciences, leading these authors to regard it as a vague concept in need of philosophical clarification. Here, in contrast, we concentrate on the use of mismatch in modelling and experimentation in evolutionary medicine. This reveals a rigorous theory of mismatch within which the term ‘mismatch’ is indeed (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  43.  21
    Not so simple powers.Jesse M. Mulder - 2024 - In James Conant & Jesse M. Mulder (eds.), Reading Rödl: on Self-consciousness and objectivity. New York, NY: Routledge.
    This chapter inquires into an initially rather startling claim Sebastian Rödl makes in his Self-Consciousness and Objectivity (SC&O): that the power of judgment is not a power among other powers, but rather “the power” (p. 60). It traces Rödl’s sophisticated understanding of powers, as presented in SC&O, in terms of a distinction between “simple powers”, such as a pear tree’s power to blossom, on the one hand, and “self-conscious powers”, such as the power of judgment, on the other. Reflection (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  97
    Simple Models in Complex Worlds: Occam’s Razor and Statistical Learning Theory.Falco J. Bargagli Stoffi, Gustavo Cevolani & Giorgio Gnecco - 2022 - Minds and Machines 32 (1):13-42.
    The idea that “simplicity is a sign of truth”, and the related “Occam’s razor” principle, stating that, all other things being equal, simpler models should be preferred to more complex ones, have been long discussed in philosophy and science. We explore these ideas in the context of supervised machine learning, namely the branch of artificial intelligence that studies algorithms which balance simplicity and accuracy in order to effectively learn about the features of the underlying domain. Focusing on statistical learning (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  45.  96
    Hume on the Idea of Existence.Phillip D. Cummins - 1991 - Hume Studies 17 (1):61-82.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Hume on the Idea of Existence1 Phillip D. Cummins One, the primary, aim of this paper is to understand an argument Hume employed to defend his contention that there is no special or distinctidea ofexistence. This contention he expressedvariouslyin the following passage: The idea ofexistence, then, is the very same with the idea of what we conceive tobe existent. To reflect on any thing simply, and to reflect on (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  46.  7
    Number ideas through pictures.Mannis Charosh - 1974 - New York,: T. Y. Crowell. Edited by Giulio Maestro.
  47. Innate ideas as a naturalistic source of metaphysical knowledge.Steve Stewart-Williams - 2005 - Biology and Philosophy 20 (4):791-814.
    This article starts from the assumption that there are various innate contributions to our view of the world and explores the epistemological implications that follow from this. Specifically, it explores the idea that if certain components of our worldview have an evolutionary origin, this implies that these aspects accurately depict the world. The simple version of the argument for this conclusion is that if an aspect of mind is innate, it must be useful, and the most parsimonious explanation for (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  48.  22
    The predicament of ideas in culture: Translation and historiography.Douglas Howland - 2003 - History and Theory 42 (1):45–60.
    Rather than a simple transfer of words or texts from one language to another, on the model of the bilingual dictionary, translation has become understood as a translingual act of transcoding cultural material--a complex act of communication. Much recent work on translation in history grows out of interest in the effects of European colonialism, especially within Asian studies, where interest has been driven by the contrast between the experiences of China and Japan, which were never formally colonized, and the (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. A simple maximality principle.Joel Hamkins - 2003 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 68 (2):527-550.
    In this paper, following an idea of Christophe Chalons. I propose a new kind of forcing axiom, the Maximality Principle, which asserts that any sentence varphi holding in some forcing extension $V^P$ and all subsequent extensions $V^{P\ast Q}$ holds already in V. It follows, in fact, that such sentences must also hold in all forcing extensions of V. In modal terms, therefore, the Maximality Principle is expressed by the scheme $(\lozenge \square \varphi) \Rightarrow \square \varphi$ , and is equivalent to (...)
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  50.  55
    The myth and fallacy of simple extrapolation in medicine.Jonathan Fuller - 2019 - Synthese 198 (4):2919-2939.
    Simple extrapolation is the orthodox approach to extrapolating from clinical trials in evidence-based medicine: extrapolate the relative effect size from the trial unless there is a compelling reason not to do so. I argue that this method relies on a myth and a fallacy. The myth of simple extrapolation is the idea that the relative risk is a ‘golden ratio’ that is usually transportable due to some special mathematical or theoretical property. The fallacy of simple extrapolation is (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
1 — 50 / 962